Certainty, probability and abduction: why we should look to C.S. Peirce rather than GoÈ del for a theory of clinical reasoning

Similar documents
Rethinking Knowledge: The Heuristic View

Qualitative and quantitative inference to the best theory. reply to iikka Niiniluoto Kuipers, Theodorus

Class #14: October 13 Gödel s Platonism

ECONOMETRIC METHODOLOGY AND THE STATUS OF ECONOMICS. Cormac O Dea. Junior Sophister

A Scientific Realism-Based Probabilistic Approach to Popper's Problem of Confirmation

PHI2391: Logical Empiricism I 8.0

Philosophy of Science. Ross Arnold, Summer 2014 Lakeside institute of Theology

Theory of Knowledge. 5. That which can be asserted without evidence can be dismissed without evidence. (Christopher Hitchens). Do you agree?

THE ROLE OF COHERENCE OF EVIDENCE IN THE NON- DYNAMIC MODEL OF CONFIRMATION TOMOJI SHOGENJI

From Transcendental Logic to Transcendental Deduction

NICHOLAS J.J. SMITH. Let s begin with the storage hypothesis, which is introduced as follows: 1

Remarks on the philosophy of mathematics (1969) Paul Bernays

1. Introduction Formal deductive logic Overview

Inquiry, Knowledge, and Truth: Pragmatic Conceptions. Pragmatism is a philosophical position characterized by its specific mode of inquiry, and

Paley s Inductive Inference to Design

Beyond Symbolic Logic

Spinoza and the Axiomatic Method. Ever since Euclid first laid out his geometry in the Elements, his axiomatic approach to

Van Fraassen: Arguments Concerning Scientific Realism

Philosophy Epistemology Topic 5 The Justification of Induction 1. Hume s Skeptical Challenge to Induction

Lecture 9. A summary of scientific methods Realism and Anti-realism

Philosophy Courses-1

Detachment, Probability, and Maximum Likelihood

Falsification or Confirmation: From Logic to Psychology

Has Nagel uncovered a form of idealism?

Tools for Logical Analysis. Roger Bishop Jones

IDHEF Chapter 2 Why Should Anyone Believe Anything At All?

Realism and the success of science argument. Leplin:

1/12. The A Paralogisms

Understanding Truth Scott Soames Précis Philosophy and Phenomenological Research Volume LXV, No. 2, 2002

World without Design: The Ontological Consequences of Natural- ism , by Michael C. Rea.

Inductive inference is. Rules of Detachment? A Little Survey of Induction

Sydenham College of Commerce & Economics. * Dr. Sunil S. Shete. * Associate Professor

Philosophy Courses-1

Pictures, Proofs, and Mathematical Practice : Reply to James Robert Brown

Introduction Symbolic Logic

Semantic Foundations for Deductive Methods

2.1 Review. 2.2 Inference and justifications

UNITY OF KNOWLEDGE (IN TRANSDISCIPLINARY RESEARCH FOR SUSTAINABILITY) Vol. I - Philosophical Holism M.Esfeld

Ayer on the criterion of verifiability

Does Deduction really rest on a more secure epistemological footing than Induction?

Intuitive evidence and formal evidence in proof-formation

Proof as a cluster concept in mathematical practice. Keith Weber Rutgers University

Richard L. W. Clarke, Notes REASONING

Boghossian & Harman on the analytic theory of the a priori

The Appeal to Reason. Introductory Logic pt. 1

Is there a good epistemological argument against platonism? DAVID LIGGINS

What is a counterexample?

3 The Problem of Absolute Reality

Naturalized Epistemology. 1. What is naturalized Epistemology? Quine PY4613

Statistical Inference Without Frequentist Justifications

INDUCTIVE AND DEDUCTIVE

Inductive Inference, Rationality and Pragmatism: Peirce and Ajdukiewicz

Alan W. Richardson s Carnap s Construction of the World

Review of "The Tarskian Turn: Deflationism and Axiomatic Truth"

145 Philosophy of Science

DEFEASIBLE A PRIORI JUSTIFICATION: A REPLY TO THUROW

An Alternative View of Schizophrenic Cognition

Jeffrey, Richard, Subjective Probability: The Real Thing, Cambridge University Press, 2004, 140 pp, $21.99 (pbk), ISBN

Verificationism. PHIL September 27, 2011

The Rightness Error: An Evaluation of Normative Ethics in the Absence of Moral Realism

The Greatest Mistake: A Case for the Failure of Hegel s Idealism

ASPECTS OF PROOF IN MATHEMATICS RESEARCH

It Ain t What You Prove, It s the Way That You Prove It. a play by Chris Binge

The Hyperuniverse Program: a critical appraisal

Bayesian Probability

Intro to Science Studies I

A-LEVEL Religious Studies

Experimental Design. Introduction

Constructive Logic, Truth and Warranted Assertibility

The problems of induction in scientific inquiry: Challenges and solutions. Table of Contents 1.0 Introduction Defining induction...

Difference between Science and Religion? - A Superficial, yet Tragi-Comic Misunderstanding

145 Philosophy of Science

Defending the Axioms

In Part I of the ETHICS, Spinoza presents his central

Introductory Kant Seminar Lecture

Difference between Science and Religion? A Superficial, yet Tragi-Comic Misunderstanding...

INTRODUCTION: EPISTEMIC COHERENTISM

On the epistemological status of mathematical objects in Plato s philosophical system

Reason and Explanation: A Defense of Explanatory Coherentism. BY TED POSTON (Basingstoke,

Is Epistemic Probability Pascalian?

Varieties of Apriority

Scientific Realism and Empiricism

Jeu-Jenq Yuann Professor of Philosophy Department of Philosophy, National Taiwan University,

World Religions. These subject guidelines should be read in conjunction with the Introduction, Outline and Details all essays sections of this guide.

SAMPLE. Science and Epistemology. Chapter An uneasy relationship

PHILOSOPHY EPISTEMOLOGY ESSAY TOPICS AND INSTRUCTIONS

Moral Objectivism. RUSSELL CORNETT University of Calgary

In Defense of Radical Empiricism. Joseph Benjamin Riegel. Chapel Hill 2006

Divisibility, Logic, Radical Empiricism, and Metaphysics

CONTENTS A SYSTEM OF LOGIC

Philosophy Epistemology. Topic 3 - Skepticism

Critical Thinking 5.7 Validity in inductive, conductive, and abductive arguments

Presuppositional Apologetics

An Empiricist Theory of Knowledge Bruce Aune

Philosophy of Mathematics Kant

Discussion Notes for Bayesian Reasoning

Introduction to Philosophy

Scientific Progress, Verisimilitude, and Evidence

SAVING RELATIVISM FROM ITS SAVIOUR

Etchemendy, Tarski, and Logical Consequence 1 Jared Bates, University of Missouri Southwest Philosophy Review 15 (1999):

Transcription:

Journal of Evaluation in Clinical Practice, 3, 3, 201±206 Certainty, probability and abduction: why we should look to C.S. Peirce rather than GoÈ del for a theory of clinical reasoning Ross Upshur BA(Hons) MA MSc MD FRCP(C) Senior Resident, Community Medicine Residency Programme, University of Toronto, Canada Correspondence Dr Ross Upshur 18 Herbert Avenue Toronto M4L 3P9 Canada Keywords: clinical reasoning, evidencebased medicine, logic, proof, statistics Accepted for publication: 1 May 1997 Abstract This paper argues that GoÈ del's proof does not provide the appropriate conceptual basis on which to counter the claims of evidence-based medicine. The nature of, and differences between, deductive, inductive and abductive inference are briefly surveyed. The work of the American logician C.S. Peirce is introduced as a possible framework for a theory of clinical reasoning which can ground the claims of both evidence-based medicine and its critics. Introduction In the controversy stimulated by advocates of evidence-based medicine (EBM), the work of the mathematician Kurt GoÈ del has been enlisted in support of those who argue against the claims of EBM. A letter to the editor of the Lancet by J.W. Sleigh (1995) and articles by Sleigh (1997) and Polychronis et al. (1996) in the Journal of Evaluation in Clinical Practice claim that GoÈ del's proof furnishes convincing evidence that the model of clinical reasoning supported by EBM is untenable. In this brief essay, the substance of GoÈ del's proof will be delineated, and its possible relationship to clinical reasoning explored. It will be argued that GoÈ del is not the logician of choice to turn to in seeking to understand clinical reasoning and citing of GoÈ del as support for such a thesis should cease. The Quine- Duhem thesis will be introduced as a means of delimiting what statistical models can achieve. The pragmatism of C. S. Peirce will be introduced to find common ground between the advocates of EBM and clinical common sense. On the use and abuse of GoÈ del I agree with Sleigh's evaluation of GoÈ del's proof. GoÈ del's paper On Formally Undecidable Propositions of Principia Mathematica and related systems I (GoÈ del 1970) is a landmark intellectual achievement of the 20th Century, and perhaps in history. If one takes the time to understand the problem he was # 1997 Blackwell Science 201

L.R. Upshur addressing and works through the intricacies of the logic (or reads the lucid exposition by Nagel & Newman 1958) one comes to two inescapable conclusions: Kurt GoÈ del was a genius and GoÈ del's proof has nothing whatsoever to do with the practice of medicine. GoÈ del's proof concerned issues related to mathematical logic, particularly problems related to the foundations of mathematics and axiomatic systems. To simplify greatly: in the early 20th Century, intense research was focused on the very logical bedrock of mathematical reasoning. Specifically, questions concerning the consistency of fundamental axioms and provability of theorems for all deductive reasoning were being investigated. Bertrand Russell and A. N. Whitehead had embarked on an ambitious project to demonstrate how all mathematics rest upon a finite number of axioms and the inference rules of deductive logic. They developed a useful symbolism for the codification of all mathematical expressions, refining and expanding the work of Frege, Peano and Cantor. The motivation for this project lies partly in the theory of knowledge. Mathematics, though not concerned with demonstrating truths about the physical universe, is none the less considered by many to be the highest, most reliable form of human knowledge. This is because statements can be rigorously and explicitly demonstrated through proofs. Proof, in its technical sense, is a property of formal mathematical systems. In a proof, each step of inference can be checked for validity and the justification for each step assessed. In an axiomatic system like Euclidean geometry, all derived theorems, even of immense complexity, can be traced back to the axioms and inference rules. If the axioms and inference rules can be shown to be consistent, that is every expression rests upon a secure chain of reasoning, then one has a seamless system that guarantees the validity of all expressions. What Russell and Whitehead tried to show is that all mathematics can be derived by such an axiom system, and mathematical logic is the foundation of mathematics. What GoÈ del showed was that this was not possible. To show that an axiom system is consistent is to show that all meaningful expressions are true and provable. In the Russell and Whitehead project, a finite number of axioms were required to demonstrate all mathematical propositions. What GoÈ del showed was that systems with a finite set of axioms will contain expressions in the system that are true but not derivable from the axiom set (i.e. true but not provable). The details of GoÈ del's proof I will leave for readers to discover. From the brief and simplified account so far, I think it is clear that the arguments of GoÈ del, Russell and Whitehead exist on a plane quite removed from meta-analysis and clinical practice guidelines. What those citing GoÈ del say Sleigh states that: If the GoÈ del theorem is applicable, it would suggest that there are (numerous) clinical truths that are unprovable with the usual statistical system of reasoning... The present practice of statistical deduction is a direct application of mathematical logic involving the application of independent truths (the population) and a proposition (the null hypothesis) that is either proved or disproved. (Sleigh 1995, p. 1172) Sleigh then goes on to claim that truth will not be contained in a recipe book, and that clinicians would be well served by applying the art of medicine in the form of clinical common sense. Polychronis and colleagues approvingly cite Sleigh and state:... [I]n simplistic and dogmatic fashion, the advocates of `evidence-based medicine' reject medical determinism and personal clinical experience, but glorify probabilism based on mathematical logic, synthesizing a certainty based on what is statistically probable, which ± in the clinical setting ± does not represent certainty at all... The basic philosophy of the applied science model of medical practice is essentially disprovability and the GoÈ del theorem (which when applied to medicine suggests that there are many clinical truths unprovable through the usual system of reasoning based on mathematical logic) indicates that practitioners who limit themselves only to what is provable will preclude the use of many useful treatments. (Polychronis et al. 1996, p. 2) There are many misunderstandings expressed in the arguments of Sleigh and Polychronis. Mathema- 202 # 1997 Blackwell Science, Journal of Evaluation in Clinical Practice, 3, 3, 201±206

Certainty, probability and abduction tical logic and probability theory, though related, are quite different species and probabilism is not related to mathematical logic in a straightforward way. Mathematical logic is complete in its abstraction. The theorems derived are tautologies, that is, they are formal truths void of content. Statistics are used to estimate parameters when the true values are not known, to lessen the degree of uncertainty about measures and calculate that degree of uncertainty. Probability and certainty are contrasting terms. For the true bite of GoÈ del's proof to pertain to clinical medicine, clinical reasoning would need to be regarded as a formal system with axioms and inference rules. This is clearly an impossible task. Any system of reasoning that relies on empirical inputs cannot be constructed as an axiomatic system and therefore cannot provide proofs. Thus clinicians rely on observation and more or less inductive or abductive methods of reasoning that are probabilistic in nature. One uses probabilistic reasoning in clinical practice daily because of the inherent uncertainties of information and variability of patients. The inferences made in clinical practice are not directly based upon mathematical logic in any meaningful sense, nor are they intended to be because the inputs are physical, psychological and social variables. They may or may not be amenable to being modelled by useful probabilities or mathematical models, but they are never in any straightforward sense based upon mathematical logic. Induction, deduction and abduction We may at once admit that any inference from the particular to the general must be attended with some degree of uncertainty, but this is not the same as to admit that such inference cannot be absolutely rigorous, for the nature and degree of the uncertainty may itself be capable of rigorous expression. (Fisher 1966, p.4) Much of the confusion articulated in the debate concerning EBM centres on the proper types of inference and reasoning used by clinicians and the role of proof. Sleigh and others conflate induction and deduction and claim that neither type of inference can provide certainty. It is here that GoÈdel is invoked as a means of showing the impossibility of deductive certainty. However, as noted above, GoÈ del's proof relates to axiomatic deductive systems of the highest abstraction. GoÈ del need not be invoked because proof is not and cannot be relevant to the practice of medicine. As argued above, medicine cannot be conceived as a closed formal system. Sleigh's assertion that the process of analysis of randomized controlled trials is derived from Whitehead and Russell reasoning is inaccurate and probably incorrect (Sleigh 1997). The target of criticism, if any, should be Sir R. A. Fisher. Induction and deduction are two types of inference that intend towards certainty. Since Hume, the problems of justifying inductive reasoning have been debated vigorously and form a central theme in the modern philosophy of science. Many of the philosophical difficulties relate to concepts of certainty and the nature of explanatory theories. Models and explanations Statistical models are a means of using mathematical techniques to derive order and information from observed data. How and why the data were collected are crucial in some theories of statistical inference to make sense of the data. The theoretical aspects of this have been worked out by Fisher, Pearson and Neyman. The null hypothesis and the error probabilities of the test of that hypothesis (Type 1 and Type 2 errors) are familiar to most, and to many are the sine qua non of statistical inference. 1 In statistical reasoning, it is hoped that randomization and proper experimental design will specify a model sufficiently to render an interpretation of the data as unambiguous as possible. A quotation from Fisher serves to illustrate this point: It is possible and indeed it is all too frequent, for an experiment to be so conducted that no valid estimate of error is available. In such a case the experiment cannot be said, strictly, to be capable of proving anything. Perhaps it should not in this case be called an experiment at all, but 1 For the purposes of this essay, we will set aside considerations of the Bayesian school of statistical reasoning. Those wishing an in-depth account of the controversy between `frequentists' and Bayesians should consult Howson & Urbach (1989). # 1997 Blackwell Science, Journal of Evaluation in Clinical Practice, 3, 3, 201±206 203

L.R. Upshur added merely to the body of experience on which, for lack of anything better, we may have to base our opinions.... if an experiment does allow us to calculate a valid estimate of error, its structure must completely determine the statistical procedure by which this estimate is to be calculated. If this were not so, no interpretation of the data could ever be unambiguous; for we could not be sure that some other equally valid method of interpretation would not lead to a different result. (Fisher 1966, p. 35; italics added for emphasis) Abstractly this is probably the case. One can imagine situations where perfectly specified models exist and the data inputs are precisely measured without bias or error. In this case the results will admit to unambiguous interpretation, even if it is in the negative sense of partitioning off a likelihood (i.e. rendering alternate explanations extremely unlikely, but not impossible). Models are only able to render accurate the processes modelled if they are data rich. In essence, all clinical models will founder to some extent because they will be underdetermined, that is, they will lack sufficient data to specify the model. Human biology is complex and emergent. The concept of complexity needs no further explication in this context. Emergence refers to the unfolding of human events through time in open dynamic systems. Each individual life occurs uniquely in the space-time continuum in a quasi-deterministic manner. The individuality cannot be captured in its fullness by models. However, it may be representative enough to be captured partially by models. This partiality is probably sufficient to support inference. The Quine-Duhem thesis holds that models relating to the empirical world are underdetermined, that is, lack sufficient data for the unequivocal realization of an interpretation. In other words, the data may be amenable to a range of plausible interpretations. When this is the case, as Oreskes et al. (1994) point out, two or more theories or model realizations may be empirically adequate for the data at hand. Choosing between differing but empirically equivalent models relies on `extraevidential considerations like symmetry, simplicity and elegance or personal political or metaphysical preferences' (Oreskes et al. 1994, p. 642). Empirically derived models, no matter how sophisticated or well specified, do not remove judgement from the process of reasoning and evaluating evidence. It is important that theoretical concerns about deductive and inductive inference not cloud descriptions of what occurs in clinical reasoning. Decision analysis and all forms of complex probability models are ideal representations of the process of what goes on in clinical reasoning. They are attempts to depict the process of reasoning in a clear and concise matter and serve as fallible guides to decision making under conditions of uncertainty. They rest on assumptions about the nature of probability and the accuracy of the data. However, the limitations of such mathematical models must always be borne in mind when it comes to their interpretation and use. Any sign of dogmatic certainty is a warning sign indeed. C.S. Peirce and abduction Inferences in clinical medicine made on the basis of statistical models and clinical encounters are characteristically abductive. They should be regarded as tentative statements that the inference holds, is provisionally the case, or pragmatically justifies action. In other words, the model (or clinical data) warrant a belief that x is likely, or may be so. The likelihood admits to variability in terms of the probability of outcome (from impossible to certain). The outer categories of impossibility and certainty relate to violations of known physical laws, logical contradictions and logical truths. Very little in clinical medicine falls under these two categories except for the certainty that if someone is born they will inevitably die. The dispute between the proponents of clinical common sense and evidence-based medicine can likely find common ground in the philosophy of C. S. Peirce. 2 Pierce was an American logician who rigorously pursued a theory of inference called abduction. Abduction is rooted in two philosophical doctrines: realism and pragmatism. Realism here is meant to indicate that there exists a realm of 2 It is of interest to note that Peirce also referred to his philosophy as `critical common-sensism'. See Buchler (1955). 204 # 1997 Blackwell Science, Journal of Evaluation in Clinical Practice, 3, 3, 201±206

Certainty, probability and abduction experience independent of the minds of humans, but which the human intellect can comprehend. In dayto-day terms our patients are real beings with real suffering. Pragmatism in this sense refers to the efforts of the human intellect to apprehend the independent universe through purposive interaction. Experiments and clinical encounters are examples of purposive interactions. Our interactions with the world are tests of the reliability of our reasoning about the world and of the usefulness of our inferences. Hence, they are provisional because they are emergent in the sense outlined above: subject to the effects and disturbances of space-time. Our diagnostic accuracy, whether based on an `algorithm' or a clinical history, will be revealed with the passage of time. The following examples illustrate the differences between inductive, deductive and abductive inferences. The first set of illustrative examples were created by Niiniluoto (1993). Simplified medical examples are given below his examples. Deduction All beans in this bag are white These beans are from this bag Therefore these beans are white All children with fevers have viral infections This child has a fever Therefore this child has a viral infection Induction These beans are from this bag These beans are white Therefore all the beans from this bag are white These children have fevers These children have viral infections Therefore all children with fevers have viral infections Abduction Most of the beans in this bag are white This handful of beans are from this bag Probably most of this handful of beans are white Most children with fevers have viral infections These children have fevers Probably these children have viral infections Abduction is tested by reality through the emergence of time. It is characterized by inference to the best explanation given the data at hand. In the long run, the frequency with which one observes phenomenon probably approximates a true value. However, we are never around to experience the long run, and experiments are not replicated endlessly. Therefore, uncertainty will permeate most of our decisions. This is not a fault of methodology but is an inherent feature of being in the world. The conclusions of the proponents of EBM and their opponents need epistemological tempering. Simply citing an average population value neither deductively nor inductively warrants a certainty or unequivocal interpretation. However, this does not mean that evidence from clinical trials or meta-analysis should be ignored in clinical decision making. Quite the contrary, trial evidence or meta-analytic findings are means of establishing the grounds of particular decisions. They set the test of the experiment in the sense that they indicate a course of action to implement and evaluate. If one does not use them, then grounds for ignoring them should be articulated and evaluated. If clinical common sense is not pragmatically evaluated to the same extent as trial evidence then no possible advance or sharpening of clinical reasoning is possible. If one accepts the Quine-Duhem thesis and adopts a Peircean stance on inference, then there are also no deterministic truths to invoke. In conclusion, the advocates of EBM should not be excused for their epistemological hyperbole. Loose talk of algorithms, paradigm shifts and claims that their critics are arrogant do a disservice to their agenda. However, their critics cannot invoke GoÈ del as support in an alternative theory of clinical reasoning. Such support may come from other philosophical doctrines such as the Quine-Duhem thesis that holds that all models are underdetermined by data and admit to a variety of reasonable interpretations. This implies that circumspection must accompany the use of statistical models in clinical reasoning, and would thus open the discussion on the appropriate theory or theories of knowledge applicable to med- # 1997 Blackwell Science, Journal of Evaluation in Clinical Practice, 3, 3, 201±206 205

L.R. Upshur icine. The philosophy of C. S. Peirce, briefly and superficially introduced here, provides a promising framework in which to develop a theory of clinical reasoning that is both rigorous and probabilistic, yet able to recognize the uncertainties and particularities of day-to-day clinical practice. References Buchler J. (ed.) (1955) Philosophical Writings of Peirce; especially Chapter 19, Critical Common-sensism, pp. 290±301. Dover Publications, New York. Fisher RA. The Design of Experiments. New York: Hafner Publications: 1966 GoÈ del K. On formally undecidable propositions of Principia mathematica and related systems I. In van Heijenoort J., Frege and GoÈ del: Two Fundamental Texts in Mathematical Logic. Cambridge Mass.: Harvard University Press: 1970. Howson C. & Urbach P. (1989) Scientific Reasoning: the Bayesian Approach. Open Court, La Salle. Nagel E. and Newman R. (1958) GoÈdel's Proof. New York: New York University Press Niiniluoto I. Peirce's theory of statistical explanation. In Charles S. Peirce and the Philosophy of Science: Papers from the Harvard Sesquecentennial Congress (ed. C. Moore). Tuscaloosa: The University of Alabama Press, 1993. Oreskes N., Shrader-Frechette K., and Belitz K. (1994) Verification, validation and confirmation of numerical models in the earth sciences. Science 263, 641±646 Polychronis A, Miles A, and Bentley P. (1996) Evidencebased medicine: Reference? Dogma? Neologism? New Orthodoxy? Journal of Evaluation in Clinical Practice 2, 1±3 Sleigh, JW. (1995) Evidence-based medicine and Kurt GoÈ del. Lancet 346, 1172 Sleigh, JW. (1997) Logical limits of randomized controlled trials. Journal of Evaluation in Clinical Practice 3, 145±148. 206 # 1997 Blackwell Science, Journal of Evaluation in Clinical Practice, 3, 3, 201±206