IT is frequently taken for granted, both by people discussing logical

Similar documents
Ayer s linguistic theory of the a priori

Quine on the analytic/synthetic distinction

Ayer and Quine on the a priori

WHAT DOES KRIPKE MEAN BY A PRIORI?

A Priori Knowledge: Analytic? Synthetic A Priori (again) Is All A Priori Knowledge Analytic?

Varieties of Apriority

KANT, MORAL DUTY AND THE DEMANDS OF PURE PRACTICAL REASON. The law is reason unaffected by desire.

Philosophical Logic. LECTURE TWO MICHAELMAS 2017 Dr Maarten Steenhagen

Overview. Is there a priori knowledge? No: Mill, Quine. Is there synthetic a priori knowledge? Yes: faculty of a priori intuition (Rationalism, Kant)

Boghossian & Harman on the analytic theory of the a priori

What is an Argument? Validity vs. Soundess of Arguments

4181 ( 10.5), = 625 ( 11.2), = 125 ( 13). 311 PPO, p Cf. also: All the errors that have been made in this chapter of the

WHAT IS HUME S FORK? Certainty does not exist in science.

III Knowledge is true belief based on argument. Plato, Theaetetus, 201 c-d Is Justified True Belief Knowledge? Edmund Gettier

Dumitrescu Bogdan Andrei - The incompatibility of analytic statements with Quine s universal revisability

Moral Psychology

Conceptual Analysis meets Two Dogmas of Empiricism David Chalmers (RSSS, ANU) Handout for Australasian Association of Philosophy, July 4, 2006

Bertrand Russell Proper Names, Adjectives and Verbs 1

Ethical non-naturalism

Analyticity and reference determiners

CHAPTER IV NON-EMPIRICAL CRITIQUE OF A PRIORI AND A POSTERIORI

ON QUINE, ANALYTICITY, AND MEANING Wylie Breckenridge

Constructing the World

Cory Juhl, Eric Loomis, Analyticity (New York: Routledge, 2010).

Is God Good By Definition?

Is anything knowable on the basis of understanding alone?

TWO CONCEPTIONS OF THE SYNTHETIC A PRIORI. Marian David Notre Dame University

Broad on Theological Arguments. I. The Ontological Argument

PHILOSOPHICAL PROBLEMS & THE ANALYSIS OF LANGUAGE

Foreknowledge, evil, and compatibility arguments

What is the Frege/Russell Analysis of Quantification? Scott Soames

Merricks on the existence of human organisms

In Defense of Pure Reason: A Rationalist Account of A Priori Justification, by Laurence BonJour. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press,

Searle vs. Chalmers Debate, 8/2005 with Death Monkey (Kevin Dolan)

Ramsey s belief > action > truth theory.

Comments on Carl Ginet s

Reply to Robert Koons

Philip D. Miller Denison University I

Beyond Symbolic Logic

10 CERTAINTY G.E. MOORE: SELECTED WRITINGS

Putnam: Meaning and Reference

Philosophy 3100: Ethical Theory

Phil/Ling 375: Meaning and Mind [Handout #10]

Summer Preparation Work

Remarks on the philosophy of mathematics (1969) Paul Bernays

Constructing the World

SWINBURNE ON THE EUTHYPHRO DILEMMA. CAN SUPERVENIENCE SAVE HIM?

Que sera sera. Robert Stone

- We might, now, wonder whether the resulting concept of justification is sufficiently strong. According to BonJour, apparent rational insight is

Free will & divine foreknowledge

Grounding and Analyticity. David Chalmers

In The California Undergraduate Philosophy Review, vol. 1, pp Fresno, CA: California State University, Fresno.

Constructing the World, Lecture 4 Revisability and Conceptual Change: Carnap vs. Quine David Chalmers

5 A Modal Version of the

SMITH ON TRUTHMAKERS 1. Dominic Gregory. I. Introduction

Wright on response-dependence and self-knowledge

Can logical consequence be deflated?

In Search of the Ontological Argument. Richard Oxenberg

Glossary (for Constructing the World)

A Defense of the Significance of the A Priori A Posteriori Distinction. Albert Casullo. University of Nebraska-Lincoln

From Transcendental Logic to Transcendental Deduction

KANT S EXPLANATION OF THE NECESSITY OF GEOMETRICAL TRUTHS. John Watling

Review Tutorial (A Whirlwind Tour of Metaphysics, Epistemology and Philosophy of Religion)

Religious belief, hypothesis and attitudes

1/9. The First Analogy

P. Weingartner, God s existence. Can it be proven? A logical commentary on the five ways of Thomas Aquinas, Ontos, Frankfurt Pp. 116.

Reply to Kit Fine. Theodore Sider July 19, 2013

the aim is to specify the structure of the world in the form of certain basic truths from which all truths can be derived. (xviii)

Wittgenstein s Logical Atomism. Seminar 8 PHIL2120 Topics in Analytic Philosophy 16 November 2012

1/5. The Critique of Theology

Does Deduction really rest on a more secure epistemological footing than Induction?

What God Could Have Made

A Posteriori Necessities by Saul Kripke (excerpted from Naming and Necessity, 1980)

Each copy of any part of a JSTOR transmission must contain the same copyright notice that appears on the screen or printed page of such transmission.

Bolzano s definition of analytic propositions

Deontic Logic. G. H. von Wright. Mind, New Series, Vol. 60, No (Jan., 1951), pp

Carnap s notion of analyticity and the two wings of analytic philosophy. Christian Damböck Institute Vienna Circle

Defending A Dogma: Between Grice, Strawson and Quine

The Inscrutability of Reference and the Scrutability of Truth

Aspects of Western Philosophy Dr. Sreekumar Nellickappilly Department of Humanities and Social Sciences Indian Institute of Technology, Madras

Review of Ontology and the Ambitions of Metaphysics by Thomas Hofweber Billy Dunaway University of Missouri St Louis

British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 62 (2011), doi: /bjps/axr026

sentences in which they occur, thus giving us singular propositions that contain the object

Primitive Concepts. David J. Chalmers

Overview of Today s Lecture

On Quine, Grice and Strawson, and the Analytic-Synthetic Distinction. by Christian Green

Self-Evidence and A Priori Moral Knowledge

Philosophy of Mathematics Kant

1 John Hawthorne s terrific comments contain a specifically Talmudic contribution: his suggested alternative interpretation of Rashi s position. Let m

Constructing the World

PHIL 155: The Scientific Method, Part 1: Naïve Inductivism. January 14, 2013

Saul Kripke, Naming and Necessity

PHILOSOPHY OF LANGUAGE

RULES, RIGHTS, AND PROMISES.

Based on the translation by E. M. Edghill, with minor emendations by Daniel Kolak.

Against the Contingent A Priori

On Interpretation. Section 1. Aristotle Translated by E. M. Edghill. Part 1

Think by Simon Blackburn. Chapter 7c The World

PHILOSOPHY OF KNOWLEDGE & REALITY W E E K 7 : E P I S T E M O L O G Y - K A N T

Wittgenstein on the Fallacy of the Argument from Pretence. Abstract

Transcription:

'NECESSARY', 'A PRIORI' AND 'ANALYTIC' IT is frequently taken for granted, both by people discussing logical distinctions1 and by people using them2, that the terms 'necessary', 'a priori', and 'analytic' are equivalent, that they mark not three distinctions, but one. Occasionally an attempt is made3 to establish that two or more of these terms are equivalent. However, it seems to me far from obvious that they are or can be shown to be equivalent, that they cannot be given definitions which enable them to mark important and different distinctions. Whether these different distinctions happen to coincide or not is, as I shall show, a further question, requiring detailed investigation. In this paper, an attempt will be made to show in a brief and schematic4 way that there is an open problem here and that it is extremely misleading to talk as if there were only one distinction. In a large class of cases, whch proposition is expressed by a sentence S will depend on three factors: (a) Which particular things correspond to the referring expressions in S, (b) which concepts correspond to the descriptive expressions, or which properties and relations correspond to them, and (c) the way in which the logical words and constructions used in S are to be understood (e.g. whether 'and' is taken to be defined by the normal truth-table). Whether the proposition so expressed is true or false will, in most of these cases, depend on the further factor (d) How things happen to be in the world, or, which states of affairs actually exist. A Priori/Empirical There are different ways in which the truth-value of a proposition may be discovered. In many cases, one must observe, by means of the senses-aided perhaps by instruments, memory or the reports of other people-particular things in the world, to find out what properties they possess, in which relations they stand to one another, and how they 1 E.g. P. F. Strawson, in Chapter 1of Introduction to Logical Theory. E.g, A. Montefiore, in Chapter 3 of A Modern Introduction to Moral Philoropby. E.g. by A. M. Quinton in I'roceedings of the Aristotelian Socieg 19634. 4 I have given a more detailed discussion of one aspect of the problem in 'Colour Incompatibilities and Analyticity' in ANALYSIS SUPPLEMENT, January 1964.

behave. This way of coming to know things is empirical. If the truthvalue of a proposition is discovered by some other means, e.g. by carrying out a mathematical proof in one's head, or by employing some logical technique, then it is known non-empirical4 or a priori. (These may be taken as equivalent terms.) We have here a distinction between ways of coming to know things; so, since guessing is not a way of coming to how, it does not fit into either half of the distinction. A proposition may be said to be a priori if its truth-value can be known a priori. If it can be known on4 empirically, then it is an empirical (or a posteriori) proposition. If it is possible to discover the truth-value of a proposition either empirically or non-empiri~ally,~ that is, if it can be known in both ways, then it is a priori. If there are any propositions whose truth-value cannot be known at all (see below) then they are neither empirical nor a priori, according to this definition. Among the propositions which can be discovered a priori it is possible to pick out a number of subclasses, depending on exactly how the discovery can be made. Logical Truths and Falsehoods If it is possible to discover the truth-value of a proposition expressed by a sentence S simply by investigating the factor (c), i.e. the meanings of the logical constants employed, taking into account the structure of the sentence (e.g. facts like repetitions of the same descriptive word) and applying purely logical considerations, without taking any account of factors (a), (b), or (d), then the proposition is said to be logical4 true (or false) or true (or false) in virtue of its logical form. By 'logical considerations' are meant ones which are completely topic-neutral insofar as they take no account of specific features of the things or properties referred to by the non-logical words used in S, but only their logical type (e.g. whether they are referring expressions or descriptive expressions, or relational terms, etc.). It follows from the above definitions that all logically true propositions can be known non-empirically, and are therefore a priori. AnalyticISynthetic In some cases (e.g. 'All unmarried uncles are brothers'), although factor (c) alone does not fully determine the truth-value of the proposition expressed by S, the truth-value may nevertheless be discoverable in an a priori manner from this factor plus further information about the defining relations between the non-logical words in S. All that is needed E,g,one can discover a priori that all unmarried uncles are brothers. On the other hand, a person who had not thought out all the logical connections might investigate this empirically by asking every man in turn whether he was an uncle, whether he was married, and whether he was a brother. One who did this would be doing something unnecessary, but not something irrelevant. Students of psychology and the social sciences may be able to think of examples of similar unnecessary investigations.

14 ANALYSIS may be simply a specification of what the relations are between the words, without their actual meaning being specified. (E.g. it may be enough to know that 'uncle' is a descriptive expression which means the same as 'brother or brother-in-law of a parent', and that 'brother-in-law' means the same as 'one who is married to a sister', without knowing what any of these expressions mean-though in that case one will not, of course, know exactly which proposition is expressed by a sentence using these words.) If the truth-value of the proposition expressed by S can be discovered or demonstrated in this way, i.e. using purely logical considerations based on (c) and defining relations1 between nonlogical words in S, then the statement is said to be analytic (analytically true, or analytically false). Any proposition whose truth-value cannot be discovered in this way is said to be gnthetic. For example, if knowledge of its truth-value has to be based on (d), or on non-logical considerations which are peculiar to the specific content or subject matter of the proposition (e.g. propositions about colours, or about geometrical shapes), then the proposition must be synthetic. It follows from the above definitions that every analytic proposition is a priori (its truth-value can be known a priori), but the converse remains problematic. The definition of 'analytic' is intended to be taken in such a way that all propositions which are logically true or logically false are included in the class of analytic propositions. We have thus found a wider and a narrower class of a priori propositions, leaving it open whether there are still more. Necessary/Contingent How things happen to be in the world might have been different. That is to say, the actual states of affairs might not have existed, and others might have existed in their place. There is a green type-writer in front of me, but there might have been a black one, or none at all. If we take full account of all these possibilities we can say that there is a class of possible states of the world, of which only one actually exists. (Or we might talk about a class of possible worlds. This should not be taken to imply that the class would consist of clearly differentiable discrete entities.) If a proposition has a truth-value which depends on factor (d), this means that its truth-value would have been different if some other possible state of affairs had existed in the world, that is, if the things in the world or their properties and behaviour or mutual relations had been different from what they are. In this case we have a contingent proposition. Defining relations need not be synonymy relations, nor need they be relations between verbally definable words. For example, ostensively defined concepts (e.g. the concepts 'red' and 'orange'?) may be indeterminate in a way that can be eliminated by the stipulation that they are to be incompatible. For more on this, see the article referred to in footnote 4, p. 12 supra.

'NECESSARY', 'A PRIORI' AND 'ANALYTIC' 15 On the other hand, if no state of affairs could possibly have existed in which it would have had a different truth-value, then the proposition is a necessay one (i.e. necessarily true, or necessarily false). There is nothing in this definition to indicate the source of the necessity of such a proposition. It may have something to do with the structure of the sentence expressing the proposition being such as to determine the truth-value independently of anything else at all, let alone how things are in the world (e.g. logically true propositions), or it may be that some limits exist to the ways in which properties and relations of objects can co-exist in one state of affairs, and that in particular every combination which would make the sentence S express a false proposition lies beyond these limits. Admittedly, the notion of necessity defined above will not be completely clear until all the possible sources of necessity have been described and classified, just as the notion of analyticity remains unclear insofar as the various kinds have not been described. But the notions are clear enough for the lines of further enquiry to be indicated. In particular, the following problems arise. (1) Are all necessary propositions a priori? Problematic. Since it does not follow immediately from the definition of 'necessary' that a proposition which is necessarily true can be known at all, it does not follow, in particular, that it can be known without the use of the senses to examine particular things in the world. Hence it does not follow that all necessary truths can be known a priori. For example, if a proposition of mathematics which is still unproven is true, e.g. Goldbach's conjecture, then it is necessarily true, since no state of the world could make it false. But it may, in spite of being true, be unprovable, i.e. there may be no general way of establishing that it holds for all possible numbers, even if it does, and even if it can be established for each in turn. If no finite proof is Ascoverable to cover all cases, then the proposition is not knowable, and consequently not a priori. (2)Are all a priori propositions necessary? Yes. This is not problematic, for it is clear that if the truth-value of a proposition can be known a priori, i.e. without using the senses to discover how things happen to be in the world, then the way things happen to be in the world cannot make any difference to its truth-value, and therefore it cannot be contingent, i.e. it must be necessary. (3) Are all a priori propositions analytic? Problematic. This is problematic since it does not follow from the fact that the truth-value of a proposition can be known without the use of the senses to examine particular objects and find out how things happen to be in the world, that its truth-value can be known on the basis of purely logical investigations of factor (c) and the definitional relations between the

16 ANALYSIS non-logical words used to express it. For example, there may be a nonempirical way of acquiring such knowledge by reflecting on the specific nature of certain physical properties (e.g. colours, or shapes). So this question, like question (I), can be answered only after further detailed investigations, if it can be answered at all. (4) Are all analytic propositions a priori? Yes. Since analytic propositions were picked out in terms of a way of dscovering their truth-values which definitely did not involve empirical investigation of how things happen to be in the world, they must all have truth-values which can be discovered a priori. (Note that the fact that empirical investigation may be required to discover exactly what some person means by a sentence S, i.e. which proposition S expresses, is not a reason for saying that it is an empirical proposition, since this applies to all propositions. A proposition is empirical only if after one has learned which proposition is being talked about, e.g. by learning the meanings of the words used to express it, it is still necessary to use empirical means in order to discover its truth-value. It is important to distinguish discovering which proposition is expressed by a sentence S from discovering whether that proposition is true or false.) (5) Are all necessary propositions analytic? Problematic. From the fact that no state of affairs can possibly exist in which the truth-value of a proposition would have been different from what it is, it does not follow obviously that the truth-value of the proposition is fully determined by the factors mentioned in defining 'analytic'. Thus, one might argue that although 'No volume is completely enclosed by three plane surfaces' expresses a necessary truth, it is not obviously analytic, since the truth may depend not on the defining relations between the words used to express it, but on something else, e.g. the 'structure' of space. In any case, the answer to this question follows from the answers to questions (4) and (1). (6) Are all analytic propositions necessary? Yes. This follows from the fact that all analytic propositions are a priori and that all a priori propositions are necessary. Since these questions are not all completely trivial, it cannot be assumed without further argument that 'necessary', 'a priori' and 'analytic' are synonyms, or even that they pick out the same set of propositions. For the same reason, it is confusing to talk about 'the analytic/empirical distinction', as some do, at least until further investigations have shown that the words 'analytic' and 'a priori' as defined above mark distinctions which coincide; though even then it may be misleading if the coincidence is not a trivial matter of definition.