Issue IX August Review of Matthew Calarco's. Zoographies: The Question of the Animal from Heidegger to Derrida

Similar documents
We Are Made of Meat. An Interview with Matthew Calarco. Leonardo Caffo

AN OUTLINE OF CRITICAL THINKING

1 Hans Jonas, The Imperative of Responsibility: In Search of an Ethics for the Technological Age (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1984), 1-10.

Kant and the Problem of Metaphysics 1. By Tom Cumming

Review of This Is Not Sufficient: An Essay on Animality and Human Nature in Derrida. Leonard Lawlor Columbia University Press pp.

From tolerance to neutrality: A tacit schism

Response to The Problem of the Question About Animal Ethics by Michal Piekarski

EXERCISES, QUESTIONS, AND ACTIVITIES My Answers

H U M a N I M A L I A 3:1

In Search of a Political Ethics of Intersubjectivity: Between Hannah Arendt, Emmanuel Levinas and the Judaic

To Provoke or to Encourage? - Combining Both within the Same Methodology

J. Aaron Simmons and Bruce Ellis Benson, The New Phenomenology: A Philosophical Introduction (New York: Bloomsbury, 2013)

Honours Programme in Philosophy

Heidegger Introduction

Undergraduate Calendar Content

At the Frontiers of Reality

FIRST STUDY. The Existential Dialectical Basic Assumption of Kierkegaard s Analysis of Despair

Q&A with John Protevi, author of Political Affect: Connecting the Social and the Somatic.

IN DEFENSE OF AN ANIMAL S RIGHT TO LIFE. Aaron Simmons. A Dissertation

Tuukka Kaidesoja Précis of Naturalizing Critical Realist Social Ontology

GS SCORE ETHICS - A - Z. Notes

THEOLOGY IN THE FLESH

In its ultimate version, McCraw proposes that H epistemically trusts S for some proposition, p, iff:

Process Thought and Bridge Building: A Response to Stephen K. White. Kevin Schilbrack

PHILOSOPHY (PHIL) Philosophy (PHIL) 1

Conditions of Fundamental Metaphysics: A critique of Jorge Gracia's proposal

Department of Philosophy

RUNNING HEAD: Philosophy and Theology 1. Christine Orsini RELS 111 Professor Fletcher March 21, 2012 Short Writing Assignment 2

Introduction. I. Proof of the Minor Premise ( All reality is completely intelligible )

Philosophical approaches to animal ethics

Philosophy of Ethics Philosophy of Aesthetics. Ross Arnold, Summer 2014 Lakeside institute of Theology

Hoong Juan Ru. St Joseph s Institution International. Candidate Number Date: April 25, Theory of Knowledge Essay

KANT, MORAL DUTY AND THE DEMANDS OF PURE PRACTICAL REASON. The law is reason unaffected by desire.

Ralph K. Hawkins Averett University Danville, Virginia

Jonathan Tran, Foucault and Theology (London & New York: T & T Clark, 2011), ISBN:

NORMATIVITY WITHOUT NORMATIVISM 1

François Laruelle and the Non-Philosophical Tradition

John Haugeland. Dasein Disclosed: John Haugeland s Heidegger. Edited by Joseph Rouse. Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 2013.

DEPARTMENT OF PHILOSOPHY UNIVERSITY OF CALIFORNIA, RIVERSIDE. Graduate course and seminars for Fall Quarter

Returning the Ethical and Political to Animal Studies STEPHANIE JENKINS

Moral requirements are still not rational requirements

PHILOSOPHY (PHIL) Philosophy (PHIL) 1. PHIL HISTORICAL INTRODUCTION TO PHILOSOPHY Short Title: HIST INTRO TO PHILOSOPHY

Review of Jean Kazez's Animalkind: What We Owe to Animals

Canadian Society for Continental Philosophy

A Review of Christina M. Gschwandtner s Postmodern Apologetics? Arguments for God in Contemporary Philosophy (New York: Fordham UP, 2013)

Teachur Philosophy Degree 2018

Introduction. 1 Bertrand Russell, The Problems of Philosophy (Indianapolis: Hackett Publishing Company, n.d.), 7.

NATURALISED JURISPRUDENCE

Deanne: Have you come across other similar writing or do you believe yours is unique in some way?

A Framework for the Good

Hannah Arendt and the fragility of human dignity

Natural Resources Journal

SYSTEMATIC RESEARCH IN PHILOSOPHY. Contents

The Greatest Mistake: A Case for the Failure of Hegel s Idealism

Life has become a problem.

Alternative Conceptual Schemes and a Non-Kantian Scheme-Content Dualism

Response to Gregory Floyd s Where Does Hermeneutics Lead? Brad Elliott Stone, Loyola Marymount University ACPA 2017

Union University Ed.D. in Educational Leadership-Higher Education Course Syllabus

Short Answers: Answer the following questions in one paragraph (each is worth 4 points).

PHILOSOPHY (413) Chairperson: David Braden-Johnson, Ph.D.

SUMMARIES AND TEST QUESTIONS UNIT David Hume: The Origin of Our Ideas and Skepticism about Causal Reasoning

Philosophy in Review XXXIII (2013), no. 5

Eating Right: The Ethics of Food Choices and Food Policy Philosophy 252 Spring 2010 (Version of January 20)

Can Christianity be Reduced to Morality? Ted Di Maria, Philosophy, Gonzaga University Gonzaga Socratic Club, April 18, 2008

Writing Module Three: Five Essential Parts of Argument Cain Project (2008)

REASON AND PRACTICAL-REGRET. Nate Wahrenberger, College of William and Mary

Week 3: Negative Theology and its Problems

Towards Richard Rorty s Critique on Transcendental Grounding of Human Rights by Dr. P.S. Sreevidya

The Rightness Error: An Evaluation of Normative Ethics in the Absence of Moral Realism

PHD THESIS SUMMARY: Rational choice theory: its merits and limits in explaining and predicting cultural behaviour

Rule-Following and the Ontology of the Mind Abstract The problem of rule-following

1/8. The Schematism. schema of empirical concepts, the schema of sensible concepts and the

B.A. in Religion, Philosophy and Ethics (4-year Curriculum) Course List and Study Plan

PHILOSOPHY DEPARTMENT FALL SEMESTER 2009 COURSE OFFERINGS

Happiness and Personal Growth: Dial.

Two Kinds of Ends in Themselves in Kant s Moral Theory

Hume's Is/Ought Problem. Ruse and Wilson. Moral Philosophy as Applied Science. Naturalistic Fallacy

Robert Kiely Office Hours: Monday 4:15 6:00; Wednesday 1-3; Thursday 2-3

a video companion study guide a movement for wholeness in a fragmented world Christian Church (Disciples of Christ) in the united states and canada

The stated objective of Gloria Origgi s paper Epistemic Injustice and Epistemic Trust is:

- We might, now, wonder whether the resulting concept of justification is sufficiently strong. According to BonJour, apparent rational insight is

Projection in Hume. P J E Kail. St. Peter s College, Oxford.

Freedom From The Pursuit of Happiness

The Middle Path: A Case for the Philosophical Theologian. Leo Strauss roots the vitality of Western civilization in the ongoing conflict between

Newbigin, Lesslie. The Open Secret: An Introduction to the Theology of Mission. Grand Rapids, Mich.: Eerdmans, Kindle E-book.

The Moral Significance of Animal Pain and Animal Death. Elizabeth Harman. I. Animal Cruelty and Animal Killing

Saving the Substratum: Interpreting Kant s First Analogy

Physicalism and Conceptual Analysis * Esa Díaz-León.

Backward Looking Theories, Kant and Deontology

5: Preliminaries to the Argument

PHILOSOPHY (PHIL) Philosophy (PHIL) 1. PHIL 56. Research Integrity. 1 Unit

Consider... Ethical Egoism. Rachels. Consider... Theories about Human Motivations

3 Supplement. Robert Bernasconi

1.3 Target Group 1. One Main Target Group 2. Two Secondary Target Groups 1.4 Objectives 1. Short-Term objectives

Man and the Presence of Evil in Christian and Platonic Doctrine by Philip Sherrard

Pihlström, Sami Johannes.

The Faiths of a Catholic University: Personal or Impersonal?

Good Eats ABSTRACT. Elizabeth Foreman Missouri State University Volume 17, Issue 1

Philosophy Catalog. REQUIREMENTS FOR A MAJOR IN PHILOSOPHY: 9 courses (36 credits)

Strange bedfellows or Siamese twins? The search for the sacred in practical theology and psychology of religion

Transcription:

BETWEEN THE SPECIES Issue IX August 2009 http://cla.calpoly.edu/bts/ Review of Matthew Calarco's Zoographies: The Question of the Animal from Heidegger to Derrida Donald L. Turner Nashville State Community College In Zoographies, Matthew Calarco offers an insightful analysis of anthropocentric trends in recent Continental philosophers Martin Heidegger, Emmanuel Levinas, Giorgio Agamben, and Jacques Derrida, combined with provocative suggestions for advancing beyond the Western tradition s humanistic dead-end thinking on interspecies ethics. An introductory essay situates animal questions within Continental philosophy. It grounds Calarco s argument within the lineage of possibilities opened by Heidegger s critique of modern metaphysical humanism and Derrida s deconstructive analysis of an essentialist, reductionist human-animal binary, and it presents two main theses: that the Continental tradition is pervasively and detrimentally anthropocentric and that the human-animal distinction can and should be abandoned to clear the way for more genuine encounters with other animal species and promote their more appropriate philosophical and political treatment. He contextualizes his argument with references to prominent pro-animal philosophical trends, distinguishing his approach from that of some types of identity politics, by which progressive agendas are divided and vitiated, and 1

from those approaches that rely too heavily on a notion of subjectivity that has problematic blind spots and metaphysical baggage. Unlike Levinas, Slavoj Žižek, and Alain Badiou, who attempt to rethink subjectivity in the wake of Heideggerian and Derridean critiques, Calarco declares his suspicion with ethical and political structures erected on this basis, most of which remain problematically anthropocentric. The first chapter charts the ways Heidegger distinguishes between human beings and other animal species, from his distinction between animal perishing and human death in Being and Time to that between linguistically capable humans and non-linguistic animals in the Letter on Humanism, paying particular attention to a 1929-30 lecture course in which Heidegger designates non-human animals as world-poor and incapable of recognizing entities as such. After clearly presenting the main points of Heidegger s analyses, Calarco begins to question them, looking at, for example, the reductionistic way Heidegger talks of the being of the animal as if animality designates a monolithic structure and not a huge diversity of beings with different kinds of experience, some of which seem quite phenomenologically rich in ways to which Heidegger fails to attend. Though he credits Heidegger with undermining traditional human-animal hierarchies and at least attempting to understand animals on their own terms, Calarco shows that Heidegger s priorities remain anthropocentric inasmuch as Heidegger never really engages animal experience as a primary interest, but always as a means of highlighting the uniqueness of human experience and the kinds of worldly relationships of which, allegedly, only humans are capable. Following the figure of the animal in Heidegger s later writings, Calarco questions Heidegger s placement of Nietzsche and Rilke as final thinkers who merely 2

exhausted the possibilities of metaphysical humanism without transcending the basic framework. He argues, with supporting references to Deleuze and Guattari s philosophy on becoming-animal, that Nietzsche and Rilke hold much more promise for posthumanist and post-anthropocentric philosophy than Heidegger recognizes. The chapter provides both an efficient summary of Heidegger s thinking and forceful challenges to it. Calarco describes possible detours around Heideggerian impasses, beginning to explore what it means to consider non-human animal beings without deploying a clean conceptual line between human and animal being, either in traditional metaphysical form or Heideggerian existential reinscriptions. Subsequent chapters follow suit. The second, dealing with the writings of Emmanuel Levinas, charts two related anthropocentric gestures in Levinas s thinking, the denial that non-human animals can experience themselves as subject to an Other s ethical demand and respond altruistically, and the denial that they can truly provoke this kind of altruistic response in human beings, arguing that the logic of Levinas s account of ethics justifies neither claim. He begins by recounting Levinas s story about Bobby, a stray dog who lived for a while near a Nazi prison camp in which Levinas was held, who earned from Levinas the title of last Kantian in Nazi Germany for his (sort of) willingness to engage the prisoners as subjects deserving respect while their human captors had debased them to the status of inhuman objects. This is the closest Levinas comes to admitting any kind of non-human ethical agency, and he eventually dismisses Bobby with the conclusion that the dog is not really Kantian because he lacked the brain needed to universalize 3

maxims. 1 In contrast, Calarco embraces the possibility that Bobby embodies some brand of ethical or proto-ethical agency, arguing that whether one explains altruism with a selfish gene theory or interprets it at the individual psychological level, Darwinian biological continuism and recent cognitive ethology undermine Levinas s anthropocentric claims that only humans act altruistically. Calarco then illustrates Levinas s claims in Totality and Infinity that the Other who imposes ethical demands must be human, before presenting Levinas s maddening equivocations, when in an interview, he maintains absolute human priority on one hand, while on the other making limited ( One cannot entirely refuse the face of the animal. ) and agnostic ( I cannot say at what moment you have the right to be called a face. I don t know if a snake has a face. ) admissions that could allow an interspecies extension of his ethical framework. Building upon the idea of agnosticism, Calarco suggests that one might remain faithful to the basic Levinasian structure in which ethics involves having one s ego displaced by an encounter that moves one to responsibility, while remaining open to the possibility that such an encounter might occur in ways other than those that serve as Levinas s main examples; one might, for example, be moved by qualities other than the Other s destitution, respond in ways other than giving with both hands, and be provoked by something non-human. Calarco proposes a quasi-levinasian ethical agnosticism that refuses final answers to the question of who or what can impose ethical demands and provides an alternative to the recent and mistaken philosophical obsession with delimiting the criteria of ethical considerability, an activity that, even 1 Emmanuel Levinas, Difficult Freedom, trans. Sean Hand (London: The Althone Press, 1990), 153. 4

when pursued by those sympathetic to animal concerns, is philosophically and politically dubious. Calarco closes the chapter by smartly defending his decision to write a book about animal ethics at all, responding to the possible objection that the agnosticism he defends calls for casting a wider net and not limiting the discussion to animals. His impassioned plea stresses that addressing specific questions about non-human animals is required to disrupt the tradition s entrenched and harmful metaphysical anthropocentrism and to stop the horrors of the modern meat and research machines, and he suggests that his approach might help resolve certain disciplinary skirmishes between pro-animal thinkers, environmentalists, ecofeminists, etc. In the third chapter, Calarco maps the question of the animal through the writings of Giorgio Agamben. It begins with this author s early contentions that the Western philosophical tradition, including Heidegger, remains bound by thinking about the specificity of human experience and the human-animal relationship only in negative terms, as when it locates the key moments in the transition from non-linguistic, nonpolitical animals to linguistic and political human beings in a mystical, ineffable Voice that transcends animality but has not or can not be linguistically articulated. Calarco then delineates Agamben s attempts to think of these moments and of this transition in more positive terms. He explores the difference between the modern solipsistic and pre-social view of the self and Agamben s picture of the self as a linguistic construct. He also considers the contrast between the traditional idea that humans have language while non-human animals do not and Agamben s view that non-human animals are fundamentally and totally immersed in language, while humans are 5

fundamentally deprived of language, beginning in a pre-linguistic state of infancy, marked by openness to the specifically human forms of history, culture, and politics that language eventually confers. Thus, Calarco shows that while Agamben attempts to think differently about the roots and implications of the essential distinction between specifically human modes of being and modes shared with non-human animals, his early work is part of a tradition for which the general need to delineate and separate is unquestioned. As with Heidegger and Levinas, Calarco suggests that empirical ethology undermines Agamben s neat lines of demarcation, and he questions Agamben s apparent assumptions that only humans are linguistic and political creatures and that the political realm only includes humans. The remainder of the chapter focuses on Agamben s more recent work to illustrate Agamben's increasing attention to problems that accompany attempts to cleanly distinguish the human from the animal. Here, Agamben contends that such delineations lie at the root of many interhuman political problems insofar as exclusion and oppression proceed on the back of a human / animal distinction, where certain qualities are identified as animal and then attributed to the marginalized human group to justify their subordination. Building on this, Calarco draws on Agamben s idea of the anthropological machine to indicate the structures that must be dismantled on the way to a more relational ontology and a more inclusive political order. The final chapter begins with an outline of the importance of animal questions for Jacques Derrida, starting with a lucid and succinct presentation of how deconstruction works with the human-animal distinction a point to which Derrida returned repeatedly illuminating how the human-animal binary opposition obscures differences, 6

pretending to recognize two cleanly and simply differentiated homogenous groups in what is actually a plethora of different types of being. Following this presentation of Derrida s deconstructive critique, Calarco explores Derrida s more positive (but not fully articulated or developed) ethical and political strategies. Inspired by Derrida s discussion of scientific and horticultural abuses, a powerful section explores the value of comparing the mind-boggling amounts of violence practiced in factory farming with the Holocaust, arguing that to deny a priori any possibility that the two situations should be compared on the grounds that humans deserve special standing simply by virtue of species membership is to commit an anthropocentric fallacy that withstands neither scientific nor ethical critique. The next section analyzes the proto-ethical demand that precedes moral assessments and political policies, presenting the way Derrida reads Jeremy Bentham s famous question, Can they suffer? to highlight not shared capacity among human and non-human animals, per the traditional interpretation, but, in line with a Levinasian dynamic, a shared incapacity and experience of susceptibility to suffering affliction. This is followed by an analysis of Derrida s ruminations on an encounter during which his cat saw him naked to show that the kinds of self-reflection and responsibility that protoethical encounters command is provoked not only by exposure to the other animal s suffering, but by revelations of other qualities as well, such as inscrutability or cognizance. In contrast with thinkers such as Peter Singer and Tom Regan, who advocate extending established humanistic ethical systems to include non-human animals, Calarco opens the next section by affirming Derrida s suspicion as to the efficacy of existing 7

moral and political frameworks for handling and promoting the kinds of ethical imperatives at stake in inter-species relationships these frameworks being tainted by problematic notions of subjectivity, dubious value hierarchies, and a compulsion for exclusionary line-drawing. Drawing on Derrida s idea of carnophallologocentrism, Calarco construes these modern humanist juridical and exclusionary elements as quasiinvisible constraints that preclude the kinds of ontological and ethical considerations that interspecies relationships require, marking a failure of imagination that mistakenly attempts to extend a system that should be cast aside. With reference to Derrida s article Eating Well, this section includes a penetrating analysis of the status of vegetarianism with reference to deconstruction. Here, Calarco problematizes any good conscience one might hope to achieve by adopting vegetarianism, emphasizing both the stricter demands of veganism and the fact that any currently possible human diet in modern industrial society will involve harm to animal life a situation requiring not a simple decision that allows complacency, but a continually vigilant striving for an ideal, the full realization of which is ruled out from the start. In the final section of the chapter, Calarco notes that even after Derrida, the tentacles of anthropocentrism reach broadly through numerous disciplines and institutions, requiring extensive historical and genealogical analysis. He argues that while Derrida s work is helpful for showing that the limit between humanity and animality is not as sharp or simply drawn as the tradition would like to think, it is limited by its retention of line drawing (albeit more tentative and complex) and ultimately fails to decisively challenge the metaphysical anthropocentrism of the Western tradition, offering 8

nothing to replace the reductive binary human-animal opposition that Derrida so thoroughly problematizes. In the forceful closing pages, Calarco outlines an alternative ontological vision, inspired by Nietzschean and Deleuzean materialism, to rival the traditional human / animal distinction that Derrida frustratingly refuses to abandon, driving home the central thesis that the human-animal distinction should be surrendered for the benefit of other animals. Calarco s book has much to offer a broad range of readers. The author has a gift for explaining complex ideas clearly, so that readers unschooled in these thinkers but sympathetic to their broader phenomenological, cultural, and ethical trends can follow the argument; he also explains things concisely, so as not to be tedious for readers who are more familiar with the material. With unwavering focus, he illuminates the many ways that anthropocentrism runs, sometimes subtly, through recent Continental philosophy, and he offers insightful and creative suggestions for modes of thought and practice that exceed these anthropocentric limitations. Throughout the work, Calarco skillfully bridges the gaps between Continental and analytic philosophy, situating his points with reference to prominent lines of utilitarian and rights-based Anglo-American pro-animal approaches, and between philosophy and other disciplines, supporting his arguments with biology, cognitive ethology, and the kinds of scientific empirical references that are sometimes missing in philosophical speculation. On a critical note, though part of the book s success is its succinctness, certain arguments might have been strengthened had Calarco analyzed a few additional texts, such as certain of Heideggerian lecture courses before Being and Time, where he describes animal worlds, including that of the snail, in ways that might have further 9

illuminated Calarco s observance that Heidegger s work becomes increasingly severe in positing abyssal ruptures between human and non-human animal being. He might also have considered some of Levinas s (especially later) work dealing with theology, given the role of such concerns in fueling Levinas s humanism. In a related point, while Calarco s summaries of basic ideas and terminology in the authors he investigates are clear and informative, occasionally a term is introduced that might have been well served with additional explanation and contextualization; for example, onto-theology and the figure of the event are introduced in a way that seems to assume an audience familiar with how these ideas function in the thinkers who use them, but many readers might need more information to fully absorb the strong points Calarco makes along these lines. These minor considerations do not undermine the general success of Calarco s impressive work but perhaps suggest additional valuable paths to pursue, by which his compelling arguments might be extended and deepened. In any event, the clearly and passionately argued Zoographies is a definitive exposition of the anthropocentrism in the philosophers it discusses. An important addition to the vigorous discussion of animality taking place in contemporary Continental philosophy, it suggests implications for a range of disciplines involved in the burgeoning fields that constitute current animal studies. 10