Jan Narveson, Pacifism: A. Philosophical Examination 1

Similar documents
NOT SO PROMISING AFTER ALL: EVALUATOR-RELATIVE TELEOLOGY AND COMMON-SENSE MORALITY

The University of Chicago Press is collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to Ethics.

2 FREE CHOICE The heretical thesis of Hobbes is the orthodox position today. So much is this the case that most of the contemporary literature

A Contractualist Reply

Scanlon on Double Effect

On Searle on Human Rights, Again! J. Angelo Corlett, San Diego State University

Moral dilemmas. Digital Lingnan University. Lingnan University. Gopal Shyam NAIR

In Defense of Radical Empiricism. Joseph Benjamin Riegel. Chapel Hill 2006

Mohammad Reza Vaez Shahrestani. University of Bonn

Oxford Scholarship Online Abstracts and Keywords

Précis of Democracy and Moral Conflict

The Grounding for Moral Obligation

Reductive Individualism and the Just War Framework

EXTERNALISM AND THE CONTENT OF MORAL MOTIVATION

Universal Injuries Need Not Wound Internal Values A Response to Wysman

Bayesian Probability

Louisiana Law Review. Cheney C. Joseph Jr. Louisiana State University Law Center. Volume 35 Number 5 Special Issue Repository Citation

DEFEASIBLE A PRIORI JUSTIFICATION: A REPLY TO THUROW

McCLOSKEY ON RATIONAL ENDS: The Dilemma of Intuitionism

Fatalism and Truth at a Time Chad Marxen

FOUNDATIONALISM AND ARBITRARINESS

Legal Positivism: the Separation and Identification theses are true.

SWINBURNE ON THE EUTHYPHRO DILEMMA. CAN SUPERVENIENCE SAVE HIM?

Etchemendy, Tarski, and Logical Consequence 1 Jared Bates, University of Missouri Southwest Philosophy Review 15 (1999):

Pollock and Sturgeon on defeaters

PHILOSOPHY 5340 EPISTEMOLOGY

Note: This is the penultimate draft of an article the final and definitive version of which is

Consequentialism, Incoherence and Choice. Rejoinder to a Rejoinder.

Is Klein an infinitist about doxastic justification?

Higher-Order Approaches to Consciousness and the Regress Problem

In Epistemic Relativism, Mark Kalderon defends a view that has become

Shieva Kleinschmidt [This is a draft I completed while at Rutgers. Please do not cite without permission.] Conditional Desires.

THE TWO-DIMENSIONAL ARGUMENT AGAINST MATERIALISM AND ITS SEMANTIC PREMISE

Act Consequentialism s Compelling Idea and Deontology s Paradoxical Idea

IS ACT-UTILITARIANISM SELF-DEFEATING?

Attfield, Robin, and Barry Wilkins, "Sustainability." Environmental Values 3, no. 2, (1994):

DISCUSSION PRACTICAL POLITICS AND PHILOSOPHICAL INQUIRY: A NOTE

The Rightness Error: An Evaluation of Normative Ethics in the Absence of Moral Realism

BOOK REVIEW: Gideon Yaffee, Manifest Activity: Thomas Reid s Theory of Action

THE CASE OF THE MINERS

Jesus Christ and the Life of the Mind. By Mark A. Noll. Grand Rapids: Eerdmans, 2011, xii+

Testimony and Moral Understanding Anthony T. Flood, Ph.D. Introduction

GCE. Religious Studies. Mark Scheme for June Advanced Subsidiary GCE Unit G572: Religious Ethics. Oxford Cambridge and RSA Examinations

Andrea Westlund, in Selflessness and Responsibility for Self, argues

in defence of an argument for evans s principle 167

PHILOSOPHY OF LANGUAGE AND META-ETHICS

Choosing Rationally and Choosing Correctly *

Compatibilist Objections to Prepunishment

Is there a good epistemological argument against platonism? DAVID LIGGINS

INTUITION AND CONSCIOUS REASONING

The Salvation Army Positional Statement PEACEMAKING

a0rxh/ On Van Inwagen s Argument Against the Doctrine of Arbitrary Undetached Parts WESLEY H. BRONSON Princeton University

No Love for Singer: The Inability of Preference Utilitarianism to Justify Partial Relationships

TWO VERSIONS OF HUME S LAW

This document is downloaded from DR-NTU, Nanyang Technological University Library, Singapore.

Honor in the Military and the Possible Implication for the Traditional Separation

Ignorance, Humility and Vice

A Kantian Revision of the Doctrine of Double Effect

Against Phenomenal Conservatism

What God Could Have Made

DISCUSSION THE GUISE OF A REASON

The view that all of our actions are done in self-interest is called psychological egoism.

In this paper I offer an account of Christine Korsgaard s metaethical

Religion, peace and conflict

Why I am not a Consequentialist David S. Oderberg

Right-Making, Reference, and Reduction

The University of Chicago Press

THE "RIGHT" TO A FAIR TRIAL

Moral Objectivism. RUSSELL CORNETT University of Calgary

Epistemic Consequentialism, Truth Fairies and Worse Fairies

J. L. Mackie The Subjectivity of Values

Traditional Morality and Utilitarianism. Chapter 16, Kai Nielsen Introduction to Ethics Professor Douglas Olena

Naturalism and is Opponents

Can A Priori Justified Belief Be Extended Through Deduction? It is often assumed that if one deduces some proposition p from some premises

24.00: Problems of Philosophy Prof. Sally Haslanger November 16, 2005 Moral Relativism

The Department of Philosophy and Classics The University of Texas at San Antonio One UTSA Circle San Antonio, TX USA.

In Defense of Culpable Ignorance

prohibition, moral commitment and other normative matters. Although often described as a branch

part one MACROSTRUCTURE Cambridge University Press X - A Theory of Argument Mark Vorobej Excerpt More information

Reason and Explanation: A Defense of Explanatory Coherentism. BY TED POSTON (Basingstoke,

-- The search text of this PDF is generated from uncorrected OCR text.

A theory of adjudication is a theory primarily about what judges do when they decide cases in courts of law.

R. M. Hare (1919 ) SINNOTT- ARMSTRONG. Definition of moral judgments. Prescriptivism

TWO ACCOUNTS OF THE NORMATIVITY OF RATIONALITY

Has Nagel uncovered a form of idealism?

Universities of Leeds, Sheffield and York

Evaluating actions The principle of utility Strengths Criticisms Act vs. rule

ALTERNATIVE SELF-DEFEAT ARGUMENTS: A REPLY TO MIZRAHI

Foundationalism Vs. Skepticism: The Greater Philosophical Ideology

Noncognitivism in Ethics, by Mark Schroeder. London: Routledge, 251 pp.

Most philosophy books, it s fair to say, contain more footnotes than graphs. By this

Self-Evidence and A Priori Moral Knowledge

Interest-Relativity and Testimony Jeremy Fantl, University of Calgary

Philosophical Perspectives, 16, Language and Mind, 2002 THE AIM OF BELIEF 1. Ralph Wedgwood Merton College, Oxford

Judge s Two Options: he can (i) let the rioters kill the five hostages, or (ii) frame an innocent person for the crime, and have him executed.

DOES CONSEQUENTIALISM DEMAND TOO MUCH?

In this paper I will critically discuss a theory known as conventionalism

Boghossian, Bellarmine, and Bayes

Debate British Parliament -Roles, Rules & Regulation. UQP1331 Basic Communication

Cognitivism about imperatives

Transcription:

Jan Narveson, Pacifism: A Philosophical Examination 1 Cécile Fabre (All Souls College, Oxford) cecile.fabre@all-souls.ox.ac.uk CSSJ Working Papers Series, SJ029 November 2014 Centre for the Study of Social Justice Department of Politics and International Relations University of Oxford Manor Road, Oxford OX1 3UQ United Kingdom Tel: +44 1865 278703 Fax: +44 1865 278725 http://social-justice.politics.ox.ac.uk 1 A retrospective on Jan Narveson, Pacifism: A Philosophical Investigation, Ethics 75 (1965): 259-271. All references to sections and page numbers are to this article, unless otherwise noted.

Narveson s article appeared in 1965, halfway through between the Cuban Missiles Crisis (1962) and the Tet Offensive (1968). The Cold War - in which the USA and the USSR did not shed each other s blood - was still the dominant model of war in American consciousness, and hundreds of thousands of American soldiers had not yet been thrown, to kill and be killed, into the fields of Vietnam. Michael Walzer had not yet published his landmark Just and Unjust Wars (1977); 2 the Trolley Problem, central to contemporary discussions of the permissibility of killing another person, had not yet made an appearance; and there was hardly any work in extant philosophical literature on the ethics of killing in general, and the ethics of war in general, let alone on pacifism. 3 Narveson s piece, if only for those reasons alone, is remarkably prescient of debates to come. It is also still widely cited in the contemporary ethics of defensive force in general and of war in particular. Its central thesis is that pacifism is an incoherent doctrine. For pacifism holds (or so Narveson tells us) that it is always morally wrong to use force against violence in other words, that all individuals have a right not to be treated violently, for short a right to security. Yet one cannot have a right without also having a right to do whatever is necessary to protect oneself from breaches of that right. Therefore, to have a right to security - a right which is central to pacifists 2 Michael Walzer, Just and Unjust Wars (New York: Basic Books, 1977). 3 A JSTOR search conducted for the purpose of writing this introductory piece with the title-keywords pacifism, war and killing yielded 55 results under Philosophy for the years 1900-1965, and 244 results for the years 1966-2013. Even accounting for the fact that Philosophy and Public Affairs and the Journal of Political Philosophy, which are both generous hosts for articles on those topics, were founded after 1965, this strikes me as a significant increase. 2

rejection of violence - is also to have a right to do whatever is necessary to remain secure and thus to use force which is precisely what pacifists deny. Or so Narveson objects. Importantly, Narveson does not deny that individuals are morally permitted not to defend themselves against violence should they so wish: his claim is that they cannot on pain of being incoherent turn their wish not to use violence into a moral principle by which we should all abide. Nor does he deny that individuals are morally permitted not to defend others against violence: his claim is that there is no basic moral duty to defend others but that if one lives in a community whose members conventionally expect of one another that they will defend one another by force, then one should either fulfill that obligation or emigrate. Reading this article in the light of nearly five decades of work in this particular area of normative ethics, one is left with the sense that although Narveson misdescribes and misses his target, he nevertheless hits on avenues of inquiry which have not been fully explored. Pacifists will begin by querying the way he characterises their position. For surely it is open to them to say, not that they oppose the use of any kind of force against violence, but that they oppose the act of killing, or even grievously maiming, another person in self-defence or in defence of others. This would enable them to block Narveson s objection that they cannot endorse punishment (to the extent that punishment is forceful.) Even so, they would still have to confront what one may call the what about your mother? objection in other words, the objection that if one act of killing is morally justified, surely it is the act of defending one s mother from a brutal murderer. As applied to war, they would still have to confront what one may call the What about WWII? objection in other words, the objection that if one war was justified, surely this one is. Narveson rightly points out that the strength of the pacifist s conviction is most severely 3

tested by these kinds of cases. Pacifists have attempted to block those objections by distinguishing between absolute pacifism (of the kind attacked by Narveson) and contingent pacifism (defined as opposition to killing and war in almost all circumstances), or between universal pacifism ( we should all oppose violence ) and relative pacifism ( only those who describe as pacifists are under a duty to oppose violence.) 4 None of those positions is without serious difficulties some of them articulated by Narveson himself. In particular, contingent pacifism as a rejection of war under current circumstances is so similar to just war theory as to be undistinguishable from it, so much so that one is left to wonder what is left of pacifism as a coherent and distinctive doctrine. That said, pacifists ought not to be moved - indeed have not been moved by the charge of incoherence which Narveson levels at them. For a start, having a right does not logically entail having a right to do whatever is necessary to protect that right: the claim that the latter follows from the former is precisely what pacifists deny, and to assert that claim without providing an independent justification for it begs the question. In addition, that claim yields the conclusion that, for example, I have the right to kill dozens of innocent bystanders to prevent you from pinching my nose if that is the only way to stop you. 5 This surely is 4 For a typology of different types of pacifism, see Andrew Fiala, "Pacifism," Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (2010), http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/fall2010/entries/pacifism. 5 For criticisms of Narveson s arguments, see Cheney Ryan, "Self-Defense, Pacifism, and the Permissibility of Killing," Ethics (1983): 508-524; Jenny Teichman, Pacifism and the Just War: A Study in Applied Philosophy (Oxford: Blackwell, 1986). 4

unacceptably permissive, and pacifists are thus on strong grounds to reject Narveson s criticism out of hand. However, although Narveson does not succeed in undermining pacifism anymore than he succeeds at establishing defensive rights, he does raise anew the question of what we may do in defence of our rights or the rights of others. That question has not yet received fully satisfactory answers. Given the avalanche of works in the ethics of defense and in just war theory through which we now have to wade, this may seem a surprising diagnosis. And yet, advocates of defensive rights all too often trust in the verdictive force of the intuition that surely we may use force, indeed kill, in self- and other defense, while pacifists place the fate of their opposition to violence in the contrary intuition that we may not do so. But more work than has been recently carried is needed to adjudicate this clash of intuitions. In addition, proponents of the view that war is sometimes justified all too often conclude that here and now, it is not for example because under current circumstances it would be disproportionate; in so doing, they are left with the task of working out what we may do, in defence of rights, when war is not an option. Narveson s question-begging and implausible move against pacifists invites us to think again, and harder, about defensive rights. Thus, while meant as a rebuttal of pacifism and in part successful as such Narveson s article perhaps unwittingly also presents a serious challenge to its critics. This, I think, is why it remains a classic to this day. 5