Epicurean Prolepsis. The Open Binghamton (The ORB) Binghamton University

Similar documents
Is Epicurus a Direct Realist?

Hellenistic Philosophy

World without Design: The Ontological Consequences of Natural- ism , by Michael C. Rea.

Class #14: October 13 Gödel s Platonism

In Defense of Radical Empiricism. Joseph Benjamin Riegel. Chapel Hill 2006

Nagel, T. The View from Nowhere. New York: Oxford University Press, 1986.

Book Reviews 69. LariyJ. Waggle Illinois State University

One previous course in philosophy, or the permission of the instructor.

What Does Academic Skepticism Presuppose? Arcesilaus, Carneades, and the Argument with Stoic Epistemology

Varieties of Apriority

III Knowledge is true belief based on argument. Plato, Theaetetus, 201 c-d Is Justified True Belief Knowledge? Edmund Gettier

Title II: The CAPE International Conferen Philosophy of Time )

Coordination Problems

What does Nature mean?

The British Empiricism

Contents EMPIRICISM. Logical Atomism and the beginnings of pluralist empiricism. Recap: Russell s reductionism: from maths to physics

Philosophies of Happiness. Appendix 8: Epicurus: Mental Pleasures, Katastematic and Kinetic

Philosophy 125 Day 1: Overview

Russell s Problems of Philosophy

- We might, now, wonder whether the resulting concept of justification is sufficiently strong. According to BonJour, apparent rational insight is

The Five Skandhas. In Buddhism, one of the ways of categorizing these various components is into what we call the five skandhas.

PHI 1700: Global Ethics

FREEDOM OF CHOICE. Freedom of Choice, p. 2

Perceiving Abstract Objects

1/12. The A Paralogisms

Philosophical Perspectives, 16, Language and Mind, 2002 THE AIM OF BELIEF 1. Ralph Wedgwood Merton College, Oxford

PHILOSOPHY OF KNOWLEDGE & REALITY W E E K 3 : N A T U R E O F R E A L I T Y

Moral Argumentation from a Rhetorical Point of View

Philosophy of Science PHIL 241, MW 12:00-1:15

1 What is conceptual analysis and what is the problem?

Law as a Social Fact: A Reply to Professor Martinez

Scientific Progress, Verisimilitude, and Evidence

Philosophy 5340 Epistemology. Topic 6: Theories of Justification: Foundationalism versus Coherentism. Part 2: Susan Haack s Foundherentist Approach

The nature of consciousness underlying existence William C. Treurniet and Paul Hamden, July, 2018

Philosophy 125 Day 13: Overview

Glossary (for Constructing the World)

1/10. The Fourth Paralogism and the Refutation of Idealism

Qué es la filosofía? What is philosophy? Philosophy

Fundamentals of Metaphysics

COOPER VS HADOT: ON THE NATURE OF HELLENISTIC THERAPEUTIC PHILOSOPHY

The Epistemology of the Cyrenaic School Voula Tsouna Cambridge University Press, Cambridge pp.

Each copy of any part of a JSTOR transmission must contain the same copyright notice that appears on the screen or printed page of such transmission.

Direct Realism and the Brain-in-a-Vat Argument by Michael Huemer (2000)

Naturalized Epistemology. 1. What is naturalized Epistemology? Quine PY4613

Introductory Kant Seminar Lecture

the aim is to specify the structure of the world in the form of certain basic truths from which all truths can be derived. (xviii)

what makes reasons sufficient?

Verificationism. PHIL September 27, 2011

Ayer on the criterion of verifiability

Zeno and Stoic Consistency

KANT, MORAL DUTY AND THE DEMANDS OF PURE PRACTICAL REASON. The law is reason unaffected by desire.

Comments on Carl Ginet s

Are There Reasons to Be Rational?

Saving the Substratum: Interpreting Kant s First Analogy

INTUITION AND CONSCIOUS REASONING

Semantic Foundations for Deductive Methods

OSSA Conference Archive OSSA 3

Faults and Mathematical Disagreement

20 TH CENTURY PHILOSOPHY [PHIL ], SPRING 2017

Testimony and Moral Understanding Anthony T. Flood, Ph.D. Introduction

24.01 Classics of Western Philosophy

Van Fraassen: Arguments Concerning Scientific Realism

Remarks on the philosophy of mathematics (1969) Paul Bernays

SAMPLE COURSE OUTLINE PHILOSOPHY AND ETHICS GENERAL YEAR 11

4/30/2010 cforum :: Moderator Control Panel

Nagel, Naturalism and Theism. Todd Moody. (Saint Joseph s University, Philadelphia)

Moral Objectivism. RUSSELL CORNETT University of Calgary

Conference on the Epistemology of Keith Lehrer, PUCRS, Porto Alegre (Brazil), June


A Defense of the Significance of the A Priori A Posteriori Distinction. Albert Casullo. University of Nebraska-Lincoln

Subjective Logic: Logic as Rational Belief Dynamics. Richard Johns Department of Philosophy, UBC

In Search of the Ontological Argument. Richard Oxenberg

Welcome back to our third and final lecture on skepticism and the appearance

John Locke. An Essay Concerning Human Understanding

Russell s Problems of Philosophy

K.V. LAURIKAINEN EXTENDING THE LIMITS OF SCIENCE

Humanities 3 V. The Scientific Revolution

NICHOLAS J.J. SMITH. Let s begin with the storage hypothesis, which is introduced as follows: 1

Putnam: Meaning and Reference

Important dates. PSY 3360 / CGS 3325 Historical Perspectives on Psychology Minds and Machines since David Hume ( )

Nature and its Classification

Philosophy 125 Day 4: Overview

Intro to Philosophy. Review for Exam 2

Frege and Russell on Names and Descriptions Naïve theories

Understanding Truth Scott Soames Précis Philosophy and Phenomenological Research Volume LXV, No. 2, 2002

GREAT PHILOSOPHERS: Thomas Reid ( ) Peter West 25/09/18

1. Introduction. Against GMR: The Incredulous Stare (Lewis 1986: 133 5).

All philosophical debates not due to ignorance of base truths or our imperfect rationality are indeterminate.

Philosophy 428M Topics in the History of Philosophy: Hume MW 2-3:15 Skinner Syllabus

The Paradox of the stone and two concepts of omnipotence

spring 05 topics in philosophy of mind session 7

UNIVERSITY OF MALTA THE MATRICULATION EXAMINATION ADVANCED LEVEL

Resemblance Nominalism and counterparts

Revelation, Humility, and the Structure of the World. David J. Chalmers

1/8. Descartes 3: Proofs of the Existence of God

Kevin Scharp, Replacing Truth, Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2013, At 300-some pages, with narrow margins and small print, the work

How Not to Defend Metaphysical Realism (Southwestern Philosophical Review, Vol , 19-27)

Summary Kooij.indd :14

Philosophy 427 Intuitions and Philosophy. Russell Marcus Hamilton College Fall 2011

Transcription:

Binghamton University The Open Repository @ Binghamton (The ORB) The Society for Ancient Greek Philosophy Newsletter 12-29-1982 Epicurean Prolepsis David Glidden University of California, Riverside, glidden@ucr.edu Follow this and additional works at: https://orb.binghamton.edu/sagp Part of the Ancient History, Greek and Roman through Late Antiquity Commons, Ancient Philosophy Commons, and the History of Philosophy Commons Recommended Citation Glidden, David, "Epicurean Prolepsis" (1982). The Society for Ancient Greek Philosophy Newsletter. 109. https://orb.binghamton.edu/sagp/109 This Article is brought to you for free and open access by The Open Repository @ Binghamton (The ORB). It has been accepted for inclusion in The Society for Ancient Greek Philosophy Newsletter by an authorized administrator of The Open Repository @ Binghamton (The ORB). For more information, please contact ORB@binghamton.edu.

V 'yb b ^ ξ University of California, Riverside 92521 For those of you, dear members of the SAGP, who are not in a position to examine what I have already written on prolepsis ("Epicurean Semantics," in press) nor to go through the draft of the longer work I am writing on that subject, I have prepared an abbreviated summary of my views, an outline of the most important points, which once committed to memory will be an aid to your understanding my lecture in Philadelphia on December 29th. We require a comprehensive grasp of the topic, more than an examination of details There are precious few texts which can provide reliable information about Epicurean prolepsis From what has survived of Epicurus* own writings there are just three examples of prolepsis, which are mentioned but not discussed, in connection with our knowledge of the gods, of justice, and of time with the last being a case where a prolepsis is said not to be relevant In book 28 of the Peri Physeos there is a mention of the epistemic role of prolepsis, but the context is fragmentary and interpretation difficult And in the theoretical section opening the Letter to Herodotus scholars generally agree that prolepsis is being discussed, but that term is conspicuously absent from the discussion. Among Epicureans, Lucretius provides no discussion of prolepsis in the epistemic section of book 4 nor does he give us any examples of prolepsis, unless we translate *notitia* in that way, which policy cannot be adopted uniformly or without prejudicing the question. The helpful Diogenes of Oenoanda is not helpful here. And Philodemus raises more difficulties than he solves, because Philoderaus is an apologist for Epicureanism in the debates with the Stoics and is consequently prone to using Stoic vocabulary, which is especially

glidden, ρ 2 evident in his Rhetorica and IDe Signis. The Stoics1 own doctrine of prolepsis as part of their elaborate conceptual psychology infects the doxographical literature, as well as the judgment of some scholars who accept the Stoicized reports of Epicurean prolepseis to conclude that the two schools in this case made use of the same conceptual device On the face of it that is most unlikely, given the differences between the two theories of psychology and knowledge, the one being elegantly elaborate and the other spartanly simple. When one thinks of the details of Stoic theory -- phantasia, katalepsis, koinai ennoiai, lekta together with the subtleties of their physics and logic in particular their logic of conditionals * one can fathom the distance between the Stoa and the Garden and appreciate that intellectually the Epicureans were always seen as country cousins. Indeed the most sophisticated reports of Epicurean doctrine come from Stoicized sources, from Cicero to Sextus. What these same sources say about Epicurean prolepsis is always from a Stoic perspective, even when the author (Diogenes Laertius, Cicero) is trying to be fair. Diogenes Laertius1 report of Epicurean prolepsis is painfully groping, looking for the right Stoic expressions to describe the device: "By prolepsis they mean a kind of katalepsis or right opinion or concept or universal thought ( consensus omnium ) stored in the mind --that is, the memory of a frequent appearance from the outside." (D.L. X 33) Diogenes * examples should be no less suspect: "As soon as man is spoken of, straightaway due to prolepsis his typos too is thought of ( noeitai ) with the sensory faculties leading the way." The expression *noeitait arouses my suspicions as does the ensuing sentence: "What primarily underlies every word is

glidden, p. 3 evident and we should not have started out to seek what is sought had we not already recognized it " What seems evident to me is that Diogenes is trying to redeem his clumsy, anachronistic account by aping two lines from the Letter to Herodotus and in doing so to subvert the doctrine, substituting word for utterance1 and suggesting that prolepsis initiates investigations, as it does for the Stoics, where Epicurus is talking about settling disputes, obviating further apodeixis by providing the necessary evidence. Cicero, in my view, is a much more careful historian of philosophy and indeed a good philosopher, but what he says about Epicurean prolepsis has difficulties of its own. I have no quarrel with his remark that Epicurus was the first to use the word prolepsis nor even that this prolepsis informs us that the gods are blessed and immortal. After all, Epicurus says much the same thing about the gods in his Letter to Menoeceus (123-124). Furthermore, Epicurus says that the truth about the gods is a koine noesis, and Cicero reports that accurately enough. But unfortunately Epicurus does not tell us how such a koine noesis might be derived from a prolepsis. Listening to Cicero would have us believe that the Epicureans derive their information concerning the character of the gods from a universal consensus, natural intuitions ("insitas eorura vel potius innatas cognitiones"), information which is stamped on the mind ("eadem insculpsit in mentibus ut eos aeternos et beatos habereraus" De Nat. Peor. I 43-45). And Cicero goes on to maintain that it is the universal nature of this consensus which makes it necessarily true. For my mind there is too much Stoicism in Cicero s account to allow me to accept this testimony lock, stock, and bagel, especially when one considers that Cicero glosses over the difference

glidden, p. 4 between apprehension of the gods1 existence, using the mind as a sixth sense what Epicurus calls epibole tes dianoias and recognition of the gods* character, which I take to be the role of prolepsis«in short, we can only make selective use of the testimonies of Diogenes Laertius and Cicero, not to mention the others What we select to accept requires an independent understanding of the Epicurean doctrine We do not even know what role prolepsis is supposed to play in Epicurean theory, though sources agree that role was discussed in Epicurus* Canon The criteria listed by Diogenes and Cicero are threefold, consisting of aisthesis, prolepsis, and pathe though Epicurus only used the word kriterion to refer to the sense faculties But this threefold division is more like a troika, with each of the three going off in a different direction. It is not a criterion of truth, because the pathe are hitched up as vehicles for choice and avoidance And aisthesis is represented as the criterion for knowledge, although Epicurus himself listed both aistheseis and pathe as having this role. According to Diogenes and Cicero, then. Epicurean prolepsis has neither a judgmental role to play, which they say is the job of aisthesis, nor an ethical role to play, the job of the pathe. So, what is the role prolepsis is supposed to have in the Epicurean Canon? If the Epicureans were Stoics the answer would be easy enough, since the Stoics divided philosophy into three parts adding logic to the parts recognized by the Epicureans: natural philosophy and ethics Our sources are emphatic that the Epicureans did not give logic a separate status. But regarding the Stoics, Diogenes Laertius reports that some divide logic into two parts. One is called peri kanonon kai kriterion and consists of the phantasiai, while the other constitutes t_o horikon,

glidden, ρ 5 definitions which are the work of common notions. Stoic ennoiai. To a Stoicizing historian this might seem to be the role of prolepsis in the Epicurean troika, but it couldn t be, since the testimony is adamant that the Epicureans denied the value of definitions. Furthermore, the Canon which is said to provide this troika is also said not to have an independent status, independent of natural philosophy. It is a real possibility, then, that the troika listed by Diogenes and Cicero has been Stoicized, and that whatever trichotomy may be present in Epicurus Canon concerned a threefold division of perceptual evidence, consisting of the evidence of the sense faculties ( aistheseis ), the evidence of the experience of pleasure and pain ( the pathe ), and something else. Diogenes even suggests what this something else might be and Epicurus confirms it: the sixth sense, epibole tes dianoias, where the mind itself is sensitive to especially fine atomic images which penetrate it and trigger recognitions. At this point. Epicurean prolepsis as a separate criterion, in the Stoic sense, seems to disappear from Epicurus Canon. With astonishing unanimity, scholars put prolepsis back into the Canon and into a pivotal role by reading it into Herodotus 37-38, where Epicurus prefaces his arguments on natural philosophy with a discussion of his theory of evidence. The word prolepsis is missing from the discussion, but this might possibly be an inconspicuous omission, if one agrees with Sedley s suggestion that Epicirus had not yet invented the word, since the only mention of the term in the Letter to Herodotus at #72 could easily be a later addition. And in the passage in question the term proton ennoema seems to be a convenient standin. What is most compelling about this interpretation is that Cicero, Sextus, and Diogenes

glidden, ρ 6 Laertius, among others, all make a claim about Epicurean prolepsis which is echoed in this passage: namely, that having a prolepsis is necessary for conducting any empirical investigation or answering any problem of natural philosophy: First of all, Herodotus, it is necessary to grasp what underlies our utterances [ ta hypotetagmena tois phthongois...dei eilephenai ], so that by referring to them we may have a means of judging our opinions, inquiries, and problems, and not give endless demonstrations which leave everything undetermined or use empty utterances For the primary thought for every utterance must be seen [ anagke gar to proton ennoema kath* hekaston phthongon blepesthai ] and there be no need of further proof [ apodeixeos ], if we are to have a point of reference for inquiries, problems, and opinions. Wherefore it is necessary to keep a close watch over our perceptions [ aistheseis ], that is to say over our current apprehendings (whether they be mental or any of the sense organs) [ tas parousas epibolas eite dianoias eitht hotou depote ton kriterion ], as well as over our present feelings [ ta hyparchonta pathe ], so that we may be able to infer what awaits confirmation and what is not evident. (Her. 37-38, von der Muehll) Without arguing in detail, let me simply point out that if what turns out to be prolepsis is being discussed here, prolepseis are not exclusively what underlies our utterances. The primary bit of information, or Frotofl ennoema, for every utterance must encompass more than prolepsis in any case. What underlies our utterances is to settle questions of natural philosophy, rather than initiate them. The first part of this passage

glidden, ρ. 7 does not present an Epicurean answer to the paradox of inquiry, but rather an answer to the question of what settles investigations: namely, the point of reference which our utterances are about. And the second half of the passage tells us how to find that point of reference by lisitng the trichotomy which Epicurus mentions elsewhere: the five sense faculties, the sixth sense, and the feelings of pleasure and pain. It is the empirical evidence derived in this way which will put an end to demonstrations, which will decide questions, which will give reference to our utterances, and most importantly will itself not need demonstration, because, as Epicurus was notorious for saying, perceptual evidence is always true. Now we do not even need to read prolepsis into this passage to make good sense of it. And in any case, the Stoic role for prolepsis, which is analogous to that of the ennoiai, the initial concepts which provide a starting point for inquiry along the line of their definitions, defining what it is one is looking for, this Stoic use of prolepsis is not what Epicurus is talking about in this passage. Defined concepts won t answer empirical questions. Consequently, if prolepseis are included in our passage, then their role is clearly an evidential one, providing some reference point about the nature of things, in the way that aisthesis does. Like aisthesis, then, prolepseis must make claims about the world, not just provide concepts with which to make those claims, something the Stoics were quite concerned about, the Epicureans not. Epicurus own examples support the point that prolepseis are evidential claims. As we have seen, one such prolepsis is that the gods are blessed and immortal. When Epicurus makes this claim in Menoeceus 123-124, he contrast prolepseis with false judgments about the character of the gods. And when he mentions the prolepsis of justice, the author

glidden, p. 8 of the Kyriai Doxai presumably Epicurus presents the claim that justice is what serves the needs of social intercourse. Apparently, prolepseis take the form of claims about the way things are. These claims are facts about the world, not mere opinions. So prolepsis enjoys the evidential status aisthesis does. Consequently I see no foundation for the most common interpretation, that Epicurean prolepsis is some kind of conceptual device. The most popular version of this thesis has been that prolepseis are the meanings of individual words, as they might also have been for the Stoics, individual concepts which when strung together in the appropriate way would provide meaning to sentences, constituting lekta Now I have argued against this interpretation in "Epicurean Semantics, where I pointed out that we should take the evidence of Plutarch and Sextus seriously, that there is nothing in Epicureanism comparable to what the Stoics claimed was the significance ( t_o semainomenon ) of voiced sounds. The Epicureans made do with just voiced sounds, or utterances, and the events happening in the world which those utterances referred to. Attention to everything which the Epicureans say about the origin and character of language suggests that utterances label states of the world, or else they are vacuous sounds. The prolepseis, then, are not vehicles of meaning, but conveyances of evidence making claims on the world, not making sense of our vocabulary. Some would maintain that nevertheless prolepseis are mental representations, though what they represent are complex ideas about the world. This too seems unlikely. The authority of perception and the authority of our feelings would be called into question, with disastrous consequences for Epicurean empiricism, were it the case that what it is

glidden, p. 9 we see or how it is we feel were somehow dependent upon our own subjective perspective and viewpoint The Epicureans were adamant on the mechanical, automatic character of perception and feeling, which somehow guaranteed the information we received from our senses was information about the state of the world, as opposed to our state of mind The purely referential character of what it is we perceive and the pleasure and pain we feel is what guarantees the epistemic authority of aisthesis and pathe Now it appears not just from secondary sources but also from what Epicurus states in book 28 of his Peri Physeos that prolepsis also enjoys such evidential authority. This would require that the claims of prolepsis have the same referential fixity as that enjoyed by aisthesis and the pathe. Indeed, it is only if this is so that prolepseis could possibly be construed as at least part of what underlies our utterances, as part of the proton ennoema behind every utterance, which is the point of reference for all investigation. We conclude that prolepsis for the Epicureans makes evidential claims on the nature of reality. But we still need to know how such prolepseis are generated and what sorts of events in the world they describe. To answer either question is to offer conjecture. One of the controversies in the literature concerns whether Epicurean prolepsis is restricted to abstract entities, as the example of justice would seem to suggest, or to individual things, as Diogenes examples suggest and the example of the character of the gods speaks in favor of. What complicates conjecture is the very real possibility that over time the Epicureans may have changed their mind on the range of prolepseis. Both Diogenes and Cicero talk of revisions of the younger Epicureans in this context, and Plutarch and Sextus make similar suggestions. It could be the case that at first

glidden, p 10 prolepsis played a rather minor role with a restricted range and over time the range extended From the examples we do have in Epicurus it seems that prolepsis is concerned with the character of a thing or a state of affairs what it is to be just, as opposed to what the instantiations of justice are, what the character of the gods is, as opposed to who the gods are. Given Epicurean epistemic realism, these claims on the character of some thing or state must be seen as claims on the world, so that prolepsis, like aisthesis for a realist, is ambiguous between the psychological act of apprehension and the content discerned, some feature of the world. In the case of prolepsis what is discerned should be some abiding character in things, as opposed to some temporary appearance. Not surprisingly. Epicurean atomism suggests the need for these two different kinds of information. Since all that exists are simply atoms moving in the void, on any occasion what one perceives is, as it were, a time slice of a continuous process ----so the apple looks green now. It is also the case that certain atomic configurations are relatively abiding in any particular cosmos. And so in our world water has a particular atomic arrangement and iron another. Information about the one, the state of current appearances, is not the same as information about the other, the relatively abiding state of nature. The history of PlatoTs Forms and Aristotle*s natural kinds should have made Epicurus more sensitive to this issue than Democritus would have been, and in any case this sensitivity to the abiding structures in nature is certainly obvious from the De Rerum Natura. There is clearly a need for information about these abiding structures in natural philosophy and this need can be satisfied in part by Epicurean inference and confirmation

glidden, ρ 11 But it also appears that we can recognize the abiding character in perceived things and states We recognize justice to be what serves social interest, the gods to be blessed and immortal Such recognitions are part of the evidence, not part of our inferences And prolepsis, it seems, constitutes such recognitions The question how prolepsis differs from aisthesis becomes, on my view, mostly a matter of degree. On a strict view of perception we perceive only sights and sounds, smells and tastes: colors, shapes, specific noises and other such primitive phenomena. To perceive a man or a tower in the distance would then require a more elaborate psychological process. At what point this more elaborate process becomes something other than perception is difficult to say. Broadly speaking, recognizing a tower in the distance remains aisthesis, not being an inference. But it could well be that at some point Epicurus or Epicureans wanted to discriminate some more sophisticated recognitions as the work of prolepsis, possibly recognitions requiring repeated experiences so as to make familiar lingering characteristics or forms. A passage in Philoderaus1 De. Signis claims there is a prolepsis for human nature, just as Diogenes Laertius suggested that there is a persistent form recognized throughout the instances of accumulated experience of seeing a man or seeing a horse. Yet judging from Epicurus own examples, perception seems to take on the responsibility for recognizing natural structures, leaving prolepsis for the more abstract characteristics requiring more than the operation of the sense organs but the mind as well, the case of justice, the case of the gods1 character. If we could determine how prolepseis arise, we might be in a position to determine their range. As I understand prolepsis, it cannot

glidden, p. 12 be the work of any particular sense organ, but it is a perceptual recognition of the mind as a result of the work of the separate sense organs But if we assume it is the work of dianoia, it is still something we perceive in the world, not a rational reconstruction or hypothesis Here the case of the gods is instructive. The mind, operating as a sixth sense sensitive to especially fine eidola, perceives the gods, just as it perceives phantoms in dreams. I suggest that this same apprehension of the mind, epibole tes dianoias, can perceive persistent characteristics characterizing the things it or the other sense faculties perceive, the sorts of things these things are. And so we have a prolepsis that the gods are blessed and immortal, over and above having a vision of them. Presumably these prolepseis are formed in the mind as a result of repeated experiences, allowing us to get acquainted with the persistent characters of things. As accumulated information, these prolepseis would be common to all familiar with the same sorts of experiences. My best guess is that in Epicurean theory prolepsis was first understood as a type of epibole tes dianoias, and the two remained associated with each other as perceptual activities of dianoia, sometimes taking in mental visions, sometimes recognizing natural kinds and characters. In the case of the gods it would have been easy to confuse the two activities as Cicero did. And it is easy to understand how the recognition of natural types could come to be identified with primitive concepts, which the Stoics wanted. I hope, dear members of the SAGP, that this synopsis of ray views will help show you the way to ataraxia, if not Philadelphia.