Figure 1 Figure 2 U S S. non-p P P

Similar documents
Paradox of Deniability

1. Lukasiewicz s Logic

A Liar Paradox. Richard G. Heck, Jr. Brown University

Horwich and the Liar

Remarks on a Foundationalist Theory of Truth. Anil Gupta University of Pittsburgh

how to be an expressivist about truth

Chadwick Prize Winner: Christian Michel THE LIAR PARADOX OUTSIDE-IN

Intersubstitutivity Principles and the Generalization Function of Truth. Anil Gupta University of Pittsburgh. Shawn Standefer University of Melbourne

Future Contingents, Non-Contradiction and the Law of Excluded Middle Muddle

Appeared in: Al-Mukhatabat. A Trilingual Journal For Logic, Epistemology and Analytical Philosophy, Issue 6: April 2013.

Can Gödel s Incompleteness Theorem be a Ground for Dialetheism? *

Troubles with Trivialism

Semantic Pathology and the Open Pair

(Some More) Vagueness

TRUTH-MAKERS AND CONVENTION T

Situations in Which Disjunctive Syllogism Can Lead from True Premises to a False Conclusion

God of the gaps: a neglected reply to God s stone problem

Informalizing Formal Logic

Lecture 3. I argued in the previous lecture for a relationist solution to Frege's puzzle, one which

Am I free? Freedom vs. Fate

Divine Eternity and the Reduplicative Qua. are present to God or does God experience a succession of moments? Most philosophers agree

prohibition, moral commitment and other normative matters. Although often described as a branch

Circularity in ethotic structures

From Necessary Truth to Necessary Existence

Automated Reasoning Project. Research School of Information Sciences and Engineering. and Centre for Information Science Research

From Transcendental Logic to Transcendental Deduction

A Logical Approach to Metametaphysics

Logic and Pragmatics: linear logic for inferential practice

15. Russell on definite descriptions

A Generalization of Hume s Thesis

Empty Names and Two-Valued Positive Free Logic

Can Negation be Defined in Terms of Incompatibility?

Affirmation-Negation: New Perspective

SWINBURNE ON THE EUTHYPHRO DILEMMA. CAN SUPERVENIENCE SAVE HIM?

A Review of Neil Feit s Belief about the Self

Reply to Robert Koons

RUSSELL, NEGATIVE FACTS, AND ONTOLOGY* L. NATHAN OAKLANDERt SILVANO MIRACCHI

CHAPTER III. Of Opposition.

Has Nagel uncovered a form of idealism?

Review of "The Tarskian Turn: Deflationism and Axiomatic Truth"

WRIGHT ON BORDERLINE CASES AND BIVALENCE 1

In Search of the Ontological Argument. Richard Oxenberg

Understanding Truth Scott Soames Précis Philosophy and Phenomenological Research Volume LXV, No. 2, 2002

NB: Presentations will be assigned on the second week. Suggested essay topics will be distributed in May.

What is the Frege/Russell Analysis of Quantification? Scott Soames

2.3. Failed proofs and counterexamples

1. Introduction Formal deductive logic Overview

Williams on Supervaluationism and Logical Revisionism

10 CERTAINTY G.E. MOORE: SELECTED WRITINGS

Constructive Logic, Truth and Warranted Assertibility

A Judgmental Formulation of Modal Logic

Deflated truth pluralism

Semantic Foundations for Deductive Methods

SAVING RELATIVISM FROM ITS SAVIOUR

Moore on External Relations

Negation, Denial, and Rejection

On Priest on nonmonotonic and inductive logic

Russell: On Denoting

Maudlin s Truth and Paradox Hartry Field

Faults and Mathematical Disagreement

Circumscribing Inconsistency

Evaluating Classical Identity and Its Alternatives by Tamoghna Sarkar

McCLOSKEY ON RATIONAL ENDS: The Dilemma of Intuitionism

A Note on a Remark of Evans *

Is the law of excluded middle a law of logic?

The Revenge of the Liar: New Essays on the Paradox. Edited by Jc Beall. Oxford University Press, Kevin Scharp. The Ohio State University

Can Negation be Defined in Terms of Incompatibility?

BOOK REVIEWS. About a new solution to the problem of future contingents

What is the Nature of Logic? Judy Pelham Philosophy, York University, Canada July 16, 2013 Pan-Hellenic Logic Symposium Athens, Greece

JELIA Justification Logic. Sergei Artemov. The City University of New York

Each copy of any part of a JSTOR transmission must contain the same copyright notice that appears on the screen or printed page of such transmission.

BENEDIKT PAUL GÖCKE. Ruhr-Universität Bochum

The distinction between truth-functional and non-truth-functional logical and linguistic

Fatalism and Truth at a Time Chad Marxen

Who or what is God?, asks John Hick (Hick 2009). A theist might answer: God is an infinite person, or at least an

Do the Paradoxes Pose a Special Problem for Deflationism? Anil Gupta. University of Pittsburgh

3. Negations Not: contradicting content Contradictory propositions Overview Connectives

A Model of Decidable Introspective Reasoning with Quantifying-In

6. Truth and Possible Worlds

Published in Michal Peliš (ed.) The Logica Yearbook 2007 (Prague: Filosofia), pp , 2008.

Action in Special Contexts

Coordination Problems

Potentialism about set theory

Chapter 3 On the Philosophy and Mathematics of the Logics of Formal Inconsistency

THIRD NEW C OLLEGE LO GIC MEETING

An Introduction to. Formal Logic. Second edition. Peter Smith, February 27, 2019

1.2. What is said: propositions

Assertion and Rejection

HANDBOOK (New or substantially modified material appears in boxes.)

Free will & divine foreknowledge

TOWARDS A PHILOSOPHICAL UNDERSTANDING OF THE LOGICS OF FORMAL INCONSISTENCY

The Ontological Argument for the existence of God. Pedro M. Guimarães Ferreira S.J. PUC-Rio Boston College, July 13th. 2011

Faith and Philosophy, April (2006), DE SE KNOWLEDGE AND THE POSSIBILITY OF AN OMNISCIENT BEING Stephan Torre

McTaggart s Proof of the Unreality of Time

On The Logical Status of Dialectic (*) -Historical Development of the Argument in Japan- Shigeo Nagai Naoki Takato

Philosophy 220. Truth Functional Properties Expressed in terms of Consistency

Truth and Modality - can they be reconciled?

ROBERT STALNAKER PRESUPPOSITIONS

Prior on an insolubilium of Jean Buridan

Que sera sera. Robert Stone

Transcription:

1 Depicting negation in diagrammatic logic: legacy and prospects Fabien Schang, Amirouche Moktefi schang.fabien@voila.fr amirouche.moktefi@gersulp.u-strasbg.fr Abstract Here are considered the conditions under which the method of diagrams is liable to include non-classical logics, among which the spatial representation of non-bivalent negation. This will be done with two intended purposes, namely: a review of the main concepts involved in the definition of logical negation; an explanation of the epistemological obstacles against the introduction of non-classical negations within diagrammatic logic. 1. From dichotomy to bivalence In the primary diagrams suggested in the logic of classes, each predication of the form S is P was presented by a circle or closed curve symbolizing the class P and in which an element S occurred; in other words, S is P is a true proposition if and only if the individual value occurs in the region purported to figure the class of individuals which satisfy the property P. A translation of classes in terms of propositions or predications is thus possible, provided that the class P is considered as a predicate term attached to a subject term S. As to the set of individuals which don't satisfy the property P, they must occur outside the closed curve that determines the set of P's. One first epistemological obstacle to non-classical logics is the lack of any universe of discourse in the first suggested diagrams, as shown by the distinction below. Figure 1 Figure 2 U S S non-p P P

2 In Figure 1, the set of individuals that are not P (i.e. the non-p's) are not located in a specific space since only the closed curve is taken into account; whereas in Figure 2, all the non-p's correspond to the region located outside the closed curve and are within the universe of discourse U. We call by dichotomy the opposition between the whole individuals located within (the class) P and the whole remaining ones located outside (the class) P. The opposition between P and non-p thus characterizes logical negation as a dichotomy; it is presented in diagrammatic logic as a spatial contrast in vs. out. As to the semantic notion of bivalence, it extends dichotomy in splitting the universe of discourse into two classes of truth-values. If S is located in the region of P's, then the proposition S is P is true; if S is not located in the region of P's, then S is P is false. Now since S cannot be both in and outside P, the truth of the proposition S is P entails the falsehood of its negation S is not P, and the falsehood of the proposition S is P entails the truth of its negation S is not P. Consequently, every proposition does have a truth-value within the universe of discourse: either it is true, or it is false; no proposition can be both in and outside the closed curve, so that if a proposition is true then it is not false and if it is false then it is not true. Another way to state these two properties of bivalence is to say that a diagram is complete and consistent. It seems difficult to challenge bivalence in logical diagrams, assuming that it implies for any element S in U both its occurrence and non-ubiquity. Nevertheless, the logic of diagrams gave way to the introduction of non-classical constants in its modern variants, including non-classical negation. How to embed the latter without questioning both preceding requirements of completeness and consistency? Our answer is: by internalizing truth-values within the logic of diagrams, and by making a distinction between two readings of negation. Our final claim is that non-classical negation is less revolutionary than it might appear first, insofar as it doesn't really challenge the general property of dichotomy. 2. From exclusion negation to choice negation By an internalization, we mean the process that consists in introducing a metalanguage notion within the object-language. While truth-values belong to metalanguage in the logic of diagrams, given that they don't occur in the logical space U, some non-classical logics make use of the following process in order to depict non-classical constants, namely: to see the general proposition of the form S is P as an element in a class of truth-value (a semantic class, say); e.g. [S is P: p] is true, with [S is P: p] for S and true for P. We thus obtain the subsequent illustrations of non-classical logic, where the Venn scheme is internalized in the semantic level of truth-values. In Figure 3, a diagram is generally presented as a range of possible relations between two distinct classes and the combinations of which are counted as 2² = 4; by analogy with

3 the classes of propositions, the classes of truth-values equally propose four possible relations between the class T of true propositions and the class F of false propositions. Figure 3 Figure 4 (non-p non-q) = P Q (non-t non-f) = T F (P Q) = (T F) = PQ TF (P non-q) = P Q (non-p Q) = PQ (T non-f) = T F (non-t F) = TF Any proposition can thus be considered as: true and non-false, false and non-true, true and false, non-true and non-false. Unlike diagrams in classical logic, Figure 4 displays a non-bivalent space in which a proposition can be neither true nor false or both true and false. In this sense, the space U' of non-classical logics is not complete but paracomplete; it is not consistent, either, but paraconsistant. A sample of paracomplete three-valued logics are Kleene's intuitionistic logic in [3] or Łukasiewicz's logic of indetermination in [4], in which some propositions are neither true nor false indécidable; a case of paraconsistent logic is Priest's dialetheist logic in [6], in which a proposition can be paradoxal and, therefore, both true and false. However, paraconsistency doesn't mean that a proposition may be both in and outside one and the same class: if it is both true and false, then it is located within the class TF that intersects T and F. Paracompleteness doesn't mean any more that a proposition may be absent from the universe of discourse, given that propositions that are neither true nor false are located in U'. Therefore, the introduction of non-classical diagrams does not entail the revision of dichotomy as such: if a proposition is not true, for instance, then it is located in the non-true (in T) and, thus, outside the true (i.e. outside T); although it may be both true and false, such a case does not constitute any more an infringement to dichotomy than for an element S to be both in the class P and the class Q. In other words, the change caused by non-classical logics may generate some plausible confusion between the concepts of bivalence and dichotomy: the former states that any true proposition is non-false and any false proposition is non-true, hence an obvious connection between such a formulation and dichotomy. However, dichotomy merely

4 requires the distinction between an arbitrary class and any other one that is not itself: P and non-p, true and non-true, false and non-false, and so on. In order to bring out the distinction between mere difference and incompatibility, it can be said that while the class T of strictly true propositions and the class F of strictly false propositions are dichotomous in classical logic and even in a number of non-classical logics, T's and F's are no more dichotomous in non-classical logics since TF is a new class in U' including both true and false propositions. Consequently, this means that a number of non-classical negations are not dichotomous whenever they don't always require true propositions to be outside the false region and false propositions to be outside the true region. Borrowing a terminology from Terence Parsons in [4], the difference is made here between negation as a choice operation and negation as an exclusion operation. While exclusion negation generally consists in projecting any proposition from a class (whether semantic or not) into another class, choice negation turns a proposition into another proposition but doesn't necessarily projects it from a semantic class to another one. Łukasiewicz's or Priest's logics are an illustration of it, since the (choice) negation of a proposition that is neither strictly true nor strictly false (say, indeterminate: T F = I) results in an unchanged truth-value when the negation is said to be normal: v(p) = v(~p) = I, so that p and non-p do have the same truth-value. Such a non-classical negation does not exhibit any more the property of exclusion that characterizes dichotomy. Let us note that, while not every logical negation acts as an exclusion operation, some non-classical negations still do. These are said to be non-normal, e.g. Post'c cyclic negation: for an ordered series of {1,...,i,... n} truth-values, v(~p) = i+1 whenever v(p) = i, so the truthvalues of P and not-p are never the same. How to characterize logical negation intensionally, if not every negation is to be depicted as a exclusion operation? As Brady put it in [1], we can consider an intensional property of logical negation that is more general than dichotomy and does justice to both classical and non-classical negations, that is: negation as a mirror-image concept with an axis of symmetry. If one depicts a range of three truth-values with T and F as opposite sides and I in the middle, then the negation of I results in I just as the mirror-image of any point located in an axis of symmetry results in this point itself. Thus, not every logical negation is an exclusion property when applied to propositions with a non-classical value; nevertheless, the distinction between classical and nonclassical remains as a dichotomy in itself between {T,F} and not-{t,f}. The overall situation may be summarized as follows: - exclusion negation ' ' is an intensional property: it rejects a proposition (p) outside the semantic class of p, but without determining the class in which (p) should be located; and conversely, choice negation '~' is extensional since it determines a specific semantic class

5 for ~(p) without rejecting it necessarily outside the semantic class of p. Priest's paraconsistent negation, for example, locates the negation of a strictly true proposition in the strictly false region F, the negation of a strictly false proposition in the strictly true region T, and the negation of a paradoxical proposition (i.e. both true and false) in the paradoxical region TF. - the assimilation of logical negation to dichotomy is due to the behavior of choice negation within classical, bivalent logic: given that only two strictly separate semantic classes occur in it (i.e. T and F), classical negation behaves exactly like an exclusion negation and the distinction between choice ' ' and exclusio '~' is thus made impossible extensionaliy speaking, contrary to the case with most of non-classical logics and especially the threevalued ones. - being inconsistent does not mean the same as being contradictory if, by contradictory, we mean the possibility to be both X and non-x whatever the syntactic category of X may be (whether a class of propositions or a class of truth-values). Paraconsistent logic does not include both true and non-true propositions or false and not-false propositions: T T and F F cannot occur in U'. Such a non-classical (choice) negation doesn't infringe dichotomy at all: it seems to do so only for whoever goes on to think of it in a classical universe of discourse U without including the more complex universe U'. But to accept TF in U is an impossible thing to do, so that the confusion between paraconsistency and true contradictions is nothing more than a confusion between the logical spaces U and U' as different frameworks for thinking about truth-values. Conclusion: non-classical negations are harmless for dichotomy as such In sum, the introduction of non-classical logics into diagrams entails neither a significant revolution within the logical space, nor the obligation to modify our representation of such a space so as to allow the ubiquity of propositions both in and outside one and the same class. The process of internalization merely helps to make propositions relatively true and false and to go beyond the strictly separate relation between T and F within a bivalent framework; now if such a process if refused, then it appears as literally impossible to think of negation from a non-classical perspective, given the spatial relation in-out as a undebatable statement of dichotomy. In a nutshell: either logical negations are dichotomous or not, as choice operations; but they don't infringe to dichotomy in a logical space at all, because such an infringement would assume a substantial change in the very geometrical properties of the logical space. Nothing similar occurs in paraconsistent or paracomplete logics in U', anyway. One task remains to be accomplished in non-classical diagrammatic logic once the internalization is accepted, namely: assuming that not every non-classical logic is a exclusion operation and, thus, an operation of complementation, how to represent the non-

6 complementary laws of projection between p and not-p for paraconsistent and paracomplete negations in U', and which of these projections should replace the dichotomous relation in-out that marks classical negation? Such a task will be accomplished in a later paper about the specific case of da Costa & Béziau's overclassical logic (see [3]), a case of paraconsistent negation that rejects the laws of non-contradiction and excluded middle while maintaining De Morgan's laws and double negation. References [1] R. T. Brady: On the formalization of the Law of non-contradictionˮ, in The Law of Non- Contradiction (New Philosophical Essays), G. Priest & J.C. Beall & B. Armour-Garb. (ed.), Clarendon Press, Oxford (2004), pp. 41-8 [2] N.C.A. da Costa & J.-Y. Béziau: Overclassical Logicˮ, Logique et Analyse 157(1997), 45-66 [3] S. Kleene: Introduction to Metamathematics, Amsterdam, Groningen, New York (1952) [4] J. Łukasiewicz: On three-valued logicˮ, Ruch Filozoficzny 5(1920), 170-1 [5] T. Parsons: Assertion, Denial, and the Liar Paradox, Journal of Philosophical Logic 13(1984); 137-152 [6] G. Priest: The Logic of Paradoxˮ, Journal of Philosophical Logic 8(1979), 219-41