Quantifiers: Their Semantic Type (Part 3) Heim and Kratzer Chapter 6

Similar documents
Ling 98a: The Meaning of Negation (Week 1)

10. Presuppositions Introduction The Phenomenon Tests for presuppositions

Factivity and Presuppositions David Schueler University of Minnesota, Twin Cities LSA Annual Meeting 2013

Lecturer: Xavier Parent. Imperative logic and its problems. by Joerg Hansen. Imperative logic and its problems 1 / 16

SAVING RELATIVISM FROM ITS SAVIOUR

On Conceivability and Existence in Linguistic Interpretation

Elements of Science (cont.); Conditional Statements. Phil 12: Logic and Decision Making Fall 2010 UC San Diego 9/29/2010

Ayer and Quine on the a priori

Comments on Truth at A World for Modal Propositions

Phil 413: Problem set #1

Broad on Theological Arguments. I. The Ontological Argument

Exercise Sets. KS Philosophical Logic: Modality, Conditionals Vagueness. Dirk Kindermann University of Graz July 2014

From Necessary Truth to Necessary Existence

On Truth At Jeffrey C. King Rutgers University

Facts and Free Logic. R. M. Sainsbury

Facts and Free Logic R. M. Sainsbury

Ayer s linguistic theory of the a priori

Lexical Alternatives as a Source of Pragmatic Presuppositions

A Defense of Contingent Logical Truths

God of the gaps: a neglected reply to God s stone problem

PHILOSOPHY OF LOGIC AND LANGUAGE OVERVIEW LOGICAL CONSTANTS WEEK 5: MODEL-THEORETIC CONSEQUENCE JONNY MCINTOSH

Philosophy 125 Day 12: Overview

A Generalization of Hume s Thesis

INFERENCES LING106 KNOWLEDGE OF MEANING DOROTHY AHN SECTION 2 [2/12/2016]

Announcements. CS311H: Discrete Mathematics. First Order Logic, Rules of Inference. Satisfiability, Validity in FOL. Example.

Phil 435: Philosophy of Language. P. F. Strawson: On Referring

Informalizing Formal Logic

TWO VERSIONS OF HUME S LAW

Foreknowledge, evil, and compatibility arguments

Reconciling Greek mathematics and Greek logic - Galen s question and Ibn Sina s answer

Quantificational logic and empty names

1. Introduction Formal deductive logic Overview

TWO DIMENSIONAL MODAL ONTOLOGICAL ARGUMENT FOR THE EXISTENCE OF GOD

The projection problem of presuppositions

In Defense of Truth functional Theory of Indicative Conditionals. Ching Hui Su Postdoctoral Fellow Institution of European and American Studies,

Prior on an insolubilium of Jean Buridan

Announcements. CS243: Discrete Structures. First Order Logic, Rules of Inference. Review of Last Lecture. Translating English into First-Order Logic

Empty Names and Two-Valued Positive Free Logic

Free will and the necessity of the past

Russell: On Denoting

Reductio ad Absurdum, Modulation, and Logical Forms. Miguel López-Astorga 1

Kai von Fintel. Massachusetts Institute of Technology. The background for this squib is the ongoing debate about whether natural language

Does Deduction really rest on a more secure epistemological footing than Induction?

Fatalism and Truth at a Time Chad Marxen

Semantic Entailment and Natural Deduction

A Defence of Kantian Synthetic-Analytic Distinction

Generation and evaluation of different types of arguments in negotiation

Leibniz, Principles, and Truth 1

Supervaluationism and Fara s argument concerning higher-order vagueness

Believing Epistemic Contradictions

Aquinas' Third Way Modalized

Deduction by Daniel Bonevac. Chapter 1 Basic Concepts of Logic

Revisiting the Socrates Example

Topics in Linguistic Theory: Propositional Attitudes

Understanding Truth Scott Soames Précis Philosophy and Phenomenological Research Volume LXV, No. 2, 2002

Theories of propositions

1/5. The Critique of Theology

Predicate logic. Miguel Palomino Dpto. Sistemas Informáticos y Computación (UCM) Madrid Spain

Uli Sauerland (Berlin) Implicated Presuppositions. 1 Introduction

Constructing the World

Logic & Proofs. Chapter 3 Content. Sentential Logic Semantics. Contents: Studying this chapter will enable you to:

G. H. von Wright Deontic Logic

Putnam: Meaning and Reference

Is Innate Foreknowledge Possible to a Temporal God?

Frode Bjørdal ON BELIEFS. 1. Introduction

Potentialism about set theory

On a priori knowledge of necessity 1

Bertrand Russell Proper Names, Adjectives and Verbs 1

Philosophy of Mathematics Kant

Embedded Attitudes *

Some observations on identity, sameness and comparison

A Defense of the Kripkean Account of Logical Truth in First-Order Modal Logic

10 CERTAINTY G.E. MOORE: SELECTED WRITINGS

Vagueness and supervaluations

Definite Descriptions and the Argument from Inference

Van Inwagen's modal argument for incompatibilism

Conditionals IV: Is Modus Ponens Valid?

Knowledge, Time, and the Problem of Logical Omniscience

What is an Argument? Validity vs. Soundess of Arguments

BART GEURTS EXISTENTIAL IMPORT

how to be an expressivist about truth

Can Gödel s Incompleteness Theorem be a Ground for Dialetheism? *

Entailment, with nods to Lewy and Smiley

BENEDIKT PAUL GÖCKE. Ruhr-Universität Bochum

Subjective Logic: Logic as Rational Belief Dynamics. Richard Johns Department of Philosophy, UBC

KAPLAN RIGIDITY, TIME, A ND MODALITY. Gilbert PLUMER

An alternative understanding of interpretations: Incompatibility Semantics

Cohen 2004: Existential Generics Shay Hucklebridge LING 720

7. Some recent rulings of the Supreme Court were politically motivated decisions that flouted the entire history of U.S. legal practice.

CAS LX 522 Syntax I Fall 2000 November 6, 2000 Paul Hagstrom Week 9: Binding Theory. (8) John likes him.

Informal Reasoning and Logical Formalization

A Priori Knowledge: Analytic? Synthetic A Priori (again) Is All A Priori Knowledge Analytic?

INHISINTERESTINGCOMMENTS on my paper "Induction and Other Minds" 1

Class 8 - The Attributive/Referential Distinction

Philosophy of Mind. Introduction to the Mind-Body Problem

UC Berkeley, Philosophy 142, Spring 2016

(Some More) Vagueness

Can logical consequence be deflated?

Intersubstitutivity Principles and the Generalization Function of Truth. Anil Gupta University of Pittsburgh. Shawn Standefer University of Melbourne

The Myth of Factive Verbs

Transcription:

Quantifiers: Their Semantic Type (Part 3) Heim and Kratzer Chapter 6 1

6.7 Presuppositional quantifier phrases 2

6.7.1 Both and neither (1a) Neither cat has stripes. (1b) Both cats have stripes. (1a) and (1b) presuppose that there are exactly two cats. Hence, it seems that we should define the denotations of neither and both accordingly. (2) f neither = λa : A Pow(D) & A = 2. [λb Pow(D). A B = ]. (3) f both = λa : A Pow(D) & A = 2. [λb Pow(D). A B]. 3

6.7.2 Presuppositionality and the relational theory (SKETCH) The existence of presuppositional determiners is incompatible with the strictly relational theory of quantifiers: a given ordered pair either is or is not a member of a relation. An almost relational theory, on which determiner meanings are potentially partial functions from Pow(D) x Pow(D) to {0, 1}, would work fine: (6a) F both = λ <A, B> : A D & B D & A = 2. A B. (6b) F no = λ <A, B> : A D & B D. A B =. (9) F neither = λ <A, B> : A D & B D & A = 2. A B =. Now we have to change the definitions of the mathematical properties. C.f. the definitions on p. 157. 4

6.8 Presuppositional quantifier phrases: controversial cases 5

6.8.1 Strawson s reconstruction of Aristotelian logic The relational definitions of quantifying determiners that we have adopted were the ones promoted by the founders of modern logic: (1a) R every = {<A, B> : A B} (1b) R some = {<A, B> : A B } (1c) R no = {<A, B> : A B = } But these definitions are not consistent with certain assumptions about the semantics of these quantifying determiners that were part of (at least some versions of) Aristotelian logic. In that tradition, generalizations such as those in (2) were considered valid. 6

6.8.1 Strawson s reconstruction of Aristotelian logic (cont.) (2) For any predicates α, β: (i) every α β and no α β is a contradiction. (ii) some α β or no α β is a tautology. (iii) every α β entails some α β. (iv) no α β entails some α not β. (3a) Every first-year student in this class did well and no first-year student in this class did well. Aristotelian logic: (3a) is contradictory. Modern logic: (3a) is contingent: It is true when there are no first-year students in the class. 7

6.8.1 Strawson s reconstruction of Aristotelian logic (cont.) (3b) Some cousin of mine smokes, or some cousin of mine doesn t smoke. Aristotelian logic: (3b) is a tautology. Modern logic: (3a) is contingent: It is false when the speaker has no cousins. (3c) Every professor at the meeting was against the proposal. Some professor at the meeting was against the proposal. Aristotelian logic: (3c) is a valid inference. Modern logic: the premise in (3c) does not entail the conclusion: The former is true but the latter false when there were no profesors at the meeting. 8

6.8.1 Strawson s reconstruction of Aristotelian logic (cont.) (3d) No student presentation today was longer than an hour. Some student presentation today wasn t longer than an hour. Aristotelian logic: (3d) is a valid inference. Modern logic: the premise is true, but its conclusion false if there were no student presentations today. 9

6.8.1 Strawson s reconstruction of Aristotelian logic (cont.) The empirical evidence bearing on the question as to which is correct is surprisingly difficult to assess. Strawson proposed that the Aristotelian laws in (2) are correct, i.e. that the determiners have the semantics in (4). (4a) F every = λ<a, B> : A. A B. (4b) F some = λ<a, B> : A. A B. (4c) F no = λ<a, B> : A. A B =. 10

6.8.1 Strawson s reconstruction of Aristotelian logic (cont.) These entries validate the Aristotelian generalizations in (2), provided that we have suitable definitions of the semantic properties. Basic semantic properties φ is a tautology iff the semantic rules alone establish that, if φ is in the domain of [[ ]], then [[φ]] = 1. φ is a contradiction iff the semantic rules alone establish that, if φ is in the domain of [[ ]], then [[φ]] = 0. φ entails ψ iff the semantic rules alone establish that, if φ and ψ are both in the domain of [[ ]] and [[φ]] = 1, then [[ψ]] = 1. 11

6.8.2 Are all determiners presuppositional? A strong position was taken by McCawley 1972 and Diesing 1992: (5) Presuppositionality Hypothesis In natural languages, all lexical items with denotations of type << e, t >, << e, t >, t >> are presuppositional, in the sense of the following mathematical definition (where δ is a lexical item of the appropriate semantic type, such as determiner): δ is presuppositional iff for all A D, B D : if A =, then <A, B> / dom(f δ ). 12

6.8.2 Are all determiners presuppositional? (11) In contingent contexts, strong determiners evoke judgments that conform to the presuppositional analysis, whereas weak determiners give rise to mixed judgments that conform sometimes to the presuppositional and sometimes to the standard analysis. (Lappin & Reinhart 1988) PRESUPPOSITION FAILURE: (strong quantifiers) (7a) All American kings lived in New York. (7b) All unicorns have accounts at the Chase Manhattan Bank. HALF TRUE (8a) OR FALSE (8b), and HALF PRESUPPOSITION FAILURES (weak quantifiers): (8a) No American king lived in New York. (8b) Two American kings lived in New York. TRUE (generic, law-like statements): (9a) Every unicorn has exactly one horn. (9b) Every unicorn is a unicorn. 13

6.8.3 Nonextensional interpretations (1) Every unicorn has one horn. (2) Every unicorn has two horns. (1) seems definitely true, while (2) seems definitely false. Thus generic statements seem to require the non-presuppositional analysis. But generics are modal in nature, and involve quantifying over other possible worlds, including those possible worlds in which unicorns exist. Perhaps these sentences require the existence of possible unicorns. These sentences don t help us choose between a presuppositional and non-presuppositional treatment of quantifying determiners. 14

6.8.3 Nonextensional interpretations (cont.) But here s an argument from Kratzer that supports the presuppositional account of generic/law-like statements. It makes sense to think of living in a world where (19a,b) are true and (19c) is false. The Samaritan Paradox (19a) The town regulations require that there be no trespassers. (19b) The town regulations require that all trespassers be fined. (19c) the town regulations require that no trespassers be fined. (19a) says that there is no trespassing in any possible worlds in which no town regulation is violated. But then, on a non-presuppositional account, (19b) and (19c) would both be true. In understanding (19b,c), we temporarily suspend the regulation that there be no trespassers; i.e. the presupposition that there are trespassers is playing a role here. 15

6.8.4 Nonpresuppostional behavior in weak determiners (20a) No phonologists with psychology degrees applied for our job. (TRUE if there aren t any) (20b) Two UFOs landed in my backyard yesterday. (FALSE if there aren t any). (8a) No American king lived in New York. (TRUE or PRESUPPOSITION FAILURE) (21a) There were no American kings in New York (TRUE) (8b) Two American kings lived in New York. (FALSE or PRESUPPOSITION FAILURE) (21b) There were two American kings in New York (FALSE) (22a) If you find every/most mistake(s), I ll give you a fine reward. (PRESUPPOSITIONAL) (22b) If you find many/a/no/three mistake(s), I ll give you a fine reward (NON-PRESUPPOSITIONAL) 16

6.8.4 Nonpresuppostional behavior in weak determiners (cont.) Diesing 1990 proposed that subjects are generated inside the VP, and that strong DPs raise into SPEC-IP, whereas weak DPs may or may not raise only if they do are they presuppositional (the Mapping Hypothesis). Those that don t raise are of type < e, t >. De Hoop 1992 proposed that the difference lies in case marking: i.e. [NH: something like] genitive or bare DPs do not raise; whereas nominative or accusative DPs do raise if topical. Those that don t raise are of type < e, t >. Others believe it has to do solely with topic and focus: topic DPs are presuppositional; whereas focus DPs aren t. 17