Like a Swiss Clockwork in the Desert: A Review of Moshe M. Pavlov s Books on Abu al-barakat al-baghdadı

Similar documents
PHILOSOPHY AND THEOLOGY

The Paradox of the stone and two concepts of omnipotence

REVIEW THE DOOR TO SELLARS

THE RELATIONSHIP BETWEEN SCIENCE, RELIGION AND ARISTOTELIAN THEOLOGY TODAY

PHILOSOPHICAL RAMIFICATIONS: THEORY, EXPERIMENT, & EMPIRICAL TRUTH

FIRST STUDY. The Existential Dialectical Basic Assumption of Kierkegaard s Analysis of Despair

Epistemology: A Contemporary Introduction to The Theory of Knowledge, by Robert Audi. New York: Routledge, 2011.

Development of Thought. The word "philosophy" comes from the Ancient Greek philosophia, which

The SAT Essay: An Argument-Centered Strategy

The Human Science Debate: Positivist, Anti-Positivist, and Postpositivist Inquiry. By Rebecca Joy Norlander. November 20, 2007

Each copy of any part of a JSTOR transmission must contain the same copyright notice that appears on the screen or printed page of such transmission.

Unit VI: Davidson and the interpretational approach to thought and language

Gale on a Pragmatic Argument for Religious Belief

SYSTEMATIC RESEARCH IN PHILOSOPHY. Contents

Environmental Ethics in Buddhism: A Virtues Approach

Philosophy 125 Day 1: Overview

Self-Awareness in Islamic Philosophy: Avicenna and Beyond. By JARI KAUKUA. Cambridge:

CRUCIAL TOPICS IN THE DEBATE ABOUT THE EXISTENCE OF EXTERNAL REASONS

Teachur Philosophy Degree 2018

Hoong Juan Ru. St Joseph s Institution International. Candidate Number Date: April 25, Theory of Knowledge Essay

Response to The Problem of the Question About Animal Ethics by Michal Piekarski

Scientific Progress, Verisimilitude, and Evidence

Difference between Science and Religion? - A Superficial, yet Tragi-Comic Misunderstanding

Philosophy of Mathematics Nominalism

1. Why were you initially drawn to epistemology (and what keeps you interested)?


Wright on response-dependence and self-knowledge

book-length treatments of the subject have been scarce. 1 of Zimmerman s book quite welcome. Zimmerman takes up several of the themes Moore

ON QUINE, ANALYTICITY, AND MEANING Wylie Breckenridge

In Defense of Pure Reason: A Rationalist Account of A Priori Justification, by Laurence BonJour. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press,

SELF-AWARENESS IN ISLAMIC PHILOSOPHY

Pihlström, Sami Johannes.

A-LEVEL Religious Studies

Has Nagel uncovered a form of idealism?

How Do We Know Anything about Mathematics? - A Defence of Platonism

Aquinas on the Beginning and End of Human Life

Proof of the Necessary of Existence

Denis Seron. Review of: K. Mulligan, Wittgenstein et la philosophie austro-allemande (Paris: Vrin, 2012). Dialectica

Reply to Kit Fine. Theodore Sider July 19, 2013

Contemporary Theology I: Hegel to Death of God Theologies

Robert Kiely Office Hours: Tuesday 1-3, Wednesday 1-3, and by appointment

R. Keith Sawyer: Social Emergence. Societies as Complex Systems. Cambridge University Press

What conditions does Plato expect a good definition to meet? Is he right to impose them?

Subjective Logic: Logic as Rational Belief Dynamics. Richard Johns Department of Philosophy, UBC

1 Why should you care about metametaphysics?

Roman Madzia. Education and Culture 30 (2) (2014):

Book Review: From Plato to Jesus By C. Marvin Pate. Submitted by: Brian A. Schulz. A paper. submitted in partial fulfillment

Religious Instruction, Religious Studies and Religious Education

Spring CAS Department of Philosophy Graduate Courses

LOCKE STUDIES Vol ISSN: X

the aim is to specify the structure of the world in the form of certain basic truths from which all truths can be derived. (xviii)

Introduction to Technical Communications 21W.732 Section 2 Ethics in Science and Technology Formal Paper #2

Faults and Mathematical Disagreement

Testimony and Moral Understanding Anthony T. Flood, Ph.D. Introduction

Koninklijke Brill NV, Leiden, 2010 DOI: / X542671

Tuukka Kaidesoja Précis of Naturalizing Critical Realist Social Ontology

Charles Hartshorne argues that Kant s criticisms of Anselm s ontological

INVESTIGATING THE PRESUPPOSITIONAL REALM OF BIBLICAL-THEOLOGICAL METHODOLOGY, PART II: CANALE ON REASON

CD 610 Moral Development

Russell on Descriptions

PL 407 HISTORY OF MEDIEVAL PHILOSOPHY Spring 2012

TO D D C. REAM. VER THE COURSE OF THE PAST FIFTEEN YEARS, intellectual historians have

Varieties of Apriority

Briggle, Adam; and Robert Frodeman. Thinking À La Carte. Social Epistemology Review and Reply Collective 7, no. 6 (2018): 8-11.

BOOK REVIEWS. The arguments of the Parmenides, though they do not refute the Theory of Forms, do expose certain problems, ambiguities and

Lahore University of Management Sciences. REL 313 Rationality and Tradition

Self-Evidence and A Priori Moral Knowledge

A Review of Norm Geisler's Prolegomena

World Religions. These subject guidelines should be read in conjunction with the Introduction, Outline and Details all essays sections of this guide.

Philoponus s Traversal Argument and the Beginning of Time

Buddhist Psychology: The Mind That Mindfulness Discloses

From Being to Energy-Being: An Emerging Metaphysical Macroparadigm Shift in Western Philosophy. Preface

In Defense of Radical Empiricism. Joseph Benjamin Riegel. Chapel Hill 2006

Spinoza and the Axiomatic Method. Ever since Euclid first laid out his geometry in the Elements, his axiomatic approach to

Haberdashers Aske s Boys School

Philosophy in Review XXXIII (2013), no. 1

UNIVERSITY OF MALTA THE MATRICULATION EXAMINATION ADVANCED LEVEL

RBL 01/2006 Kirk, Alan, and Tom Thatcher, eds. Semeia Studies 52. Thomas J. Kraus Hilpoltstein, Federal Republic of Germany D-91161

Habermas and Critical Thinking

WHAT IS ETHICS? KEY DISTINCTIONS:

Understanding Truth Scott Soames Précis Philosophy and Phenomenological Research Volume LXV, No. 2, 2002

Comments on Scott Soames, Philosophical Analysis in the Twentieth Century, volume I

Philosophical Review.

INTUITION AND CONSCIOUS REASONING

UNITY OF KNOWLEDGE (IN TRANSDISCIPLINARY RESEARCH FOR SUSTAINABILITY) Vol. I - Philosophical Holism M.Esfeld

Etchemendy, Tarski, and Logical Consequence 1 Jared Bates, University of Missouri Southwest Philosophy Review 15 (1999):

[MJTM 16 ( )] BOOK REVIEW

Bart Streumer, Unbelievable Errors, Oxford: Oxford University Press, ISBN

A conversation about balance: key principles

Holtzman Spring Philosophy and the Integration of Knowledge

Life has become a problem.

Explanatory Indispensability and Deliberative Indispensability: Against Enoch s Analogy Alex Worsnip University of North Carolina at Chapel Hill

STEWART COHEN AND THE CONTEXTUALIST THEORY OF JUSTIFICATION

HABERMAS ON COMPATIBILISM AND ONTOLOGICAL MONISM Some problems

Craig on the Experience of Tense

Book Reviews. Rahim Acar, Marmara University

Difference between Science and Religion? A Superficial, yet Tragi-Comic Misunderstanding...

Timothy Williamson: Modal Logic as Metaphysics Oxford University Press 2013, 464 pages

Online version of this review can be found at:


Transcription:

REVIEW ARTICLE Like a Swiss Clockwork in the Desert: A Review of Moshe M. Pavlov s Books on Abu al-barakat al-baghdadı Moshe M. Pavlov. Abū l-barakāt al-baghdādī s Scientific Philosophy: The Kitāb al-muʿtabar. Abingdon, UK and New York, NY: Routledge, 2016. 370 pages. ISBN: 9781138640450. Moshe M. Pavlov. Abū l-barakāt al-baghdādī s Metaphysical Philosophy: The Kitāb al-muʿtabar. Abingdon, UK and New York, NY: Routledge, 2017. 387 pages. ISBN: 9781138640498. Pauline Froissart * This review essay covers Moshe M. Pavlov s two-volume project on the twelfth-century Jewish philosopher Abū al-barakāt al-baghdādī s (d. ca. 547/1152) magnum opus, the Kitāb al-muʿtabar: Abū l-barakāt al-baghdādī s Scientific Philosophy (hereinafter ASP) and Abū l-barakāt al-baghdādī s Metaphysical Philosophy (hereinafter AMP). Although the structure of these two volumes allows an independent reading of only one of them and even of separate chapters from them I have privileged a common review of them in order to provide an evaluation of the project as a whole rather than one of its aspects. I will expand my evaluation after a brief summary of the two books content. The general project seeks to detail the systematic character of Abū al-barakāt s philosophical endeavor more particularly the high level of interconnection between his scientific and metaphysical positions as well as the distinctively Jewish nature of its purpose (at the exclusion of Islamic elements) (ASP, 7). By way of an introduction, the first volume includes a general presentation of the whole project, a biographical account of Abū al-barakāt al-baghdādī, and a broad overview of the * PhD Candidate in Islamic Philosophy, McGill University, Institute of Islamic Studies. Correspondence: pauline.froissart@mail.mcgill.ca. DOI dx.doi.org/10.12658/nazariyat.4.3.r0004en 169

NAZARİYAT history of philosophy from Plato and Aristotle to our twelfth-century thinker. In the biographical description, the author, based on Moshe Gil s work, 1 enjoins one to identify Abū al-barakāt with the Talmudist Rabbi Baruch ben Melekh and to adopt the hypothesis of the latter s coerced conversion to Islam. The main part of the first volume is divided between an exposition of the philosopher s ontological and epistemological critical stances against the Aristotelian tradition and a detailed presentation of his contributions with regard to the principles of sciences, understood as physics, psychology, and logic. The second volume is dedicated to the metaphysical accounts developed in the first book of the metaphysical part of the Kitāb al-muʿtabar. The presentation order of the philosophical topics in the two volumes closely follows the Kitāb al-muʿtabar s own content structure. The two volumes take part in the same general project of proving the work s systematic nature as the ontological and epistemological developments elaborated in the scientific part acquire their full meaning, once recaptured at the metaphysical level and, more specifically, once they reach the culminating cumulative conclusion of the whole system and its ontological and epistemological consequences are plainly grasped (ASP, xi). This culminating cumulative conclusion consists in the possibility for humanity to access a special kind of cognition of God s ipseity, a notion conceived of as the equivalent of the Jewish Shem ha-meforash, the Special Name of God. According to the author, Abū al- Barakāt s identification with the highly erudite Talmudist and strictly observant Jew Rabbi Baruch ben Melekh, as well as the culmination of his system in an authentically Jewish teaching, demonstrate the Kitāb al-muʿtabar s distinctively Jewish identity. The author s general approach consists primarily of an in-depth internal analysis of the Kitāb al-muʿtabar, which highlights its rigorously systematic nature and recapitulates the system s main contributions to the concepts and problematics specific to analytical philosophy. His close reading manifests many valuable insights on the minute structure of Abū al-barakāt s system, and his endeavor to actualize its main issues and conclusions in contemporary debates deserves praise with regard to the level of philosophical ingenuity such a task requires. Nevertheless, the entire project is, unfortunately, deeply undermined by an insufficient and inadequate historical contextualization. When the author feels the need to cover briefly potential sources that were influential on our twelfth-century thinker, most times he mobilizes references to Plato (d. 347 bce) and Aristotle (d. 322 bce) without further justification. The obviously massive contributions of Abū al-barakāt s Muslim predecessors and Late Antique Neoplatonists to the shaping of his thought are 1 Moshe Gil, Jews in Islamic Countries in the Middle Ages (Leiden: Brill, 2004), 470. 170

Review Article almost invariably passed over. I will develop two examples selected from each volume to illustrate this insufficient and inadequate historical contextualization by referring to two cases in which Avicenna s (d. 428/1037) obvious influence on the development and structuration of Abū al-barakāt s particular points of doctrine are completely set aside by the author, who provides no satisfactory justification for doing so. In ASP, in the first section of the chapter dealing with the psychological part of Abū al-barakāt s scientific project Epistemological ascertainment of psychology a section designed to provide a historical introduction to the chapter s content, the author dedicates one and a half pages out of a sixteen-page section to Avicenna s conception of the soul (ASP, 235-36) while Plato, Aristotle, and John Philoponus (d. ca. 570) enjoy a total of seven pages (ASP, 228-35). Avicenna s conception of the soul is presented as a mere combination of the Aristotelian hierarchical notion with the notion of the ego derived from Philoponus (ASP, 235). This subsection simply concludes on the difference between the two philosophers respective definition of the soul. The baffling character of this very limited treatment of Avicenna s influence on Abū al-barakāt s psychology, one that is completely disproportionate with regard to its importance, can be easily spelled out if we compare it with how the recent scholarship to which Pavlov should have access 2 as well as the less recent research of which he obviously made use 3 covered this specific topic. In the second chapter of AMP, dealing first with the question of time, the author highlights Abū al-barakāt s significant use of a thought experiment (AMP, 90-93) that he describes as an unusual attempt in medieval philosophy to explicate the nature of time by an operational method of a thought experiment (AMP, 90). In the corresponding note to the quoted sentence, he adds that thought experiments were not prominent before Ernst Mach [1838-1916] (AMP, 130, note 32), that it is to say, not before the end of the nineteenth century. I will not elaborate here upon the prominence of thought experiments or the lack thereof before Mach, 4 but 2 See, for example, Jari Kaukua s article and monograph on closely related topics that vetted the nature of Avicenna s influence on Abū al-barakāt s psychology: Jari Kaukua, Self-awareness in Islamic Philosophy: Avicenna and Beyond (New York: Cambridge University Press, 2015), 104-23; Jari Kaukua, Self, Agent, Soul: Abū al-barakāt al-baghdādī s Critical Reception of Avicennian Psychology, in Subjectivity and Selfhood in Medieval and Early Modern Philosophy, ed. Jari Kaujua and Tomas Ekenberg (Switzerland: Springer, 2016), 75-89. 3 An article by Shlomo Pines, with whom the author is frequently critically engaged throughout the two volumes, appears in his collected Studies in Abū l-barakāt al-baghdādī s Physics and Metaphysics. Entitled La conception de la conscience de soi chez Avicenne et chez Abū l-barakāt al-baghdādī, it deals explicitly with this influence. See Shlomo Pines, La conception de la conscience de soi chez Avicenne et chez Abū l-barakāt al-baghdādī, in Studies in Abū l-barakāt al-baghdādī s Physics and Metaphysics (Jerusalem: Magnes Press and Leiden: E. J. Brill, 1979), 181-258. 4 Even though the existence of collective works such as Ierodiakonou and Roux s Thought Experiments 171

NAZARİYAT rather will focus on the fact that the author bases his claims on Abū al-barakāt s originality throughout the two volumes on remarks of this kind. I have selected this last example, which could have been considered as simply anecdotal, because it eloquently illustrates how Pavlov s inadequate historical contextualization makes his statements about Abū al-barakāt s originality, which I still consider undeniable, dubious. Indeed, the only mention of the well-known Floating / Flying Man argument developed in different versions by Avicenna seems to me to be amply sufficient to question the author s statement about the absence of thought experiments in medieval works, more specifically in the works to which Abū al-barakāt had direct and recurrent access. 5 Due to the format s requirement of a review essay, I have to restrict my presentation to these two examples to give the reader some idea of the lack of historical contextualization toward which I am pointing. In view of the blatant absence of any critical discussion on the potential influences of the figures who shaped the 800-year history of philosophy that separate Abū al-barakāt from Aristotle, concluding on the non-existence of Islamic elements within the former s philosophical endeavor sounds more analogous to a petitio principii than a research hypothesis. This lack of proper historical contextualization makes Pavlov s repetitive claims on the thinker s radical originality very dubious. Even though I am also deeply convinced of the uniqueness of Abū al-barakāt s philosophical enterprise, removing it from its adequate historical framework makes it very hazardous to determine the nature and extension of its originality. An internal analysis of the text, regardless of how rigorous and minute it can be, is not enough to address the issue of potential historical influences. Many of the most significant sources were left unidentified simply because they were, for example, too obvious for the contemporary reader to require further labelling. Furthermore, the way a philosopher may refer to his/her predecessors more often counts as a rhetorical stage-setting than as a meticulous approach to situate oneself objectively if only it were possible within the scope of the history of philosophy. in Methodological and Historical Contexts would require a little bit more caution before formulating plain statements of this kind. See Katerina Ierodiakonou and Sophie Roux, Thought Experiments in Methodological and Historical Contexts (Leiden: Brill, 2011). 5 My point here does not require me to address the debated issue of Avicenna s philosophical purpose behind his Floating / Flying Man thought experiment. However, to my knowledge the nature of his thought experiment has never been challenged. See Michael E. Marmura, Avicenna s Flying Man in Context, The Monist 69, no. 3 (1986): 383-95. Moreover, Jon McGinnis has recently addressed the variety of the use of these experiments by Muslims philosophers, in particular by Avicenna. See Jon McGinnis, Experimental Thoughts about Thought Experiments in Medieval Islam, PhilSci Archives, accessed online on 28 August 2016, http://philsci-archive.pitt.edu/12391/. 172

Review Article With regard to the three main components of these two books thesis the Kitāb al-muʿtabar s systematic character, its culminating point in a special cognition of God s ipseity, and the distinctively Jewish nature of Abū al-barakāt s philosophy only the first one has been demonstrated convincingly. I would only express my reserve with respect to the underlying notion of the systematicity at play in the author s demonstration without contesting his final conclusion a notion that appeared to me as too embedded within the worldview of analytical philosophy to avoid creating a sensation of an anachronism once used in a medieval work. I also agree that the Kitāb al-muʿtabar s structure manifests a deep cohesion, touching, as Pavlov also alluded to, to a feeling of organicity. Nevertheless, the standard of systematicity toward which this philosophical treatise tends is obviously alien to the standard developed across the last century in analytical philosophy, which is mostly based on a framework conditioned by the development of modern scientific practices. I consider the two other parts of this project s thesis as stimulating research hypotheses that could have opened new perspectives and raised new questions on this philosophical masterpiece. Indeed, postulating a first and foremost Jewish character and impetus to Abū al-barakāt s philosophical enterprise could have, for example, forced the uncovering of unidentified Jewish sources and figures who could have remained unnoticed under the first layers of more obvious Islamic and Neoplatonist influences. Nevertheless, the author s tone and way of exposition indicate that these two statements are more truths that he has to convey rather than hypotheses designed to dynamize the field. Throughout the two volumes, these two aspects of the thesis are repeated at every crucial step of development, but without any significant addition or being seriously confronted with counterarguments and narratives. These numerous repetitions may be explained by the editorial choice to conceive of the chapters as independent entities that could be read separately; however, this technique has two side-effects: It significantly raises the burden of a complete reading of the two volumes and gives the impression of clouding the minutiae points of the demonstration. In conclusion, even though the author manages to prove the main point of his thesis the Kitāb al-muʿtabar s outstanding systematicity through a careful internal analysis of the work, the rest of his conclusions are deeply undermined by a blatant lack of sufficient historical contextualization a blatant lack that makes these two volumes too hazardous to recommend to an audience not sufficiently initiated into Islamic philosophy and too weak to raise interest among a more advanced readership. 173