Philosophy 125 Day 21: Overview

Similar documents
Retrospective Remarks on Events (Kim, Davidson, Quine) Philosophy 125 Day 20: Overview. The Possible & The Actual I: Intensionality of Modality 2

Nominalism III: Austere Nominalism 1. Philosophy 125 Day 7: Overview. Nominalism IV: Austere Nominalism 2

It turns out that there is an important class of sentences that we have so far pretty much avoided mentioning: modal sentences.

Philosophy 125 Day 4: Overview

Philosophy 125 Day 12: Overview

Philosophy 125 Day 13: Overview

Theories of propositions

5 The necessary and the possible

1. Introduction. Against GMR: The Incredulous Stare (Lewis 1986: 133 5).

From Necessary Truth to Necessary Existence

Overview of Today s Lecture

Philosophy 125 Day 8: Overview

Counterparts and Compositional Nihilism: A Reply to A. J. Cotnoir

Resemblance Nominalism and counterparts

Possibility and Necessity

Lecture 3: Properties II Nominalism & Reductive Realism. Lecture 3: Properties II Nominalism & Reductive Realism

Modal Realism, Still At Your Convenience

PHILOSOPHICAL PROBLEMS & THE ANALYSIS OF LANGUAGE

Timothy Williamson: Modal Logic as Metaphysics Oxford University Press 2013, 464 pages

Philosophy of Mathematics Nominalism

KAPLAN RIGIDITY, TIME, A ND MODALITY. Gilbert PLUMER

Intermediate Logic Spring. Extreme Modal Realism

Philosophy 125 Day 1: Overview

Comments on Ontological Anti-Realism

Postscript to Plenitude of Possible Structures (2016)

OBJECTIVITY WITHOUT THE PHILOSOPHER S SPECIAL OBJECTS: A PRIORIAN PROGRAM. James Van Cleve, University of Southern California

MODAL REALISM AND PHILOSOPHICAL ANALYSIS: THE CASE OF ISLAND UNIVERSES

Modal Realism, Counterpart Theory, and Unactualized Possibilities

Unrestricted Quantification and Reality: Reply to Kim. Takashi Yagisawa. California State University, Northridge

Presuppositions (Ch. 6, pp )

Objections to the two-dimensionalism of The Conscious Mind

Names Introduced with the Help of Unsatisfied Sortal Predicates: Reply to Aranyosi

Truth and Modality - can they be reconciled?

Deflationary Nominalism s Commitment to Meinongianism

On Truth At Jeffrey C. King Rutgers University

On possibly nonexistent propositions

To appear in Philosophical Studies 150 (3): (2010).

Postmodal Metaphysics

Existentialism Entails Anti-Haecceitism DRAFT. Alvin Plantinga first brought the term existentialism into the currency of analytic

There are three aspects of possible worlds on which metaphysicians

Maximal Possibilities *

Socrates, Seated Socrates. First Philosophy and Sophistic

TAKASHI YAGISAWA Department of Philosophy, C.S.U.N. Primitive Worlds. 0. Introduction

Philosophy 148 Announcements & Such. Inverse Probability and Bayes s Theorem II. Inverse Probability and Bayes s Theorem III

Mereological Ontological Arguments and Pantheism 1. which draw on the resources of mereology, i.e. the theory of the part-whole relation.

WHY THERE REALLY ARE NO IRREDUCIBLY NORMATIVE PROPERTIES

On Priest on nonmonotonic and inductive logic

Metaphysical Dependence and Set Theory

A DEFENSE OF PRESENTISM

USAGE STATEMENT & AGREEMENT. This document is the property of the author(s) and of

Constructing the World

Comments on Truth at A World for Modal Propositions

A Defense of Contingent Logical Truths

BOOK REVIEWS. Duke University. The Philosophical Review, Vol. XCVII, No. 1 (January 1988)

Primitive Concepts. David J. Chalmers

Abstract Abstraction Abundant ontology Abundant theory of universals (or properties) Actualism A-features Agent causal libertarianism

Branching versus Divergent Possible Worlds

Metametaphysics. New Essays on the Foundations of Ontology* Oxford University Press, 2009

Fatalism and Truth at a Time Chad Marxen

Replies to Giuliano Torrengo, Dan Zeman and Vasilis Tsompanidis

The Sea-Fight Tomorrow by Aristotle

The Substance of Ontological Disputes. Richard C. Lamb

Kripke s famous thesis that proper names are rigid designators is accepted by many and

Unnecessary Existents. Joshua Spencer University of Wisconsin-Milwaukee

REPLY TO LUDLOW Thomas M. Crisp. Oxford Studies in Metaphysics 1 (2004): 37-46

Presentism and eterrnalism HAROLD W. NOONAN. Department of Philosophy. University of Nottingham. Nottingham, NG72RD, UK. Tel: +44 (0)

ACTUALISM AND THISNESS*

Putnam: Meaning and Reference

Argument from Vagueness for Modal Parts

Saving the Substratum: Interpreting Kant s First Analogy

On Possibly Nonexistent Propositions

Compositional Pluralism and Composition as Identity

Truth At a World for Modal Propositions

Bertrand Russell Proper Names, Adjectives and Verbs 1

Philosophy 1100: Introduction to Ethics. Critical Thinking Lecture 1. Background Material for the Exercise on Validity

TEMPORAL NECESSITY AND LOGICAL FATALISM. by Joseph Diekemper

5 A Modal Version of the

Real Metaphysics. Essays in honour of D. H. Mellor. Edited by Hallvard Lillehammer and Gonzalo Rodriguez-Pereyra

Fundamentals of Metaphysics

5: Preliminaries to the Argument

Subjective Logic: Logic as Rational Belief Dynamics. Richard Johns Department of Philosophy, UBC

The Methodology of Modal Logic as Metaphysics

Contextual two-dimensionalism

Nature of Necessity Chapter IV

A defense of contingent logical truths

Facts and Free Logic. R. M. Sainsbury

Facts and Free Logic R. M. Sainsbury

Critical Study of Michael Jubien, Ontology, Modality, and the Fallacy of Reference

Metaphysical Necessity: Understanding, Truth and Epistemology

Time travel and the open future

Aquinas' Third Way Modalized

Analyticity and reference determiners

What God Could Have Made

Published in Analysis 61:1, January Rea on Universalism. Matthew McGrath

Principles of Plenitude (1986) Our chief concern is with actuality, with the way the world is. But inquiry into the actual may

Phil 435: Philosophy of Language. [Handout 7] W. V. Quine, Quantifiers and Propositional Attitudes (1956)

Dartmouth College THE DIVINE SIMPLICITY *

Universals. If no: Then it seems that they could not really be similar. If yes: Then properties like redness are THINGS.

1.2. What is said: propositions

David Lewis (1941 ) Introduction

Transcription:

Branden Fitelson Philosophy 125 Lecture 1 Philosophy 125 Day 21: Overview 1st Papers/SQ s to be returned this week (stay tuned... ) Vanessa s handout on Realism about propositions to be posted Second papers/s.q. s to be assigned next week (to be due at final) Agenda: Modality (Unit 3) De dicto vs de re modal claims Lewis vs Kripke on de re modal claims Possible worlds as a tool for nominalizing properties, etc. Scrutinizing Lewis Realism about possible worlds * Four basic tenets of Lewisian realism about possible worlds * Objections to some of the Lewisian tenets * Alternative realist/non-realist accounts (Stalnaker/Rosen) Actualism (Plantinga et al)

Branden Fitelson Philosophy 125 Lecture 2 Brief Review of Modality Stuff Up to Now Modal operators are intensional: they make non-opaque sentences opaque. Many logics of necessity and possibility have been floated over the ages. These logics have disagreed on basic principles (axioms) for modality. There was no systematic way of understanding the relationships between these many modal logics. Moreover, there was no extensional semantics for modal claims. And, extensionality is considered a hallmark of logicality. Until the middle of the 20th century, which saw the advent of possible worlds semantics (a.k.a., Kripke semantics). This provided a unified, extensional semantics for modal claims and modal logics. Translations liekt the following: Necessarily, p p is true in every possible world w that is accessible from the actual world (the accessibility relation depends on context). If we assume that all possible worlds are accessible from here, then we get back the naive modal logic (which interprets necessity as truth in all worlds).

Branden Fitelson Philosophy 125 Lecture 3 The Possible & The Actual IV: De Dicto vs De Re Modality 1 So far, we ve been talking about the semantics and logic of de dicto modal claims claims in which modal operators are applied to entire statements p. There is another kind of modal claim, called de re (even more controversial!). Consider the following de re claim involving the necessity operator: (i) The thing Branden is thinking about is necessarily an even number. Assuming I am thinking about the number 2, (i) is true, because the number 2 is necessarily an even number (even-ness is not a contingent property of 2). But, if we move the operator outside, we get the following de dicto claim: (ii) Necessarily, the thing Branden is thinking about is an even number. But, (ii) is false, since it is a contingent property of me that I happen to be thinking about the number 2 (and, not, say, the number 3). In the de dicto claim, the operator has wide scope; in the de re claim it has narrow scope. Possible worlds semantics can also be used to understand de re modal claims.

Branden Fitelson Philosophy 125 Lecture 4 The Possible & The Actual IV: De Dicto vs De Re Modality 2 Naively, as propositions can be true or false in various possible worlds, objects can exist or fail to exist in various possible worlds, and in the various worlds where they exist they can have various (differing) properties. To wit: x is necessarily P x is P in all possible worlds in which x exists x is contingently P x is P in some possible worlds in which x exists, and x is non-p in some possible worlds in which x exists This provides a possible worlds semantics for claims about essential or necessary properties of objects (e.g., the kinds in Aristotelian metaphysics). Moreover, we can think of each possible world w as having a population of inhabitants. And, different possible worlds can have different populations of inhabitants (no overlaps for Lewis, but some overlaps for Kripke). Note: there is a key difference between de re and de dicto translations. In the de re case, we must restrict quantification to those worlds in which the object x in question exists. This is unnecessary in the de dicto case. Why?

Branden Fitelson Philosophy 125 Lecture 5 The Possible & The Actual V: Lewis versus Kripke on De Re Modality We said earlier that (naively) we could understand x s being necessarily F as x s being F in all possible worlds in which x exists. For Lewis, this would reduce to x s being a member of F w, for all w in which x exists. Interestingly, Lewis rejects this naive approach to de re modality. He does so because he doesn t believe that objects can be identified across possible worlds. In other words, while I exist in the actual world, Lewis would say that I don t exist in any non-actual worlds. This renders the naive approach trivial. Why does Lewis say this? He is persuaded by the following argument (Loux): Suppose that some individual (call it x) exists in each of a pair of worlds, w 1, and w 2. We can dub x as it is found in w 1, x-in-w 1, and x as it is found in w 2 x-in-w 2. Now, if w 1 and w 2 are genuinely different worlds, things will go differently for x-in- w 1, and x-in-w 2. But, if this is so, there are bound to be properties that x-in-w 1 has but x-in-w 2 lacks. Accordingly, if x exists in each of w 1 and w 2, then we have a violation of the indiscernibility of identicals. But, the indiscernibility of identicals is true, so our assumption that one object could occupy two different possible worlds must be false.

Branden Fitelson Philosophy 125 Lecture 6 Kripke and others who reject the conclusion of this argument (for reasons we will discuss below) offer the following way out. They say, we can think of properties as world-indexed. On this view, x can have the property being F-in-w, and fail to have the property F-in-w : two different properties. E.g., Socrates might be courageous-in-w but fail to be courageous-in-w. This does not imply that one object has and fails to have one and the same property, so it poses no violation of the indiscernibility of identicals. This avoids violating the indiscernability of identicals. But, on this view, what does it mean to say that my height could have been different? That for some w, my height w is different than my height w? Is this a difference in height? Moreover, on this view, we can no longer extensionally distinguish having-a-heart w and having-a-kidney w. If these properties are world-bound, then they have the same extension in all worlds (no extension outside w ). And, how can objects have properties contingently? Intuitively, having a property P contingently is to have P in some worlds but to lack P (not some other property) in other worlds, which is impossible on this proposal.

Branden Fitelson Philosophy 125 Lecture 7 Which do you think is the more unintuitive consequence? S.Q. Kripke et al point out some odd consequences of Lewis approach. On Lewis approach, when I talk about properties I have necessarily, I am really talking about properties P that I have in w, and that different people have in w. But, how are the properties of other people relevant to properties of me? When I deliberate, I want to know what I should do, not what other people should do. So, why do I care what happens to my counterparts who do X? If I m deliberating about whether to bring an umbrella to work, I think about what would happen to me in various circumstances, were I to bring it. If it were to rain, I d remain dry, if not, I d be unnecessarily weighed down, etc. Say, actually, it does not rain, but I bring my umbrella. In some sense, I wish I hadn t brought my umbrella. But, on Lewis view, this is wishing that my counterpart hadn t brought his umbrella. What s that got to do with me? But, Kripke has us wishing that we hadn t brought-our-umbrella-in-w. This also seems strange, since it s the lack of the very same property (having brought our umbrella) we want, not some other property (if there be such).

Branden Fitelson Philosophy 125 Lecture 8 Lewis story about counterparts (as opposed to persons leading double lives in different possible worlds simultaneously) is similar to his story about perdurance (as opposed to endurance) of persons within worlds through time. Something perdures iff it persists by having different temporal parts, or stages, at different times, though no one part of it is wholly present at more than one time... it endures iff it persists by being wholly present at more than one time. Perdurance corresponds to the way a road persists through space; part of it is here and part of it is there, and no part is wholly present at two different places. Endurance corresponds to the way a universal... would be wholly present wherever & whenever it is instantiated. Endurance involves overlap: the content of two different times has the enduring thing as a common part. Perdurance does not. Endurance is to be rejected in favour of perdurance. We perdure; we are made up of temporal parts, and our temporary intrinsics are properties of these parts, wherein they differ one from another. There is no problem at all about how different things can differ in their intrinsic properties. On this view, we identify things through time only by relations of similarity between temporal parts. For Lewis, the same is true of trans-world identity.

Branden Fitelson Philosophy 125 Lecture 9 The Possible & The Actual VI: Possible Worlds as a Tool for Nominalization In recent years, realists about possible worlds (especially, David Lewis) have found clever ways to use possible worlds for the purpose of nominalizing other sorts of discourse, concerning universals, propositions, etc. Armed with possible worlds (we ll scrutinize the nature of these below) plus set theory, Lewis nominalizes universals, propositions, and other abstract entities. The trick is to define universals, propositions, etc. as sets. These sets will contain particulars, possible worlds, and/or sets thereof, but nothing else. For Lewis, a property P is just a very large set of sets of concrete particulars. In each possible world w, there will be a set P w of concrete particulars that are P in w (i.e., P s extension in w). The property P is just the big set, which contains all of the smaller sets P w as members: P = {P 1, P 2,..., P n,...}. As for propositions, they are also just sets, but they are sets of possible worlds (not sets of sets of concrete particulars, like properties are). Specifically, a proposition p is just a set of p-ish possible worlds. Intuitively, the p-ish worlds are just the worlds in which p is true. But, this is not the official line.

Branden Fitelson Philosophy 125 Lecture 10 Lewis wouldn t want to say that p is the set of worlds in which p is true, since this would not eliminate propositions. Instead, Lewis takes a world s being p-ish as a primitive or ontologically basic feature of a world, and he uses this primitive aspect to segregate worlds into the p-ish and the non-p-ish. On this account, the actual world w is snow is white -ish, and George W. Bush is President of the U.S. -ish, and these are primitive features of w. Necessarily p is true iff the set of p-ish worlds has every possible world as a member. And, Possibly p is true iff the set of p-ish worlds is nonempty. Problem: Lewis s account implies there can be only one necessary truth T, since a necessarily true proposition is just the set of all possible worlds. But, it seems strange to say that 2 + 2 = 4 expresses the same proposition as 4 + 4 = 8. Also, there can be only one necessary falsehood F (the null set). There are some virtues of Lewis approach to properties. Since it is not confined to actual extensions, it gives the intuitively right answer that having a heart (H) and having a kidney (K) come out as distinct properties.

Branden Fitelson Philosophy 125 Lecture 11 To see this, note that, despite the fact that H w = K w, there will (intuitively) be worlds w in which H w K w. So, H and K will be different sets H K. But, how does Lewis account of properties handle abstract reference, generally? We want claims like White is a color ( W is a C ) to come out necessarily true. How can Lewis theory of properties accommodate this? If C is a kind of property, then, for Lewis, it will be a set of properties. This, for Lewis, makes C a set of sets of sets of individuals. Picture this as follows: Color = {White, Blue,...} = {{White w, White w,...}, {Blue w, Blue w,...},...} So, White is a color will come out true, since W is a subset of C. And, presumably, this will be true in all possible worlds (set theory is necessary!). What about Courage is a virtue? Does Lewis modal approach allow us to avoid Loux s ceteris paribus clauses? S.Q. Moreover, how might Lewis handle Quine s trickier example These two species are cross-fertile? S.Q. Problem: Lewis account of properties implies that properties which are exemplified by the same individuals in all possible worlds are identical. But, being triangular and being trilateral do not seem to be identical properties.

Branden Fitelson Philosophy 125 Lecture 12 The Possible & The Actual VII: Scrutinizing Lewisian Possible Worlds 1 Lewis Realism about possible worlds rests on the following four tenets: 1. Possible worlds exist. Other possible worlds are just as real as the actual world. They may not actually exist, if actually existing requires something to exist in the actual world, but they do, nevertheless, exist. 2. Other, non-actual possible worlds are the same sort of thing as the actual world: concrete, mereological wholes containing I and my surroundings. They differ from ours not in kind, but only in what goes on at them. We call ours actual only because it is the one we happen to inhabit. 3. The indexical analysis of the adjective actual is correct. Actual is indexical, like I or here or now : it depends for its reference on the circumstances of utterance... the world where the utterance is located. 4. Possible worlds cannot be reduced to something more basic. Possible worlds are what they are and not another thing. It would be a mistake to identify them with some allegedly more respectable entity, e.g. a set of sentences of a language they re respectable entities in their own right.

Branden Fitelson Philosophy 125 Lecture 13 The Possible & The Actual VII: Scrutinizing Lewisian Possible Worlds 2 Tenet (1) is consistent with thinking of possible worlds as ways things might have been. But, tenet (2) seems inconsistent with this way of thinking about possible worlds. If possible worlds are ways things might have been, then the actual world should be the way things are, not I and my surroundings. That is, we can think of possible worlds as (i) existing, (ii) things that truth is defined relative to, and (iii) things our modal claims quantify over, without thinking that they are concrete objects (or made up of concrete objects) like the actual world is. [Stalnaker s slogan: the way the world is the world ] One might think that (3) implies (2), by implying that actuality is world-relative that our world is actual relative to itself, but all other possible worlds are actual relative to themselves too, and so there is no absolute perspective from which non-relative judgments of actuality can be made. But, this reasoning is mistaken. (3) is merely a semantical tenet about how to understand indexical terms. (2) can have strong metaphysical implications.

Branden Fitelson Philosophy 125 Lecture 14 If one thinks (as Stalnaker does) of the actual world as being synonymous with reality, then (2) can be false (and it s plausible to think it is), even if (3) is true. One can be a solipsist (one who accepts the metaphysical claim that only they exist) even if one accepts the indexical semantics for I. Stalnaker:... fictional characters are as right, from their point of view, to affirm their fullblooded reality as we are to affirm ours. But their point of view is fictional, and so what is right from it makes no difference as far as reality is concerned. So, one can accept (1) and (3) without accepting (2). One can, in addition, accept (4) without accepting (2). That is, one can take possible worlds as (1) existing things and (4) ontologically basic and ineliminable from our best theory of the world without taking them to be (2) just like the actual world. Stalnaker s alternative realism says possible are different kinds of things than the actual world. One natural move is to take them to be abstract entities. This would be consistent with accepting (1), (3), and (4), while rejecting (2). van Fraassen (a non-realist) works with possible world stories. Similarly, Rosen endorses a fictionalist approach to possible worlds. Links on website.

Branden Fitelson Philosophy 125 Lecture 15 The Possible & The Actual VIII: Actualism 1 Many philosophers (including Stalnaker) balk at the idea that non-actual possible worlds are just as real as the actual world. They think of the actual world as synonymous with reality. For them, the actual world constitutes an absolute or privileged perspective on matters of real existence. Actualists see many problems with possibilism (the view that there exist non-actual, possible worlds or situations). First, they see various technical problems with the variety of set-theoretic possibilism Lewis endorses: There can only be one necessary truth and one necessary falsehood. * 2 + 2 = 4 = 3 6 = 18, and 2 + 2 4 = 3 6 18 Necessarily coextensional properties (and propositions) are identical. * Triangularity = Trilaterality Sets do not seem to be the kinds of things that we can have propositional attitudes with respect to, or that can be the bearers of truth-values. * Is believing that 3 6 18 the same as believing the null set?

Branden Fitelson Philosophy 125 Lecture 16 The Possible & The Actual VIII: Actualism 2 Some responses to the the technical problems. First, the problem of necessary truth/falsehood: that there can be only one of each. This problem needs to be clarified a bit. Which sense of necessity is supposed to be involved here? What s the problem with saying that if it is logically impossible for propositions a and b to have different truth-values, then a = b? The example involving 2 + 2 = 4 and 3 6 = 18 is, arguably, not a counterexample to this principle. If one doesn t include the laws of arithmetic with the laws of logic, then there is no counterexample here. OK, what about: x = x = p implies p? It s not so obvious to me that these express different propositions. A similar point can be made about properties. If it is logically impossible for P and Q to have different extensions, then what s wrong with saying that P = Q? Stalnaker discusses these issues at length in his book Inquiry.