Haberdashers Aske s Boys School

Similar documents
Semantic Foundations for Deductive Methods

Predicate logic. Miguel Palomino Dpto. Sistemas Informáticos y Computación (UCM) Madrid Spain

Prior, Berkeley, and the Barcan Formula. James Levine Trinity College, Dublin

Semantic Entailment and Natural Deduction

LTJ 27 2 [Start of recorded material] Interviewer: From the University of Leicester in the United Kingdom. This is Glenn Fulcher with the very first

Does Deduction really rest on a more secure epistemological footing than Induction?

Early Russell on Philosophical Grammar

Artificial Intelligence: Valid Arguments and Proof Systems. Prof. Deepak Khemani. Department of Computer Science and Engineering

What would count as Ibn Sīnā (11th century Persia) having first order logic?

Empty Names and Two-Valued Positive Free Logic

Class #14: October 13 Gödel s Platonism

Broad on Theological Arguments. I. The Ontological Argument

Study Guides. Chapter 1 - Basic Training

the notion of modal personhood. I begin with a challenge to Kagan s assumptions about the metaphysics of identity and modality.

Class 33 - November 13 Philosophy Friday #6: Quine and Ontological Commitment Fisher 59-69; Quine, On What There Is

16. Universal derivation

Bertrand Russell Proper Names, Adjectives and Verbs 1

A BRIEF INTRODUCTION TO LOGIC FOR METAPHYSICIANS

ILLOCUTIONARY ORIGINS OF FAMILIAR LOGICAL OPERATORS

Summary Kooij.indd :14

UC Berkeley, Philosophy 142, Spring 2016

TWO VERSIONS OF HUME S LAW

Pictures, Proofs, and Mathematical Practice : Reply to James Robert Brown

Quine on the analytic/synthetic distinction

Lecture 4. Before beginning the present lecture, I should give the solution to the homework problem

From Necessary Truth to Necessary Existence

How Gödelian Ontological Arguments Fail

Self-Evidence in Finnis Natural Law Theory: A Reply to Sayers

Who or what is God?, asks John Hick (Hick 2009). A theist might answer: God is an infinite person, or at least an

Announcements. CS243: Discrete Structures. First Order Logic, Rules of Inference. Review of Last Lecture. Translating English into First-Order Logic

In Search of the Ontological Argument. Richard Oxenberg

What is the Frege/Russell Analysis of Quantification? Scott Soames

In Part I of the ETHICS, Spinoza presents his central

Varieties of Apriority

Ayer and Quine on the a priori

2.1 Review. 2.2 Inference and justifications

Leibniz, Principles, and Truth 1

Quantificational logic and empty names

Issue 4, Special Conference Proceedings Published by the Durham University Undergraduate Philosophy Society

Coordination Problems

Russell on Plurality

Aquinas' Third Way Modalized

9.1 Intro to Predicate Logic Practice with symbolizations. Today s Lecture 3/30/10

Action in Special Contexts

Constructive Logic, Truth and Warranted Assertibility

An Introduction to. Formal Logic. Second edition. Peter Smith, February 27, 2019

Validity of Inferences *

Since Michael so neatly summarized his objections in the form of three questions, all I need to do now is to answer these questions.

Who is a person? Whoever you want it to be Commentary on Rowlands on Animal Personhood

Could have done otherwise, action sentences and anaphora

Evaluating Classical Identity and Its Alternatives by Tamoghna Sarkar

Necessity and Truth Makers

On Tarski On Models. Timothy Bays

NOT SO PROMISING AFTER ALL: EVALUATOR-RELATIVE TELEOLOGY AND COMMON-SENSE MORALITY

Lecture 3. I argued in the previous lecture for a relationist solution to Frege's puzzle, one which

Transition to Quantified Predicate Logic

[3.] Bertrand Russell. 1

I. In the ongoing debate on the meaning of logical connectives 1, two families of

Verificationism. PHIL September 27, 2011

Faults and Mathematical Disagreement

Ayer on the criterion of verifiability

SMITH ON TRUTHMAKERS 1. Dominic Gregory. I. Introduction

Theories of propositions

Conscientious Objection as a Human Right: A Logico-anarchist Approach

Philosophical Logic. LECTURE SEVEN MICHAELMAS 2017 Dr Maarten Steenhagen

Intuitive evidence and formal evidence in proof-formation

Study Guide: Academic Writing

Can Negation be Defined in Terms of Incompatibility?

1. Lukasiewicz s Logic

The cosmological argument (continued)

CHAPTER 1 A PROPOSITIONAL THEORY OF ASSERTIVE ILLOCUTIONARY ARGUMENTS OCTOBER 2017

III Knowledge is true belief based on argument. Plato, Theaetetus, 201 c-d Is Justified True Belief Knowledge? Edmund Gettier

SAVING RELATIVISM FROM ITS SAVIOUR

Aspects of Western Philosophy Dr. Sreekumar Nellickappilly Department of Humanities and Social Sciences Indian Institute of Technology, Madras

LGCS 199DR: Independent Study in Pragmatics

CHAPTER 2 THE LARGER LOGICAL LANDSCAPE NOVEMBER 2017

TRUTH-MAKERS AND CONVENTION T

Boghossian & Harman on the analytic theory of the a priori

A Liar Paradox. Richard G. Heck, Jr. Brown University

The Rightness Error: An Evaluation of Normative Ethics in the Absence of Moral Realism

A Brief Introduction to Key Terms

Ayer s linguistic theory of the a priori

Logical Omniscience in the Many Agent Case

1 Clarion Logic Notes Chapter 4

Pragmatic Presupposition

Artificial Intelligence Prof. P. Dasgupta Department of Computer Science & Engineering Indian Institute of Technology, Kharagpur

THE MEANING OF OUGHT. Ralph Wedgwood. What does the word ought mean? Strictly speaking, this is an empirical question, about the

That -clauses as existential quantifiers

Deflationary Nominalism s Commitment to Meinongianism

Comments on Truth at A World for Modal Propositions

Logic I or Moving in on the Monkey & Bananas Problem

Verification and Validation

Exercise Sets. KS Philosophical Logic: Modality, Conditionals Vagueness. Dirk Kindermann University of Graz July 2014

Kevin Scharp, Replacing Truth, Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2013, At 300-some pages, with narrow margins and small print, the work

Some proposals for understanding narrow content

Can Negation be Defined in Terms of Incompatibility?

Theory of Knowledge. 5. That which can be asserted without evidence can be dismissed without evidence. (Christopher Hitchens). Do you agree?

Metametaphysics. New Essays on the Foundations of Ontology* Oxford University Press, 2009

TRUTH IN MATHEMATICS. H.G. Dales and G. Oliveri (eds.) (Clarendon: Oxford. 1998, pp. xv, 376, ISBN X) Reviewed by Mark Colyvan

Bob Hale: Necessary Beings

Transcription:

1 Haberdashers Aske s Boys School Occasional Papers Series in the Humanities Occasional Paper Number Sixteen Are All Humans Persons? Ashna Ahmad Haberdashers Aske s Girls School March 2018

2 Haberdashers Aske s Occasional Paper Number Sixteen March 2018 All rights reserved Are All Humans Persons? Ashna Ahmad Abstract In this paper I propose a formal take on the question of whether all humans are persons, leaving aside the ethical aspects of the question which are usually given more attention. I define all humans are persons as a postulate of the form x(h(x) P(x)) and attempt to prove it by -introduction. I then evaluate this method in comparison with a more semantically-focused attempt to prove that humans and persons are logically equivalent or synonymous, as opposed to having a generalised conditional relationship. This paper concludes that due to the nature of the concepts of humanity and personhood, formal approaches to proving this postulate, despite being advantageous in some ways, will always fall short. Whether all humans are persons, whether personhood is entailed by humanity and other such questions, are important legal and ethical concerns. There has been no shortage of writing on the matter from a moral perspective, not least because the quality of being a person is commonly associated with entitlement to additional rights under the law. The debate surrounding abortion is an obvious example of this association; the distinction between a human and a person has been used to justify abortion on the grounds that a foetus is a member of the former category but not the latter and hence does not have a distinct right to life, for instance by abortion provider Dr. Parker as quoted in The Blaze. 1 However, it seems that the moral implications of this question have consumed and taken over what would usually be a question of categorisation, of verifying whether a postulated logical equivalence holds. Leaving aside the matter of whether an 1 Scanlon, Kate Abortion provider: A fetus is not a person; it s a human entity The Blaze, Feb 8 2017

3 ethical statement has truth-value, an ethical treatment of the question of whether humans are persons arguably fails to reach the crux of the issue. Instead of being treated as a predicate with its own intrinsic definition, personhood is often established as a necessary and sufficient condition for the granting of other properties and rights to the elements of the domain for which the predicate personhood (henceforth P) is true. One legal text even describes personhood, rather explicitly, as an instrument for claiming certain rights and privileges. 2 [italics added] As exemplified by the scenario involving abortion, one may argue that all humans are persons (or, conversely, that some humans are not persons) and implicitly mean that all humans are entitled to the rights attributed to persons, which is not equivalent to all humans being persons; it only shows that humans and persons have some rights in common. While the applicability of human rights is a valid discussion in its own right and one which social commentators will never tire of having, it does not get to the logical core of the question; that is, the nature of the postulate all humans are persons as a proposition. The aim of this essay is to take a different look at the question in the title, and to explore whether logical and linguistic reasoning can tackle the question of whether all humans are persons in a way in which the tired ethical debates surrounding the topic cannot. The statement can be paraphrased as for all x, humanity entails personhood (where x is naturally a free variable) and symbolically represented as x (H(x) P(x)). At first glance, this is a straightforward generalised conditional which can be proven the normal way. The general method for proving a generalised conditional, known as -introduction, is to assume some instance of H(x), prove P(x), discharge the assumption and infer that H(x) P(x) for arbitrary x and therefore for all x. Alternatively, it is not necessary to assume H(x) because H(x) P(x), having a false antecedent, is trivially true. 3 The proof would hence look something like the following: - Let x be arbitrary. - [Proof of H(x) P(x)] - Since x is arbitrary, it can be inferred that x (H(x) P(x)) This method can be used to prove generalised conditionals, given certain conditions. I shall use a fairly trivial set-theoretic example to illustrate this. Example: Let A and B be sets. Prove that A B = A A B. 4 1) A B x(x B x A) 2) x B (assumption) 3) A B = A (x B x A) 4) x(x B x A) (from 2 & 3) 2 McHugh, James T. What Is the Difference between a Person and a Human Being within the Law. The Review of Politics, vol. 54, no. 3, 1992, pp. 445 461 3 Cohen, Marc S. Methods of Proof for Quantifiers. Introduction to Logic Lecture 12. University of Washington, Seattle. 4 The postulate for this proof is the contrapositive of a postulate on an example sheet from Stanford s Introduction to Logic course, but the proof itself is the writer s own.

4 Thus, by assuming that x is arbitrary and using the axioms of set theory (or firstorder logic, depending on which language is being used), a set-theoretic statement which turned out to be equivalent to a generalised conditional is demonstrably provable. It should, however, now be rather obvious that a similar method would not work for the statement in the title of the essay. Such a method would have to proceed by proving that H(x) P(x) and generalising the proof, and while it would be possible to generalise it by assuming that x is arbitrary (one would simply assume x: H(x)), there is no way to reach the conditional from this assumption. In the example proof, it was quite evident that if x were an arbitrary element of B and the set A were defined as the union of A and B, x would also be an element of A, but the proof relied on translating the consequent (A B) of the original conditional into a conditional in its own right and subsequently using the antecedent of the original conditional to prove the translated consequent with the help of the axioms of set theory (i.e. the definition of the union of two sets). This could not be done in the case of x(h(x) P(x)), for two reasons. The first of these is simply structural: the proof in the example contained an additional building block in the form of the definition of A as A B, and an additional definition can make all the difference to the provability of a statement. The second concerns another component of a proof which can be used to deduce its results: axioms. The union of two sets is a clearly-defined concept in set theory which can be uncontroversially used as an axiom from which to derive other results; the same cannot be said of the notions of humanity and personhood, which have no axioms to bind them and may vary wildly depending on the context of their discussion and the background and political stance of whomever is interpreting them. Hence, one can conclude that although the statement in the title of this essay is in effect a generalised conditional and humanity and personhood, being attributes, could be defined as predicates, this statement is not logically provable due to the nature of the concepts it involves. Another way of evaluating the statement All humans are persons is to take a more linguistic approach, inspired by how the meanings of and relations between words are analysed in semantics. To go about this, the statement could be interpreted in two different ways, each representing a side of a divide which, although it has blurred recently and some deny emphatically that it should exist, still runs through formal grammar: the divide between formal and functional linguistic theories. Formal approaches favour more abstract analyses focusing on structures (phonemes, morphemes, sentences and so on) in and of themselves, whereas functional ones emphasise how such structures are shaped by how they are used. 5 Noting this theoretical distinction, one may rephrase the question in the title of this essay either as Are human and person logically equivalent? or as Are human and person synonyms? Given the definition of two or more statements as logically equivalent if they have the same truth-value in every model 6, it is tempting to conflate this concept with synonymy, which can also colloquially mean that two statements are interchangeable. To an extent, both concepts represent functional perspectives, 5 Coffin, Caroline, Donohue, Jim and North, Sarah. Exploring English grammar: From formal to functional. Routledge, 2013. 13. 6 Mendelson, Elliott. Introduction to Mathematical Logic. Springer US, 1987. 9.

5 since model in this context could be equivalent to use (in model theory, the term usually refers to the structure within which the axioms of a theory are applied). Therefore, while proofs of logical equivalency are most commonly written and justified using formal language, the requirement of a model means that this does not invariably have to be the case. However, the notion of synonymy goes further; instead of merely being a formally provable relation of, crudely put, sameness in all situations, synonymy encompasses a wealth of stylistic and sociocultural subtleties and implications 7, making a formal proof of synonymy impossible. Using the criteria of logical equivalence or synonymy appears to have its advantages over attempting to prove that all humans are persons through first-order logic or set theory. For one thing, it treats humanity and personhood as what they are: not abstract units, but words, bound just as much by the pragmatics of their use as by the grammatical and syntactical contexts in which they occur even more so when synonymy is the chosen criterion. For another, no additional definitions or axioms are required to show that the terms human and person are logically equivalent or synonymous, because both of these attributes are (in this context) based on the use and the semantic characteristics of the terms rather than having the syntactical basis which a proof using formal language would have had. Unfortunately, these criteria present us with their own problems. The statement All humans are persons is not a biconditional; although it entails that all humans are persons, it says nothing about whether all persons are humans, and therefore nothing about the equivalence or otherwise of the two predicates. Moreover, synonymy amounts to more than just all x is y ; it is a narrower relation and implies an element of stylistic identity which is not implied by all humans are persons. 8 All that is meant by all humans are persons is that everything which happens to be a human also happens to be a person; not any sort of tonal commonality between the words. So it seems that neither logic nor semantic theory has helped to find a sound approach with which to prove or disprove that all humans are persons. A successful proof of this postulate must meet a number of demanding criteria: it must not be totally formal, so as not to ignore the subjective interpretations of humanity and personhood which make the terms so difficult to define, yet it must also preserve the status of the postulate as undeniably a generalised conditional. It may well be impossible to write any such proof, and so it is likely that the postulate is not decidable. If this experiment with logical and linguistic proof has shown one thing, it is that when there is no way to reason that a conditional or an equivalence is true, the result is a debate such as the one surrounding whether humanity entails personhood: one with no correct answer, ever more obfuscatory language, and the decision of whether to view all humans as persons left entirely up to subjective interpretation and the lurking influence of social mores. 7 Dowty, David R., Robert E. Wall, and Stanley Peters. Introduction to Montague Semantics. Springer Netherlands, 1981. 49. 8 Ibid.