Topics in Philosophy of Mind Other Minds Spring 2003/handout 2

Similar documents
NOTES ON WILLIAMSON: CHAPTER 11 ASSERTION Constitutive Rules

ON EPISTEMIC ENTITLEMENT. by Crispin Wright and Martin Davies. II Martin Davies

How Hard Are the Sceptical Paradoxes?

Scepticism, Rationalism and Externalism *

A Priori Skepticism and the KK Thesis

THE SEMANTIC REALISM OF STROUD S RESPONSE TO AUSTIN S ARGUMENT AGAINST SCEPTICISM

John Hawthorne s Knowledge and Lotteries

Scepticism, Rationalism and Externalism

PHL340 Handout 8: Evaluating Dogmatism

Contextualism and the Epistemological Enterprise

A Priori Bootstrapping

Transmission Failure Failure Final Version in Philosophical Studies (2005), 126: Nicholas Silins

STEWART COHEN AND THE CONTEXTUALIST THEORY OF JUSTIFICATION

McDowell and the New Evil Genius

Is Moore s Argument an Example of Transmission-Failure? James Pryor Harvard University Draft 2 8/12/01

Direct Realism and the Brain-in-a-Vat Argument by Michael Huemer (2000)

This is a collection of fourteen previously unpublished papers on the fit

The Skeptic and the Dogmatist

STROUD, AUSTIN, AND RADICAL SKEPTICISM

10 CERTAINTY G.E. MOORE: SELECTED WRITINGS

Outsmarting the McKinsey-Brown argument? 1

VARIETIES OF SKEPTICISM. Jonathan Vogel Amherst Collge and Harvard University

This handout follows the handout on The nature of the sceptic s challenge. You should read that handout first.

INTRODUCTION. This week: Moore's response, Nozick's response, Reliablism's response, Externalism v. Internalism.

Philosophy Epistemology. Topic 3 - Skepticism

Skepticism is True. Abraham Meidan

New Lessons from Old Demons: The Case for Reliabilism

Can A Priori Justified Belief Be Extended Through Deduction? It is often assumed that if one deduces some proposition p from some premises

Klein on the Unity of Cartesian and Contemporary Skepticism

Varieties of Apriority

Mohammad Reza Vaez Shahrestani. University of Bonn

THE MORAL ARGUMENT. Peter van Inwagen. Introduction, James Petrik

On A New Cosmological Argument

Wittgenstein on the Fallacy of the Argument from Pretence. Abstract

Received: 30 August 2007 / Accepted: 16 November 2007 / Published online: 28 December 2007 # Springer Science + Business Media B.V.

Notes for Week 4 of Contemporary Debates in Epistemology

DEFEASIBLE A PRIORI JUSTIFICATION: A REPLY TO THUROW

KANT S EXPLANATION OF THE NECESSITY OF GEOMETRICAL TRUTHS. John Watling

DOUBT, CIRCULARITY AND THE MOOREAN RESPONSE TO THE SCEPTIC. Jessica Brown University of Bristol

Jeu-Jenq Yuann Professor of Philosophy Department of Philosophy, National Taiwan University,

Dogmatism and Moorean Reasoning. Markos Valaris University of New South Wales. 1. Introduction

SUPPOSITIONAL REASONING AND PERCEPTUAL JUSTIFICATION

How to Mistake a Trivial Fact About Probability For a. Substantive Fact About Justified Belief

Skepticism and Internalism

Seigel and Silins formulate the following theses:

Questioning Contextualism Brian Weatherson, Cornell University references etc incomplete

Scepticism, Infallibilism, Fallibilism

M.Phil. thesis ( May 1999)

So, among your current vast store of indubitable beliefs are the following: It seems to me that I am in Philosophy 100.

LENT 2018 THEORY OF MEANING DR MAARTEN STEENHAGEN

Skeptical Hypotheses and Moral Skepticism

ALTERNATIVE SELF-DEFEAT ARGUMENTS: A REPLY TO MIZRAHI

KRIPKE ON WITTGENSTEIN. Pippa Schwarzkopf

Common Sense: A Contemporary Defense By Noah Lemos Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, pp. xvi


RESPECTING THE EVIDENCE. Richard Feldman University of Rochester

G.E. Moore A Refutation of Skepticism

AN EPISTEMIC PARADOX. Byron KALDIS

CONDITIONAL PROPOSITIONS AND CONDITIONAL ASSERTIONS

MULTI-PEER DISAGREEMENT AND THE PREFACE PARADOX. Kenneth Boyce and Allan Hazlett

what you know is a constitutive norm of the practice of assertion. 2 recently maintained that in either form, the knowledge account of assertion when

5: Preliminaries to the Argument

WHAT DOES KRIPKE MEAN BY A PRIORI?

From the Routledge Encyclopedia of Philosophy

Of Skepticism with Regard to the Senses. David Hume

External World Skepticism

Ayer on the criterion of verifiability

SKEPTICISM, EXTERNALISM AND INFERENCE TO THE BEST EXPLANATION. Jochen Briesen

Speaking of Knowing PATRICK RYSIEW 1. INTRODUCTION

How and How Not to Take on Brueckner s Sceptic. Christoph Kelp Institute of Philosophy, KU Leuven

Externalism and a priori knowledge of the world: Why privileged access is not the issue Maria Lasonen-Aarnio

Exercise Sets. KS Philosophical Logic: Modality, Conditionals Vagueness. Dirk Kindermann University of Graz July 2014

Moral Relativism and Conceptual Analysis. David J. Chalmers

Externalism, Self-Knowledge and Transmission of Warrant

Knowing and Knowledge. Though the scope, limits, and conditions of human knowledge are of personal and professional

Reductio ad Absurdum, Modulation, and Logical Forms. Miguel López-Astorga 1

A Closer Look At Closure Scepticism

KNOWING AGAINST THE ODDS

Do we have knowledge of the external world?

fails utterly. Similarly, a second received interpretation imputes an aim of refuting

PHILOSOPHY EPISTEMOLOGY ESSAY TOPICS AND INSTRUCTIONS

Entitlement, epistemic risk and scepticism

OSSA Conference Archive OSSA 3

A. Problem set #3 it has been posted and is due Tuesday, 15 November

All philosophical debates not due to ignorance of base truths or our imperfect rationality are indeterminate.

Penultimate Draft: Final Revisions not included. Published in Philosophical Books, 1995.

Stout s teleological theory of action

Notes on Bertrand Russell s The Problems of Philosophy (Hackett 1990 reprint of the 1912 Oxford edition, Chapters XII, XIII, XIV, )

Précis of Empiricism and Experience. Anil Gupta University of Pittsburgh

TRANSCENDENTAL ARGUMENTS: VERIPICATIONISM OR PARASITISM? Douglas Ehring

Epistemological Foundations for Koons Cosmological Argument?

Different kinds of naturalistic explanations of linguistic behaviour

Ayer s linguistic theory of the a priori

Verificationism. PHIL September 27, 2011

Indexical Reliabilism and the New Evil Demon *

What is the Frege/Russell Analysis of Quantification? Scott Soames

Foreknowledge, evil, and compatibility arguments

McCLOSKEY ON RATIONAL ENDS: The Dilemma of Intuitionism

Epistemology. Theory of Knowledge

Chance, Chaos and the Principle of Sufficient Reason

Transcription:

24.500 Topics in Philosophy of Mind Other Minds Spring 2003/handout 2 Stroud Some background: the sceptical argument in Significance, ch. 1. (Lifted from How hard are the sceptical paradoxes? ) The argument from the unproved assumption Let a be a sentence expressing an unproved assumption, p be a sentence expressing some external world proposition, for instance that one has a hand, and interpret Kα > Kβ as: one knows that α antecedently to knowing that β (Pryor s terminology: see The skeptic and the dogmatist ). (Note that Kα > Kβ implies both Kα and Kβ.) Then the argument from the unproved assumption can be put as follows: UA (U) Kα (Ka > Kα ) (U) is a schema, instances of which are obtained by replacing α with sentences expressing external world propositions. Replacing α once with p, and then replacing it with a (which itself expresses an external world proposition, for instance that one s perceptual faculties are reliable), yields: (1) Kp (Ka > Kp) And: (2) Ka (Ka > Ka) Since the antecedently-to relation is (we may assume) asymmetric: (3) (Ka > Ka) It follows from the consequent of (1) that Ka, and from (2) and (3) it follows that Ka. Hence the sceptical conclusion: (4) Kp

2 An example: I cannot acquire sufficient reason to believe that I am not dreaming by any empirical procedure. For before carrying out an empirical procedure can give me reason to believe something, I need to have sufficient reason to believe that it has been properly carried out, a fortiori that it has been carrried out at all. And I can have sufficient reason to believe that only if I have sufficient reason to believe that I did not dream its execution. So empirically based reason to believe that I am not dreaming is excluded. Since the proposition seems quite unsuitable to be reasonably believed by me a priori, I cannot, the sceptic will contend, acquire sufficient reason to believe it at all. (Wright, Facts and Certainty, first emphasis mine.) Letting d express the proposition that one is dreaming, the schema in the Stroudian version of UA is: (U*) Kα (K d > Kα ) Following Stroud, call the claim that every external world instance of (U*) is true, Descartes Condition. We may concede that once we accept Descartes Condition, the game is over. But why should we accept it? According to Stroud, it appears to be an instance of a more general principle that we accept in everyday life: Given our original favourable response to Descartes s reasoning, then, it can scarcely be denied that what I have called his assumption or condition seems perfectly natural to insist on. Perhaps it seems like nothing more that an insistence of a familiar commonplace about knowledge. We are all aware that, even in the most ordinary circumstances when nothing very important turns on the outcome, we cannot know a particular thing unless we have ruled out certain possibilities that we recognize are incompatible with our knowing that thing. (Significance, 24, my emphasis).

3 Note that the italicized claim should be read as: we cannot know a particular thing unless we have antecedently ruled out possibilities that we recognize are incompatible with our knowing that thing. And later Stroud mentions another possibility for the general principle of which Descartes Condition is an instance: Reflecting even on the uncontroversial everyday examples alone can easily lead us to suppose that [the general principle] is something like this: if somebody knows something, p, he must know the falsity of all those things incompatible with his knowing that p (or perhaps all those things he knows to be incompatible with his knowing that p). (29-30, my italics) Again, for explicitness the word antecedently should be inserted before know in the italicized part. The first quotation (and the parenthetical part of the second) suggests the following schematic principle (where α and β may be replaced with any sentences expressing external world propositions): (A) [Kα & K(Kα β)] (Kβ > Kα) And the second quotation suggests an alternative: (B) [Kα & (Kα β)] (Kβ > Kα) Note that, because K(Kα β) implies Kα β, the antecedent of (A) is equivalent to the antecedent of (B) plus the conjunct K(Kα β), and so (by the principle of strengthening the antecedent ) (B) implies (A). We may therefore exclusively consider (A), since the weaker the principle, the stronger the sceptic s case. Assuming (reasonably enough, at least for knowers like ourselves) that one does know that if one knows some external world proposition p, then one is not dreaming, then an instance of (A), replacing β with d, gives us Descartes Condition. (Note that sceptical consequences can be drawn from (A) more quickly: replacing α and β both with p and assuming that K(Kp p), gives us that Kp, because (Kp > Kp).)

4 Sceptical consequences aside, (A) is not very appealing. Replacing β with Kp, and assuming that K(Kp Kp), we get the KK principle: Kα KKα (see, in particular, Williamson on this). And what s even worse, (A) implies that if one knows p, one knows that one knows p antecedently to knowing p! That just cannot be right.. An alternative (less interesting) exegesis of Stroud s sceptical argument: Principle (A ) (cf. the previous quotations from Stroud): if one knows that α and knows that one s knowing that α is incompatible with it s being false that β, then one knows that β: (A ) [Kα & K(Kα β)] Kβ Hence: (1) [Kp & K(Kp d)] K d (2) K d [Premise] (3) [Kp & K(Kp d)] [From (1), (2)] (4) K(Kp d) [Premise] (5) Kp [From (3), (4)] Stroud against Austin Austin is read as (in effect) claiming that the sceptic imposes on knowledge an unreasonable or outrageous requirement (41), or (a completely different thought), violating or rejecting the everyday meaning of the word know (57). Austin thought that an inquiry into the sources of the sceptical conclusion as a matter of picking, one by one a mass of seductive (mainly verbal) fallacies (42). Austin s remark is about the sense datum theory, not about scepticism. So the quote suggests that Stroud himself thinks (or, at any rate, thought he certainly doesn t think it now) that scepticism is driven by the sense datum theory. See also the para on 43-4 about Closure which, in conjunction with n.4, suggests that Austin thinks we don t know that other people aren t zombies (that we aren t brains in vats, etc). This is potentially confusing because of Stroud s use of the dreaming hypothesis, which is not incompatible with one s having hands, etc.

5 One dialectical complication is that Austin is not (or not straightforwardly), replying to a sceptical argument (as it might be, an Other Minds version of the sceptical argument in Stroud s ch. 1.) Still less is Austin trying to prove, using only premises that the sceptic would accept, that the sceptical conclusion is false. It s clear from the last few paragraphs that Austin think that there is no justification for supposing that there is another mind communicating with you at all. At any rate, Stroud s main complaint about Austin is that it is possible for a perfectly meaningful expression to be appropriately and justifiably applied in paradigm situations and for its negation to be equally appropriately and justifiably applied in others, even though what is said in each of the positive applications is never true (73), which he supports with Clarke s example of the aircraft spotters. And so (well, maybe) Stroud thinks that Austin is trying to show that we (I) do know that there are other minds, on the basis of certain facts about English usage. (Since the relevant facts about English usage presuppose the existence of other minds, they would be certainly be disputed by a sceptic. Hence the whole strategy seems forlorn in any event.) What are appropriately and justifiably supposed to mean? Note 12 suggests that this is a Gricean idea: the norms governing conversation sometimes prohibit uttering truths ( Glanzberg is either in the pub or the library, The pillar box looks red, etc.), and mandate uttering falsehoods ( He s six feet tall, Everything on the menu is overpriced, (more controversially) There s no beer, etc.). But the spotters example doesn t seem to be a case of this sort (the spotters are ignorant of a crucial fact). In fact, since there appears to be a disanalogy between the spotters case and our own (namely, there s no corresponding crucial fact in our case), the example might be of better use to the anti-sceptic.