Against Monism. 1. Monism and pluralism. Theodore Sider

Similar documents
Sider, Hawley, Sider and the Vagueness Argument

No Physical Particles for a Dispositional Monist? Baptiste Le Bihan Université de Rennes 1. Draft (Forthcoming in Philosophical Papers)

Monism, Emergence, and Plural Logic

Maximality and Microphysical Supervenience

Merricks on the existence of human organisms

Against Lewisian Modal Realism From a Metaontological Point of View. Tora Koyama, Osaka University, Japan

Compositional Pluralism and Composition as Identity 1. Kris McDaniel. Syracuse University

Counterparts and Compositional Nihilism: A Reply to A. J. Cotnoir

Published in Analysis 61:1, January Rea on Universalism. Matthew McGrath

abstract: What is a temporal part? Most accounts explain it in terms of timeless

Compositional Pluralism and Composition as Identity

Why Four-Dimensionalism Explains Coincidence

The Evil of Death: What Can Metaphysics Contribute?

Bare Particulars. Theodore Sider Philosophical Perspectives 20 (2006),

Mereological Nihilism and the Special Arrangement Question

Real Metaphysics. Essays in honour of D. H. Mellor. Edited by Hallvard Lillehammer and Gonzalo Rodriguez-Pereyra

Modal Realism, Counterpart Theory, and Unactualized Possibilities

Recent Work on Ontological Pluralism

Against the Vagueness Argument TUOMAS E. TAHKO ABSTRACT

1. Introduction. Against GMR: The Incredulous Stare (Lewis 1986: 133 5).

SIMON BOSTOCK Internal Properties and Property Realism

There might be nothing: the subtraction argument improved

Postscript to Plenitude of Possible Structures (2016)

A note on science and essentialism

pieces of wood and several screws. Then I screwed the pieces of wood together. In doing so, I

Defending Contingentism in Metaphysics

THERE ARE NO THINGS THAT ARE MUSICAL WORKS

Kantian Humility and Ontological Categories Sam Cowling University of Massachusetts, Amherst

Postmodal Metaphysics

Comments on Van Inwagen s Inside and Outside the Ontology Room. Trenton Merricks

Eliminativism and gunk

Framing the Debate over Persistence

Against Vague and Unnatural Existence: Reply to Liebesman

Under contract with Oxford University Press Karen Bennett Cornell University

BOOK REVIEWS. Duke University. The Philosophical Review, Vol. XCVII, No. 1 (January 1988)

Statues and Lumps: A Strange Coincidence?

Humean Supervenience: Lewis (1986, Introduction) 7 October 2010: J. Butterfield

Quality and Structure. Shamik Dasgupta. Forthcoming in Current Controversies in Metaphysics (Routledge), edited by Elizabeth Barnes.

The World and Truth About What is Not

From: Vance, Chad (2013). In Defense of the New Actualism (dissertation), University of Colorado Boulder. 2.2 Truthmakers for Negative Truths

Is the Existence of the Best Possible World Logically Impossible?

DO WE NEED A THEORY OF METAPHYSICAL COMPOSITION?

Mereological Nihilism and Theoretical Unification

Reply to Eli Hirsch. Theodore Sider July 19, 2013

Metametaphysics. New Essays on the Foundations of Ontology* Oxford University Press, 2009

Armstrongian Particulars with Necessary Properties

A Review of Neil Feit s Belief about the Self

Restricted Composition

Structural realism and metametaphysics

Intro to Ground. 1. The idea of ground. 2. Relata. are facts): F 1. More-or-less equivalent phrases (where F 1. and F 2. depends upon F 2 F 2

A Spatial Approach to Mereology

24.09 Minds and Machines spring an inconsistent tetrad. argument for (1) argument for (2) argument for (3) argument for (4)

The Problem of Identity and Mereological Nihilism. the removal of an assumption of unrestricted mereological composition, and from there a

Putnam: Meaning and Reference

Entity Grounding and Truthmaking

ARMSTRONGIAN PARTICULARS WITH NECESSARY PROPERTIES *

Grounding and Analyticity. David Chalmers

A version of this paper appears in Australasian Journal of Philosophy 93 (2015), pp THE RIGHT STUFF. Ned Markosian

SAVING THE SHIP* JOHN BIRO University of Florida ABSTRACT

Getting Priority Straight

THE TWO-DIMENSIONAL ARGUMENT AGAINST MATERIALISM AND ITS SEMANTIC PREMISE

Material Coincidence and the Indiscernibility Problem Eric T. Olson

How Successful Is Naturalism?

Are the Questions of Metaphysics More Fundamental Than Those of Science? Alyssa Ney. Draft of November 1, 2017

Intrinsic Properties Defined. Peter Vallentyne, Virginia Commonwealth University. Philosophical Studies 88 (1997):

Vagueness in sparseness: a study in property ontology

Chapter Six. Putnam's Anti-Realism

Resemblance Nominalism and counterparts

Toward a Commonsense Answer to the Special Composition Question

Abstract: In this paper, I propose a way to modify panpsychism in order to avoid its notorious combination problem.

Revelation, Humility, and the Structure of the World. David J. Chalmers

Simplicity and Why the Universe Exists

Taking monism seriously

Right-Making, Reference, and Reduction

a0rxh/ On Van Inwagen s Argument Against the Doctrine of Arbitrary Undetached Parts WESLEY H. BRONSON Princeton University

A Cartesian argument against compositional nihilism

Common Sense in Favor of Mereological Nihilism?

BEGINNINGLESS PAST AND ENDLESS FUTURE: REPLY TO CRAIG. Wes Morriston. In a recent paper, I claimed that if a familiar line of argument against

Constitution 1 Theodore Sider

Commentary. David Lewis. Oxford: Blackwell, 1986* Louis derosset

Platonism, Alienation, and Negativity

Getting priority straight

Comments on Saul Kripke s Philosophical Troubles

Against the No-Miracle Response to Indispensability Arguments

Reply to Kit Fine. Theodore Sider July 19, 2013

Truth and Molinism * Trenton Merricks. Molinism: The Contemporary Debate edited by Ken Perszyk. Oxford University Press, 2011.

Composition. Question: Did you say that there were some bigger triangles COMPOSED of littler ones?

Logical Realism and the Metaphysics of Logic Michaela McSweeney Draft please do not cite without permission

Possible Worlds I: Modal Realism

PRESENTISM AND PERSISTENCE

Merricks, Causation, and Objects

Scrying an Indeterminate World

Why Counterpart Theory and Three-Dimensionalism are Incompatible. Suppose that God creates ex nihilo a bronze statue of a

542 Book Reviews. Department of Philosophy. University of Houston 513 Agnes Arnold Hall Houston TX USA

MINIMAL TRUTHMAKERS DONNCHADH O CONAILL AND TUOMAS E. TAHKO

The Cost of Truthmaker Maximalism

Diagnosing Verbal Disputes: The Case of Ontology

Prioritizing Platonism Kelly Trogdon & Sam Cowling Penultimate version; forthcoming in Philosophical Studies

Published in Mind, 2000, 109 (434), pp

Some Good and Some Not so Good Arguments for Necessary Laws. William Russell Payne Ph.D.

Transcription:

Against Monism Theodore Sider Analysis 67 (2007): 1 7. Final version at: http://www.blackwell-synergy.com/ toc/anal/67/293 Abstract Jonathan Schaffer distinguishes two sorts of monism. Existence monists say that only one object exists: The World. Priority monists admit the existence of The World s parts, but say that their features are derivative from the properties of The World. Both have trouble explaining the features of statespace, the set of possibilities available to The World. 1. Monism and pluralism Let s agree to take ontology seriously. We must then take monism seriously. According to monism, there exists only one (nonabstract 1 ) object: the entire world. 2 To be sure, monism clashes with what we ordinarily think and say. But so do other revisionary ontologies that we ought to take seriously. Consider nihilism, the thesis that the only objects that exist are the partless elementary particles of physics. 3 Although the nihilist says that tables and chairs do not exist, she is quick to add that there do exist particles arranged tablewise, particles arranged chairwise, and so on. 4 Here are three reasons to take nihilism seriously, despite its revisionary nature. (1) Nihilism is not refuted by mere perception. If there were no tables, only particles arranged tablewise, Thanks to Dave Chalmers, John Hawthorne, Jonathan Schaffer (whose paper From Nihilism to Monism sparked my interest in the topic), and especially Frank Arntzenius for discussion of the connection between fundamental properties and statespaces. 1 I have no particular definition of abstract in mind; but I mean to count spacetime points, tropes, etc., as concrete. 2 Recent literature on monism and related topics includes Hawthorne and Cortens (1995); Albert (1996); Horgan and Potrč (2000, 2002); Schaffer (2007, Forthcoming). 3 Cian Dorr (2005, 2002) defends nihilism; Trenton Merricks (2001) and Peter van Inwagen (1990) defend related views. 4 van Inwagen (1990). Particles arranged tablewise is a plural referring expression, to be distinguished from singular expressions such as aggregate of particles arranged chairwise and group of particles arranged chairwise. The nihilist rejects the existence of aggregates and groups (construed as being concrete, anyway). 1

our sensory experience would be the same. (2) Nihilism is not refuted by science. Evidence that leads chemists to posit molecules and economists to posit economies is just as well accounted for by the more cautious posits of the nihilist: particles arranged molecule-wise, particles arranged economy-wise. (3) Nihilists can count ordinary and scientific sentences as being in some sense correct, even if they are not strictly true. For instance, there exists a table is correct iff there exist particles arranged tablewise. 5 Like nihilism, monism is a revisionary theory of the reality that underlies the appearances of ordinary thought and science. Like nihilism, monism is consistent with both perception and science. Suppose that, as we would ordinarily say, there exists a person working at a desk. The monist will say instead that The World has a certain property in virtue of which it is correct to say that there exists a person working at a desk. And when the chemist says that matter is composed of molecules, this is correct, if not strictly true, because The World has an appropriate property. Jonathan Schaffer (2007) construes these properties adverbially: The World is tabley-here and chair-ey there. 6 Neither mere perception nor scientific experiment will tell us whether tables and chairs and we ourselves really exist, or whether there is only The World with its properties of being tabley-here, chairey-there, and personey-there. I take monism seriously enough to give arguments against it. All fundamental properties, for the monist, are properties of the entire world. 7 (They must be, for there are no other objects in the monist s ontology to have fundamental properties.) My arguments turn on this fact. 8 What is intuitively wrong with monism is that it takes the fundamental facts to be facts about the whole world. When an object has an intrinsic property, for instance a certain shape, that seems to be a fact just about that object, not about the rest of the world. When two things are separated by a certain distance, that is of course not a fact about either object individually, but it seems to be a 5 Correctness might be held to suffice for truth in ordinary linguistic contexts; see Horgan and Potrč (2000); van Inwagen (1990, 10 11). 6 See also Hawthorne and Cortens (1995), who appeal to adverbial modification in defense of the view that no objects exist. I construe this talk as not presupposing the real existence of regions of space or spacetime; otherwise the view isn t really monism. The monist might instead appeal to Josh Parson s (2004) distributional properties. I discuss this issue at length in a forthcoming paper. 7 By fundamentality and naturalness I have in mind Lewis s (1986, 59 69) picture. 8 Thus, my arguments apply also to what Schaffer (2007, Forthcoming) calls priority monism, according to which, despite the existence of smaller objects, only The World has fundamental properties. (My monism is what Schaffer calls existence monism.) 2

fact just about the two; the fact doesn t bring in any other objects. Now, there may be some facts that are much more holistic than this, for instance facts about quantum-entangled systems. 9 But monism goes too far; it makes every fundamental fact maximally holistic. 10 Only if we are pluralists and posit a plurality of sub-world entities can we avoid this consequence. One could just leave the argument there, but I prefer not to flat-footedly insist on premises about the nature of fundamental properties. 11 I want to push the argument further in three ways, two involving possibility, one involving intrinsicality. 2. Combinatorial possibility Consider a world containing just a single computer screen with a 4x4 pixel resolution. Each pixel can be on or off. Since there are 16 pixels, and there are two states for each pixel, 2 16 states are possible for the entire screen. 12 The existence of this statespace is common ground between monists and pluralists. But only the pluralist can give a satisfying account of why the statespace has 2 16 members. The pluralist can say: the statespace has 2 16 members because i) there are 16 pixels, each of which has two available fundamental states; ii) the fundamental states of the system include only the states of the individual pixels; and iii) the possibilities for the entire system are generated combinatorially from the entities in the system and the fundamental states those entities can inhabit. The monist can tell no such story. For the monist, the fundamental properties are the members of the statespace itself: the 2 16 maximally specific properties of the entire screen. These properties are not generated combinatorially from more fundamental pixel-properties. Why, then, are there exactly 2 16 of them? Relatedly, consider screens with different numbers, n, of pixels. The statespace always has 2 n members. What accounts for this regularity? The pluralist has an easy answer; the monist does not. Relatedly, no world of this sort will ever have a statespace with a cardinality that is not a power of 2. Why are statespaces with the other cardinalities 9 Schaffer (2007, Forthcoming) argues for monism by appeal to entangled systems. 10 Even in quantum mechanics, some states of particles charge, for instance aren t holistic. Also, quantum mechanics per se does not require that all particles are entangled. 11 Compare Lewis s (1986, 202 204) argument from temporary intrinsics. 12 Anti-haeccitists will think that there are fewer members of the statespace, but the argument is otherwise unaffected. 3

missing? Again, only the pluralist can answer the question. Facts about the size of the statespace aren t the only facts that the pluralist is in a better position to explain. There are also facts about the structure of the statespace. Suppose our task is to describe the statespace. To say only that there are 2 16 points in it would leave out all sorts of information about the natural groupings of points in the statespace. Consider, for instance, the subset of the statespace consisting of the points in which exactly one pixel is lit. The members of this subset go together in a way that the members of the following subset do not: { { 1,1, 2,4, 3,4 }, {}, { 2,3 } } Such natural groupings can be readily explained by the pluralist; they emerge from the natural groupings of the most fundamental facts, facts concerning which pixels are lit. If I know that the facts about the pixels are fundamental, and I know some general facts about similarity, then I have enough information to tell you which subsets of the statespace go together. The general facts about similarity I have in mind would likewise tell me that if I had a 8x8 array of pixels, then the set of points in the statespace in which a single pixel is lit would also count as a natural subset of the statespace. For the monist, the facts about which subsets of the statespace go together must be brute. When faced with the statespace of the 4x4 screen, the set S 1 of single-pixel-lit states is a natural subset. When faced with the statespace of the 8x8 screen, the set S 2 of single-pixel-lit states will be a natural grouping. There are patterns here that ought to be explained. The single-pixel-lit states always go together. But why? The monist cannot give the obvious answer, that this pattern in the natural groupings is generated by general facts about naturalness and the fact that the single-pixel states are fundamental. 3. Haecceitistic possibility Consider a two-pixel world nothing else exists. And each of the two pixels may be either on or off. Some people haecceitists think that a world in which pixel A is off and pixel B is on is a different world from the world in which pixel A is on and pixel B is off. If haecceitism is true, the statespace would have four members (both on, both off, A on/b off, A off/b on). Whether the statespace has four members might matter. For instance, if there were certain probabilistic laws governing the system, the claim that there 4

are four members in the statespace might be part of an explanation appealing to a limited principle of indifference of why it s more likely to have: one pixel off and one on, than to have: each pixel off. Now, it seems to me that the monist cannot say that the statespace of the two-pixel system has four members. The monist, I think, must say that there are just three states in the statespace: both-off, both-on, and one-off-and-one-on. Intuitively, to distinguish two states in the statespace, each a one-off-one-on state, would require positing the individual pixels. How else would these states differ, other than by a permutation of the properties had by the pixels? As I say, it seems true that the monist cannot distinguish two one-off-one-on states. My best argument for this appeals to the following principle: Fundamental states are qualitative Fundamental states involve the instantiation of purely qualitative properties and relations. If a fundamental state involves one object, that state is the instantiation of a qualitative property by that object. If a fundamental state involves more than one object, that state is the instantiation of a qualitative relation by those objects. I understand qualitative properties and relations as those that must be isomorphically distributed in duplicate possible worlds. Given this principle, the monist must admit that the states of the two-particle system involve the instantiation of qualitative properties by The World. But if the monist distinguishes two properties X and Y of the entire system, corresponding to what the pluralist would call, A-on/B-off and A-off/B-on, then X and Y cannot be qualitative, because a possible world in which The World has property X would be a duplicate of a possible world in which The World has property Y. (Recall the symmetry of the world nothing exists in the world other than the two pixels.) 4. Intrinsicality Why posit multiple objects? My argument so far has been: to yield an attractive theory of the statespace. My final argument will be: to yield an attractive definition of intrinsicality. We ordinarily take it that some pairs of objects are perfect duplicates and others are not (any two electrons are exactly alike; no two people, not even twins, are exactly alike), and that some properties are intrinsic and others are 5

not (having unit negative charge is intrinsic; being within five feet of a proton is not). Now, the monist won t take statements like these at face value the monist thinks that there don t really exist electrons. Still, the monist will want to say that such claims are correct ; they have the same status as do other claims about the world that we ordinarily make, for instance there exist some tables and chairs, there exist electrons, and so on. So: it s common ground that we want to make some sense of the notions of intrinsicality and duplication. David Lewis (1986, 61 62) suggested the following definitions: Definition of duplication objects are duplicates iff their parts may be put in one-one correspondence preserving the perfectly natural (fundamental) properties and relations Definition of intrinsicality a property is intrinsic iff it can never differ between a pair of possible duplicates These definitions, or definitions a lot like them, 13 are, I think, the best that have been proposed. But they are not available to the monist. If the monist takes Lewis s definitions at face value, they apply only to properties of The World, since that s the only object there is. We thereby get the correct result that the natural properties of The World are intrinsic; but no other facts of intrinsicality are generated. There seems to be no way to get from the fact that the monist s World-properties are all intrinsic to any facts about the correctness of ordinary judgments of intrinsicality, for instance that the property of having unit negative charge is intrinsic. Suppose, on the other hand, that the monist does not take Lewis s definitions at face value, but instead takes them in whatever spirit ordinary claims about the world are to be taken (as being merely correct rather than true). In this spirit, the monist is free to speak of properties of electrons and the like. But Lewis s definitions still won t generate the desired facts, because the monist ought to say even in the spirit of speaking merely correctly, rather than truly that only The World has perfectly natural properties. Might the monist deny this, and claim that sub-world claims of naturalness are correct? But how would the correctness of these claims be grounded in strictly true claims of 13 In my view, the definitions must be revised in light of the possibility of gunk. See Sider (1993, chapter 4). See also Sider (1996) for a defense of Lewis s definitions. 6

naturalness? I don t see how they could be. At any rate, the monist owes us a story. 14 References Albert, David Z. (1996). Elementary Quantum Metaphysics. In J. T. Cushing, A. Fine and S. Goldstein (eds.), Bohmian Mechanics and Quantum Theory: An Appraisal, 277 284. Dordrecht: Kluwer Academic Publishers. Dorr, Cian (2002). The Simplicity of Everything. Ph.D. thesis, Princeton University. (2005). What We Disagree About When We Disagree About Ontology. In Mark Kalderon (ed.), Fictionalism in Metaphysics, 234 86. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Hawthorne, John (O Leary-) and Andrew Cortens (1995). Towards Ontological Nihilism. Philosophical Studies 79: 143 165. Horgan, Terence and Matjaž Potrč (2000). Blobjectivism and Indirect Correspondence. Facta Philosophica 2: 249 270. (2002). Addressing Questions for Blobjectivism. Facta Philosophica 4: 311 322. Lewis, David (1986). On the Plurality of Worlds. Oxford: Basil Blackwell. Merricks, Trenton (2001). Objects and Persons. Oxford: Clarendon. Parsons, Josh (2004). Distributional Properties. In Frank Jackson and Graham Priest (eds.), Lewisian Themes, 173 80. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Schaffer, Jonathan (2007). From Nihilism to Monism. Australasian Journal of Philosophy 85: 175 91. (Forthcoming). Monism. Available online at http://people.umass. edu/schaffer/papers/monism.pdf. 14 Actually, my forthcoming paper on monism shows how the monist could tell such a story. I wrote the latter paper after the present one. 7

Sider, Theodore (1993). Naturalness, Intrinsicality and Duplication. Ph.D. thesis, University of Massachusetts. Available online at http://homepages.nyu. edu/~ts65/papers/diss.pdf. (1996). Intrinsic Properties. Philosophical Studies 83: 1 27. van Inwagen, Peter (1990). Material Beings. Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press. 8