REASONING ABOUT REASONING* TYLER BURGE

Similar documents
In Defense of The Wide-Scope Instrumental Principle. Simon Rippon

Pictures, Proofs, and Mathematical Practice : Reply to James Robert Brown

Does Deduction really rest on a more secure epistemological footing than Induction?

Luminosity, Reliability, and the Sorites

Instrumental reasoning* John Broome

On A New Cosmological Argument

Philosophy 5340 Epistemology. Topic 6: Theories of Justification: Foundationalism versus Coherentism. Part 2: Susan Haack s Foundherentist Approach

TWO VERSIONS OF HUME S LAW

SUPPOSITIONAL REASONING AND PERCEPTUAL JUSTIFICATION

Semantic Entailment and Natural Deduction

Skepticism is True. Abraham Meidan

A solution to the problem of hijacked experience

Buck-Passers Negative Thesis

Philosophical Perspectives, 16, Language and Mind, 2002 THE AIM OF BELIEF 1. Ralph Wedgwood Merton College, Oxford


Philosophy Epistemology. Topic 3 - Skepticism

DEFEASIBLE A PRIORI JUSTIFICATION: A REPLY TO THUROW

Finite Reasons without Foundations

The Problem of Induction and Popper s Deductivism

Can A Priori Justified Belief Be Extended Through Deduction? It is often assumed that if one deduces some proposition p from some premises

Evidential arguments from evil

Hume. Hume the Empiricist. Judgments about the World. Impressions as Content of the Mind. The Problem of Induction & Knowledge of the External World

From Necessary Truth to Necessary Existence

A Note on Straight-Thinking

in defence of an argument for evans s principle 167

HAVE WE REASON TO DO AS RATIONALITY REQUIRES? A COMMENT ON RAZ

Boghossian & Harman on the analytic theory of the a priori

What is the Frege/Russell Analysis of Quantification? Scott Soames

Generic truth and mixed conjunctions: some alternatives

Learning is a Risky Business. Wayne C. Myrvold Department of Philosophy The University of Western Ontario

the negative reason existential fallacy

McDowell and the New Evil Genius

International Phenomenological Society

Varieties of Apriority

2nd International Workshop on Argument for Agreement and Assurance (AAA 2015), Kanagawa Japan, November 2015

Logic: inductive. Draft: April 29, Logic is the study of the quality of arguments. An argument consists of a set of premises P1,

Stout s teleological theory of action

Coordination Problems

REASONS AND ENTAILMENT

ILLOCUTIONARY ORIGINS OF FAMILIAR LOGICAL OPERATORS

What would count as Ibn Sīnā (11th century Persia) having first order logic?

Justified Inference. Ralph Wedgwood

PHILOSOPHY OF LANGUAGE AND META-ETHICS

A Priori Bootstrapping

SKEPTICISM, ABDUCTIVISM, AND THE EXPLANATORY GAP. Ram Neta University of North Carolina, Chapel Hill

Avoiding the Dogmatic Commitments of Contextualism. Tim Black and Peter Murphy. In Grazer Philosophische Studien 69 (2005):

In Defense of Radical Empiricism. Joseph Benjamin Riegel. Chapel Hill 2006

Keywords precise, imprecise, sharp, mushy, credence, subjective, probability, reflection, Bayesian, epistemology

Exercise Sets. KS Philosophical Logic: Modality, Conditionals Vagueness. Dirk Kindermann University of Graz July 2014

Philosophy 5340 Epistemology Topic 4: Skepticism. Part 1: The Scope of Skepticism and Two Main Types of Skeptical Argument

Received: 30 August 2007 / Accepted: 16 November 2007 / Published online: 28 December 2007 # Springer Science + Business Media B.V.

Transmission Failure Failure Final Version in Philosophical Studies (2005), 126: Nicholas Silins

A Model of Decidable Introspective Reasoning with Quantifying-In

Module 5. Knowledge Representation and Logic (Propositional Logic) Version 2 CSE IIT, Kharagpur

Philosophy Epistemology Topic 5 The Justification of Induction 1. Hume s Skeptical Challenge to Induction

Logic is the study of the quality of arguments. An argument consists of a set of

Did Jesus Commit a Fallacy?

Semantic Foundations for Deductive Methods

MULTI-PEER DISAGREEMENT AND THE PREFACE PARADOX. Kenneth Boyce and Allan Hazlett

There are two common forms of deductively valid conditional argument: modus ponens and modus tollens.

EXTERNALISM AND THE CONTENT OF MORAL MOTIVATION

Higher-Order Approaches to Consciousness and the Regress Problem

1.2. What is said: propositions

The Inscrutability of Reference and the Scrutability of Truth

TWO CONCEPTIONS OF THE SYNTHETIC A PRIORI. Marian David Notre Dame University

CRUCIAL TOPICS IN THE DEBATE ABOUT THE EXISTENCE OF EXTERNAL REASONS

Reply to Kit Fine. Theodore Sider July 19, 2013

Portfolio Project. Phil 251A Logic Fall Due: Friday, December 7

Bayesian Probability

Comment on Robert Audi, Democratic Authority and the Separation of Church and State

Russellianism and Explanation. David Braun. University of Rochester

AN EPISTEMIC PARADOX. Byron KALDIS

Bayesian Probability

Philosophy 12 Study Guide #4 Ch. 2, Sections IV.iii VI

VARIETIES OF SKEPTICISM. Jonathan Vogel Amherst Collge and Harvard University

Conditionals II: no truth conditions?

Noncognitivism in Ethics, by Mark Schroeder. London: Routledge, 251 pp.

Should We Assess the Basic Premises of an Argument for Truth or Acceptability?

British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 62 (2011), doi: /bjps/axr026

Externalism and a priori knowledge of the world: Why privileged access is not the issue Maria Lasonen-Aarnio

Saving the Substratum: Interpreting Kant s First Analogy

Review: The Objects of Thought, by Tim Crane. Guy Longworth University of Warwick

What is Good Reasoning?

KNOWING AGAINST THE ODDS

Backwards induction in the centipede game

Trying to Kill the Dead: De Dicto and De Re Intention in Attempted Crimes. By Gideon Yaffe. Introduction

Knowledge is Not the Most General Factive Stative Attitude

General Philosophy. Dr Peter Millican,, Hertford College. Lecture 4: Two Cartesian Topics

IS EVIDENCE NON-INFERENTIAL?

Bootstrapping and The Bayesian: Why The Conservative is Not Threatened By Weisberg s Super-Reliable Gas Gauge

An Inferentialist Conception of the A Priori. Ralph Wedgwood

Right-Making, Reference, and Reduction

ON WRITING PHILOSOPHICAL ESSAYS: SOME GUIDELINES Richard G. Graziano

Is rationality normative?

Validity of Inferences *

In Epistemic Relativism, Mark Kalderon defends a view that has become

ROBUSTNESS AND THE NEW RIDDLE REVIVED. Adina L. Roskies

Chapter 5: Ways of knowing Reason (p. 111)

Epistemic Contextualism as a Theory of Primary Speaker Meaning

Introducing Our New Faculty

Transcription:

REASONING ABOUT REASONING* Mutual expectations cast reasoning into an interesting mould. When you and I reflect on evidence we believe to be shared, we may come to reason about each other's expectations. I develop expectations about your expectations, expecting them to be expectations about mine. The double-mirror aspect of such situations suggests that there may in some sense be no stopping. Of course, we do run out of expectations. But to some this seems to result merely from inability to understand sufficiently complicated nestings, rather than from lack of reason to acquire each of infinitely many nested beliefs. Limitless nesting of psychological "contents" has played an important role in accounts of communication, convention and related topics. But there have been few attempts to analyze precisely how the infinity of contents might be generated. An exception is David Lewis' account in Convention pp. 52-57. This account contains significant errors which are easily overlooked because of the complexity and subtlety of the subject matter. Fortunately, they are also easily corrected, at least within the general framework of the account. The purpose of this note is to identify and correct the oversights. A key to the discussion is the term 'have reason to believe.' The term is used by Lewis in such a way that if a person has reason to believe something and does not already believe it, he would be extremely irrational to disbelieve it and he should come to believe it with only a little reflection (pp. 53, 59, 63). Having reason is understood to vary with one's inductive standards and background information. 651

The reasons normally "had" in the situations we shall be discussing are inductive reasons. They therefore admit of uncertainty. In what follows I shall sometimes speak of one's reason to believe r as making r probable for one to a certain specified degree. It is unimportant to my purpose whether inductive reasoning be actually, or even ideally, explicable in terms of numerical probabilities. The appeal to probability is merely a way of making applications of the following point picturesque: When one has reason to be less than fully certain about each of a plural number of epistemically independent theses the assumption of each of which is needed to justify a conclusion, one's certainty about the conclusion (relative to those assumptions) should be less than one's certainty about any one of the assumptions. It is common to assume that if numerical probabilities are assigned, the probability of the conclusion (relative to the reasons for believing it) is no more than the product of the probabilities assigned to those reasons, assuming the reasons independent, x Lewis illustrates his theory of interpersonal reasoning by reference to a particular case. We imagine that state of affairs A is any sort of evidence for the conclusion that we will meet~at a given spot tomorrow - for example, a signal of some kind. I shall call the state of affairs of our meeting at that spot and time state of affairs B. Lewis makes the following assumptions, and I shall adopt them: (1) You and I have reason to believe that some state of affairs A holds. (2) Each of us is such that if he had reason to believe that A held, then he would thereby have reason to believe that you and I have reason to believe that A held. (3) Each of us is such that if he had reason to believe that A held, then he would thereby have reason to believe that B would hold. (B) Each of us has reason to believe that if he would have reason to believe B held granted that he had reason to believe A held, then the other would have reason to believe B held granted that he had reason to believe A held. Lewis claims that these four premises imply 652 (4) Each of us is such that if he had reason to believe that A he!d, then he would thereby have reason to believe that each of us has reason to believe that B would hold.

He also claims that they imply REASONING ABOUT REASONING (5) Each of us is such that if he had reason to believe that A held, then he would thereby have reason to believe that each of us would have reason to believe that the other has reason to believe that B would hold and so on, with indefinitely many iterations in the consequent) These claims are mistaken. We can most easily bring out why by representing simplified versions of the relevant sentences in symbolic, abbreviated form: (1') R(I,A) (2') R(I,A) -* R(I,[R(I,A)] ) & R(I,[R(Y,A)] ) (3') R(I,A) --> R(I,B) (B') R(I [R(I,A) --} R(I,B). -~.R(Y,A) ~ R(Y,B)] ) (4') R(I,A) -~. R(I [R(I,B)] ) & R(I, [R(Y,a)]) 'R' stands for 'have reason to believe'; 'I,' for T; 'Y,' for 'you.' The brackets are intended for ease of reading. The arrow stands for 'if... then (thereby)...' - except in its occurrence as main connective in the content clause of (B'), where it stands for ordinary 'if... then...': the difference in the meaning here can be slurred without harm. I assume that the analog of modus ponens holds for the arrow. We do not need to give a semantics for the notation. Whereas the argument from (1') through (4') represents only the first person point of view, (1)-(4) incorporate an analogous argument from the second person viewpoint. Our remarks will apply (by analogy) to both arguments. Using (1') and (3') we can detach (a) R(I,B). To get the first conjunct in the consequent of (4'), we need the iteration principle (6') R(I,Ci -'- R(I, [R(I,C)]) where 'C' stands for any content clause. Let us grant (6') for the present. This together with (a) gives us (b) R(I, [R(I,B)]). Using (1') and (2') we can detach and simplify to (c) R(I, [R(Y,A)]). Now my reason described in (c) is inductive. Suppose it has a probability strength of 65%. My reason described in (B') is also 653

inductive. Suppose it has a probability strength of 66%. Using (B') and (3'), one is tempted to try a sort of detachment that would yield (d) R(I, [R(Y,A) -~ R(Y,B)] ). But such a detachment would be within the scope of 'R' - within the first person point of view. And so far, we have assumed only (3'), not that I have reason to believe (3'). Let us grant the following for the sake of the argument: (7') R(I,C) & (R(I,C) -+ R(I,D)). ~ R(I,IR(I,C) ~ R(I,D)] ) where 'C' and 'D' stand for any content clauses. The idea is that if I have reason to believe some state of affairs obtains, and that state of affairs gives me reason to believe that another state of affairs obtains, then I have reason to believe that this evidential or reasongiven relationship holds for me. With (7'), (1') and (3') we can derive (e) R(I, [R(I,A) ~ R(I,B)] ). The status of the reason described in (e) is a deep problem. Hume argued that such reasons were clearly not deductive and that if they were inductive, then induction could not be justified. I do not want to embroil myself in this matter. But I shall suppose, what seems plausible, that my reason described in (e) has a probability strength of less than 100%. We are now in a position to diagnose the sources of Lewis' mistake. My reason in (B') has a probability strength of only 66%, and any premises l conjoin with that reason may carry their own degrees of uncertainty. Unless such premises are 100% probable (or epistemically derivative), the conjunction will have less strength than any of the conjuncts. Thus we may derive (d) from (B') and (e) only if the product of the probability strengths of my reasons - those reasons described in (B') and (e) is sufficiently high. If it is, we obtain (d). The same point applies in conjoining (d) and (c) to get (f) R(I, [R(Y,B)] ). (This derivation is more clearly problematic than that of (d) because its interpretation does not hinge on the Humean issues surrounding (e).) In fact, on our assumptions about probability strength in (c) and (B'), we cannot derive (f). For the reason described in (d) has a strength of less than 66%; that in (c) has a strength of 65%; the 654

REASONING ABOUT REASONING reasons are (reasonably) independent epistemically; so their product is less than 50%. In ordinary circumstances, this situation might be regarded as one in which I lack the reason described in (f). If my inductive support were strong enough to justify (f), of course, we could conjoin (f) with (b), and thereby have (4'). The moral is that the truth of (4) depends on the combined strength of our reasons regarding three matters: the other's appreciation of the evidence ((2')), the other's inductive standards and background information ((B')), and our own inductive reasons ((7') and actually (6') as well). How will iteration affect matters? (1), (2), (4) and (B) (or analogs, cf. note 2) do not entail (5) for the same reason that the previous alleged entailment failed. But if (B'), (7') and (c) are strong enough to produce (4'), then by relying on (4') (and an analog of (B') which is of at least equal probability strength), one can derive the appropriate representation of (5) - on one condition. The reasons generated by (6') and (7') must not become weaker as these principles are reapplied. This condition seems no less plausible than the iteration principles themselves. Thus Lewis' entailment claims can be corrected by making explicit the principles (6') and (7'), and by requiring that the combined reasons cited in the premises be sufficiently strong. Of course, even this account might be doubted. Not all epistemologies would accept (6') and (7'). It might be thought that one could have first-order reasons but lack the information or subtlety to have higher-order reasons. Moreover, there is the bothersome Hume, who had inductive reasons to believe the sorts of things everyone else believes, but who doubted that he had those reasons. On Lewis' account of 'have reason to believe' (accepting (6') and (7')), we would have to conclude that Hume was "extremely irrational." So doing would be a mite severe. Whether this difficulty is best accommodated by minor refmements in the interpretation of'have reason to believe' or by important changes in the iteration principles, I leave as an open question. UNIVERSITY OF CALIFORNIA, LOS ANGELES LOS ANGELES, CALIFORNIA 90024 USA 655

NOTES I am indebted to Gregory Kavka for remarks on an earlier version. The assumption of the independence of justifications must be seen as an idealization. It has been argued that it is an unfruitful and fundamentally misleading idealization. Since our appeal to probability strength is purely heuristic, this issue can be set aside. (1)-(5) are formed from like-numbered sentences in Convention (Harvard University Press, Cambridge, 1969), pp. 52-53, by replacing 'indicates' in the latter sentences by Lewis' definition of the term. A indicates to someone x that --- if and only if, if x had reason to believe that A held, x would thereby have reason to believe that ---. (B) is the relevant instance of Lewis' assumption that you and I have reason to believe that we share the same background information and inductive standards, at least nearly enough so that A will indicate the same things to both of us. Actually Lewis claims that instances of this assumption would be needed to get (5) and more eomphcated iterations. Thus it is (1)-(3) and relevant analogues of (B) which are alleged to imply (5). Ignoring this point will not be crucial to our criticism. 656