On Russell's "brief but notorious flirtation with phenomenalism"

Similar documents
Ayer on the argument from illusion

Contents EMPIRICISM. Logical Atomism and the beginnings of pluralist empiricism. Recap: Russell s reductionism: from maths to physics

Perception and Mind-Dependence: Lecture 2

THE REFUTATION OF PHENOMENALISM

Summary of Sensorama: A Phenomenalist Analysis of Spacetime and Its Contents

17. Tying it up: thoughts and intentionality

VI. CEITICAL NOTICES.

Has Logical Positivism Eliminated Metaphysics?

Examining the nature of mind. Michael Daniels. A review of Understanding Consciousness by Max Velmans (Routledge, 2000).

ON QUINE, ANALYTICITY, AND MEANING Wylie Breckenridge

Fr. Copleston vs. Bertrand Russell: The Famous 1948 BBC Radio Debate on the Existence of God

Direct Realism and the Brain-in-a-Vat Argument by Michael Huemer (2000)

Review Tutorial (A Whirlwind Tour of Metaphysics, Epistemology and Philosophy of Religion)

Sufficient Reason and Infinite Regress: Causal Consistency in Descartes and Spinoza. Ryan Steed

Does the Skeptic Win? A Defense of Moore. I. Moorean Methodology. In A Proof of the External World, Moore argues as follows:

Primary and Secondary Qualities. John Locke s distinction between primary and secondary qualities of bodies has

Divisibility, Logic, Radical Empiricism, and Metaphysics

Verificationism. PHIL September 27, 2011

Holtzman Spring Philosophy and the Integration of Knowledge

PHILOSOPHY 4360/5360 METAPHYSICS. Methods that Metaphysicians Use

Philosophy 5340 Epistemology Topic 4: Skepticism. Part 1: The Scope of Skepticism and Two Main Types of Skeptical Argument

How Do We Know Anything about Mathematics? - A Defence of Platonism

Introduction. I. Proof of the Minor Premise ( All reality is completely intelligible )

PHILOSOPHY A.S. UNIT 2 PAPER, JANUARY 2009 SUGGESTED ANSWERS TO SELECTED QUESTIONS

Each copy of any part of a JSTOR transmission must contain the same copyright notice that appears on the screen or printed page of such transmission.

To appear in The Journal of Philosophy.

In Defense of Radical Empiricism. Joseph Benjamin Riegel. Chapel Hill 2006

Précis of Empiricism and Experience. Anil Gupta University of Pittsburgh

Reviews WITTGENSTEIN, CRITIC OF RUSSELL. Russell Wahl. English and Philosophy / Idaho State U Pocatello, id 83209, usa

Three Fundamentals of the Introceptive Philosophy

THE TWO-DIMENSIONAL ARGUMENT AGAINST MATERIALISM AND ITS SEMANTIC PREMISE

Saving the Substratum: Interpreting Kant s First Analogy

Realism and its competitors. Scepticism, idealism, phenomenalism

SENSE-DATA G. E. Moore

Comments on Scott Soames, Philosophical Analysis in the Twentieth Century, volume I

Nature and its Classification

Ayer on the criterion of verifiability

LOCKE STUDIES Vol ISSN: X

Every simple idea has a simple impression, which resembles it; and every simple impression a correspondent idea

BOOK REVIEWS. 259 H. C. STEVENS. University of Chicago.

1/12. The A Paralogisms

Charles Hartshorne argues that Kant s criticisms of Anselm s ontological

Ockham s Razor in Russell s Philosophy John L. Taylor

BonJour Against Materialism. Just an intellectual bandwagon?

BERTRAND RUSSELL, as Philosopher

Abstract: Neutral monism is the view that each particular is intrinsically neither

How Not to Defend Metaphysical Realism (Southwestern Philosophical Review, Vol , 19-27)

Behavior and Other Minds: A Response to Functionalists

Epistemology: A Contemporary Introduction to The Theory of Knowledge, by Robert Audi. New York: Routledge, 2011.

MY PURPOSE IN THIS BOOK IS TO PRESENT A

Craig on the Experience of Tense

Philosophy 5340 Epistemology. Topic 6: Theories of Justification: Foundationalism versus Coherentism. Part 2: Susan Haack s Foundherentist Approach

General Philosophy. Dr Peter Millican,, Hertford College. Lecture 4: Two Cartesian Topics


Experiences Don t Sum

ALTERNATIVE SELF-DEFEAT ARGUMENTS: A REPLY TO MIZRAHI

Varieties of Apriority

1/9. The First Analogy

Elements of Mind (EM) has two themes, one major and one minor. The major theme is

Presentism and Physicalism 1!

Martin s case for disjunctivism

The Problem with Complete States: Freedom, Chance and the Luck Argument

Thoughts, Things, and Theories

KANT S EXPLANATION OF THE NECESSITY OF GEOMETRICAL TRUTHS. John Watling

III Knowledge is true belief based on argument. Plato, Theaetetus, 201 c-d Is Justified True Belief Knowledge? Edmund Gettier

Ayer and Quine on the a priori

Think by Simon Blackburn. Chapter 7b The World

Constructing the World

PHILOSOPHY 5340 EPISTEMOLOGY

Postscript to Plenitude of Possible Structures (2016)

Quine s Naturalized Epistemology, Epistemic Normativity and the. Gettier Problem

The Metaphysical Status of Tractarian Objects 1

William James described pragmatism as a method of approaching

Adam Smith and the Limits of Empiricism

proper construal of Davidson s principle of rationality will show the objection to be misguided. Andrew Wong Washington University, St.

Think by Simon Blackburn. Chapter 7c The World

Vagueness. Bertrand Russell

The Philosophy of Physics. Physics versus Metaphysics

Under contract with Oxford University Press Karen Bennett Cornell University

Introductory Kant Seminar Lecture

Bertrand Russell has exercised an influence on the course of philosophy in the

5 A Modal Version of the

Please remember to sign-in by scanning your badge Department of Psychiatry Grand Rounds

Van Fraassen: Arguments Concerning Scientific Realism

Wright on response-dependence and self-knowledge

Moral Objectivism. RUSSELL CORNETT University of Calgary

Philosophy Epistemology Topic 5 The Justification of Induction 1. Hume s Skeptical Challenge to Induction

Remarks on the philosophy of mathematics (1969) Paul Bernays

What Must There be to Account for Being?

Saul Kripke, Naming and Necessity

World without Design: The Ontological Consequences of Natural- ism , by Michael C. Rea.

Analyticity, Reductionism, and Semantic Holism. The verification theory is an empirical theory of meaning which asserts that the meaning of a

Testimony and Moral Understanding Anthony T. Flood, Ph.D. Introduction

Idealism. Contents EMPIRICISM. George Berkeley and Idealism. Preview: Hume. Idealism: other versions. Idealism: simplest definition

BOOK REVIEWS. The arguments of the Parmenides, though they do not refute the Theory of Forms, do expose certain problems, ambiguities and

3. Knowledge and Justification

IS GOD "SIGNIFICANTLY FREE?''

Bertrand Russell and the Problem of Consciousness

On the epistemological status of mathematical objects in Plato s philosophical system

Knowledge and Authority

Transcription:

On Russell's "brief but notorious flirtation with phenomenalism" In his recent book entitled Russell, A.J. Ayer claims that Russell in 1914 abandoned the causal theory of perception for a version of phenomenalism. l Ayer says that Russell made no attempt to develop this theory after 1914, and that he tacitly reverted to the causal theory in his later works. It is true that Russell significantly revised his views on perception in 1914, but I hope to show that Russell's revisions did not involve rejection of a causal theory. Russell, by his own admission, changed his views many times during his rich and lengthy philosophical career. Many commentators have made capital of these changes in accusing Russell of incoherence, whereas attentive reading of the works from The Problems of Philosophy (19l2} to H"wnan Knowledge (1948) discloses a unity in the questions handled, along with growth and development in the answers provided. Since Russell did change his theory of perception radically in 1914, one might ask whether my dis~greement with Ayer is merely a verbal dispute about what one calls a causal theory. I do not believe this is the case. In the first place, although the causal theory accepted in 1914 is different from his earlier theory, it is a genuine causal theory in the sense that, like the earlier one, it locates perceptions at the end of causal chains which begin with physical objects. Russell continually emphasized this as a crucial feature of any correct theory of perception. Secondly, there is Ayer's claim that Russell lapses to the earlier theory in his later works. This, I believe, is a mistake. The mistake arises, quite naturally, from the difficulty in understanding how an event (in the early works, a sense-datum or sensibile; and in the later works, sensations or percepts} can be caused by a physical object, when at the same time that event is one of the events out of which the physical object is constructed. When Russell's solution to this problem is grasped it is no longer feasible to attribute a reversion to the pre 1914 theory to him. Accordingly, one of the aims of this paper is to adumbrate Russell's solution. la.j. Ayer, Russell (London: Fontana, 19721, pp. 72~I02. 13

Russell's 1914 works, notably "The Relation between Physics and Sense-Data" and Our Knowledge of the External World,2 conta in suggestions which greatly influenced later versions of phenomenalism such as Carnap's Aufbau. Russell himself admits that in "The Relation between Physics and Sense-Da ta" he was strongly attracted by the possibil tty of interpreting physical objects as structures composed of elements actually experienced. However, in the same paper, he says that he became convinced that this was an impossible programme, and so "gave up the attempt to construct 'matter' out of experienced data alone, and contented [himself] with a picture of the world which fitted physics and perception into a single whole."3 Grover Maxwell refers to this passage when he speaks of Russell's "brief but notorious fl irtation with phenomenal ism in 1914."4 However, as Russell well knew, a flirtation does not constitute an espousal. The 1914 works have been the chief source of those who attribute phenomenalism to Russell in that period. The works are well known, but the passages in which Russell explicitly accepts a causal theory of perception have been surprisingly overlooked. Prior to 1914 Russell accepted a version of the causal theory in which sense-data with which we are acquainted provide the basis for inferences to physical objects. The physical objects, such as tables and chairs, are things which we can know only indirectly, but they are the causes of sense-data. Ayer calls this inference to things a type different from the type of things directly known a "vertical inference", and he characterizes causal theories by their appeal to vertical inference. Only two years after the publication of The FToblems of Philosophy Russell realized something which called for a drastic revision in his theory of perception. At this time Russell was inspired by Whitehead's theory of matter, and was bolstered by the success they had had together in replacing 'inferred entities by logical constructions in FTimipia Mathematica. Russell regarded the use of this technique: "Whenever possible replace inferred entities by logical constructions", as the supreme maxim of scientific philosophizing. He sought to use this method 20ur Knowledge of the External World as a Field for Scientific Method in Philosophy (London: Allen and Unwin, 1926). ThIs was first puollshed in 1914. My references are to the 1926 edition. "The Relation oetween Physics and Sense-Data" was first publ ished in 1914, and was reprinted in Mysticism and Logic (London: Longmans, Green, 1918; New York: Norton, 1929). All page numbers refer to the latter edition. 3My Philosophical Development (New York: Simon and Schuster, 1959), p. 105. 4Bertrand Russell, ed. D.F. Pears (New York: Anchor, 1972), p. 110. 14 to solve problems which arose from the apparent incompatibility between the.knowledge we have of physical objects from our perceptions and the knowledge we have of the same objects through a study of modern physics. Common-sense views of perception tell us that these objects have certain features which they cannot possibly possess if physics is correct. For example, common sense tells us that the surfaces of these objects possess continuity with regard to color and tangibility, whereas physics tells us. that the surfaces are outer layers of gappy systems of colorless particles. While trying to present a coherent picture of the world from the viewpoints of both physics and perception, Russell made a remarkable discovery: There were several novelties in the theory as to our knowledge of the external world which burst upon me on New Year's Day 1914. The most important of these was the theory that space has six dimensions and not only three. s What we ordinarily think of as three-dimensional physical space is made up of points. Each of these points, however, may be considered as a perspective, or point of view, of a perceiver. At each perspective, then, there is a three-dimensional perceptual space which is private to the observer. This three-dimensional space at each point in a three-dimensional space yields a space with six dimensions. The importance of this discovery, which to many must seem eccentric, baroque, or even unintelligible, cannot be overemphasized. Russell had always regarded sense-data as physical entities in as much as they were suitable objects of study for physics. They were, however, private to each perceiver, and their physical location was held to be in the region of the brain of a perceiver. With the recognition of the six-dimensional character of space, the greatest difficulty in considering sense-data as parts of external physical objects was overcome, and the way was made clear for constructing physical objects from sense-data, rather than inferring the existence of those objects which we could never experience. Prior to Russell's realization that a sense-datum could be located in two places, that is, in the private space of an observer, and in the public perspective space, it seemed a mystery that data which are essentially private could provide any reliable information about the world of physics. From this point on Russell was aware of, and repeatedly pointed out in his later works, the two requirements of a satisfactory theory of perception: (1) Ontologically, perceptions are events. Perception is SMy Philosophical Development, p. 105. 15

what happens when one becomes aware of something through his senses. 6 In order to locate these events in space-time and to explain their causal connections with other events, a physical theory is required. (2) From the viewpoint of epistemology, perception is the process of getting to know certain kinds of facts without inference. These facts are the basis of all other empirical knowledge. As Russell says, In considering the reasons for believing in any empirical statement, we cannot escape from perception. '" individual percepts are the basis of all our knowledge, and no method exists by which we can begin with data which are public to many observers.? But the epistemological and ontological aspects of perception are not unrelated. Russell ultimately accepts a causal theory of perception because he believes that, even if the account of the world given by physics were ontologically correct, "Epistemologically, physics might be expected to collapse if perceptions have no external causes."8 The great virtue of Russell's theory is its abllity to provide a unified treatment of both types of problems. Nevertheless, Russell's practice of examining these related questions independently of one another has misled Ayer and others. In "The Relation between Physics and Sense-Data" Russell is concerned with the epistemological aspect of the problem. He is not attempting to argue the truth of the physical account of sense-data which locates them as the effects of physical causes; rather, he assumes the approximate truth of this account. However, he insists that in so far as physics is verifiable, it must be capable of interpretation in terms of sense-data alone, since verification consists always in the occurrence of an expected sense-da~um. Moreover, if sense-data are to constitute a verification of physics, then it must be possible to give an account of physics which is consistent with the information physics gives us, but which exhibits space, time and matter as functions of sense-data. Russell quickly realized that no convincing interpretation of physics could be given merely on the basis of sense-data which were actually experienced. Physics, and even our corrnnon-sense notion of "thing", demand more continuity and stability than the fragmentary actual sense-data provide. Adhering to his principle of never introducing inferred entities 6Human Knowledge: Its Scope and Limits (New York: Simon and Schuster, 1948), p. 203.?Ibid., p. 8 8The Analysis of Mattep (London: Routledge, Kegan Paul, 1927), p. 197. 16 whenever it is possible to do without them, Russell found that the only entities whose existence he must assume in order to connect the world of physics with the world of sense-perception, are entities which are metaphysically similar to sense-data, except that they exist unperceived. Both actual sense-data and those which would be data if observed are called "sensibilia". Unsensed sensibilia differ from Mill's permanent possibilities of sensation, because, whereas unsensed sensibilia are only possible data, they have real, not merely possible, existence. Russell used a principle of analogy to infer that sensibilia exist at perspectives where no perceiver is present. Ayer classifies this inference to unsensed sensibil ia as a "horizontal inference", i.e. an inference which invokes only entities which are of the same type as the entities available to experience. Ayer distinguishes Russell's two theories of perception on the basis of the distinction between horizontal and vertical inferences to the existence of the external world. This distinction characterizes the change in Russell's theory nicely. However, I believe it is a mistake to ide~tify, as Ayer does; the vertical theory with the causal theory and the horizontal theory with phenomenalism. An examination of the 1914 works will enable us to see that Russell rejected phenomenalism, but accepted a horizontal theory of perception which was at the same time a causal theory. In "The Relation between Physics and Sense-Data" the only inferred entities which are required are unsensed sensibilia. All other entities are constructed from sensibilia. Ayer is aware that, as Russell actually presents the construction, he does use vertical inference to other minds when he accepts the testimony of others regarding their own sense-data. This, however, could be eliminated, since the existence of the required sensibilia can be secured on the basis of analogy with experienced data. There is no need to present the details of the construction here. Briefly, what Russell does is to collect data from various perceivers, to fill in gaps with un sensed sensibilia, to use principles of resemblance and continuity, and to adopt the usual assumptions about the velocities of light and sound. From all this he is able to exhibit common-sense "things" as well as physical space and time as functions of our perceptions The "thing", for example, is the class of all its appearances (sensibilia). In this construction the six-dimensional character of space is important because it allows the assignment of each sensibile to two places: the place which is the point of view of which the sensibile is a member, i.e. the place fpom which the sensibile appears; and the place where the 17

"thing" of which the sensibile is a member is located, or the place at which it appears. The place from which the sensibile appears is in the region of the brain of a perceiver. But sensibilia are, after all, the appearances of a "thing", and it is reasonable to say that the "thing" is located at the perspective where the various appearances converge. This perspective need not be a place where a perceiver is present. The ordinary three-dimensional space of physics is constructed by correlating the perceptual and perspective spaces. Nothing in Russell's construction indicates rejection of a causal theory of perception. Russell is concerned here with interpretation and verification of physics on the basis of sense-data, not in the causal origins of these data. His chief interest was to assimilate the physical world to the world of perceptions rather than to explain perceptions in terms of physics. As he points out in The Anatysis of Matter, such an interpretation of physics will tend toward idealism. 9 Thus many passages in Human Knowtedge and The Anatysis of Matter, later works in which Russell explicitly adopts a causal theory, have the same phenomenalistic flavor as the 1914 works. Evidence that Russell continued to accept a causal theory in "The Relation between Physics and Sense-Data" is found in the following passage, in which he is discussin9 illusions: '" it would appear that abnormal sense-data, of the kind we regard as deceptive, have intrinsically just the same status as any others, but differ as regards their correlations or causal connections with other "sensibilia" and with "things."io Furthermore, even though Russell does not deal with causal connections in this account, recognition of their importance is one of his motives in constructing physical matter in addition to the things recognized by common sense. It is matter, rather than things, which concerns the physicist. I shall quote these passages at length because they reveal so clearly Russell 's assumptions about causal connections between things and their appearances. Yet they occur in the very same source which Ayer uses to support his claim that Russell abandoned the causal theory. Russell wants "to be able to express the fact that the appearance of a thing in a given perspective is causally affected by the matter between the thing and the perspective." He tentatively defines "matter" as "the limit of [the thing's] appearances as their distance from the thing diminishes." He admits that our empirical knowledge of matter is 9Ibid., p. 7. IO"The Relation between Physics and Sense-Data," p. 179. 18 somewhat restricted, because we can infer the limit of these appearances only approximately by means of the appearances we can observe. However, once we have accomplished this, Russell claims, We are now in a position to understand in outline the reverse journey from matter to sense-data which is performed by physics. The appearance of a thing in a given perspective is a function of the matter composing the thing and of the intervening matter.. The nearer we approach to the thing, the less its appearance is affected by the intervening matter. As we travel further and further from the thin~, its appearances diverge more and more from their initial character; and the causat taws of the divergence are to be stated in terms of the matter which lies between them and the thin y... The whote oausat efficaoy of a thing resides in its matter. I The crucial change in Russell "s view between 1912 and 1914 does not involve rejection of a causal theory of perception, but rather a very different analysis of what physical objects are (i.e. classes of appearances}, an analysis made possible by the six-dimensional character of space. Prior to 1914, Russell required a vertical inference to establish the existence of physical objects. After 1914 he did not. In addition to a different analysis of physical objects, a more sophisticated understanding of causal connections is required in order to harmonize a causal theory of perception with the acceptance of horizontally inferred physical objects. Causality was no longer regarded by Russell as a relation which holds between an unknown physical object and an experienced sensibile, or sense-datum. Rather, causal laws describe connections and patterns of change which hold between earlier or more distant parts of processes and later or nearer parts of the same processes. Russell hints at this in his 1914 account of "matter", but spells it out more explicitly in The Anatysis of Mind, after he has rejected the vertical inference to minds, and so has given up sense-data in favour of non-relational sensations from which both minds and matter are constructed. 12 This same understanding of causality as well as the co~itment to horizontal inference is evident in Russell's later works. Whenever he is primarily concerned with epistemological questions, he assumes that the percept is at the end of a causal chain whose source was a physical object. Percepts are understood as events whose components are sensations and other elements. Percepts, which are stages in physical processes, are the epistmo10gica11y important parts of the processes. Causal laws allow us to infer earlier stages in the same processes. In the set of postulates in Human Knowtedge which Russell proposed as a sufficient set IIIbid., pp. 165-6. (All ital ics mine.} 12The Anatysis of Mind (London: Allen and Unwin, 1921), pp. 302-3. 19

for the validation of scientific method, the postulate of separable causal lines is the one which permits the sort of inference required. Russell's works of 1914 present, according to his own account, tentative constructions. In later works, as a result of developments in the theory of general relativity, quantum mechanics, and behavioural psychology - all of which pushed him toward neutral monism and the adoption of an event ontology - the construction is developed and revised. In the later works Russell's concern shifts to a law-like scientific account of the world instead of the construction of common-sense "things". But such a concern is already foreshadowed in the earl ier account of "ma tter". Perhaps the lack of concern with common-sense "things" in later works also explains why he no longer emphasized the six-dimensional character of space, though he never repudiated the importance of this discovery. When a new edition of Our KnowZedge of the ExternaZ WorZd was issued after Russell became a neutral monist, he only pointed out that he no longer accepted sense-data, and that the construction would go through if "sensations" was substituted for "sense-data".13 There was no need to disclaim a phenomenalistic theory of perception and to explain that he had since embraced a causal theory: the causal theory was already an intrinsic part of the 1914 works. In spite of all the changes, Russell continued to regard the work of 1914 as a tentative step toward the more complete theory of the later I'oQrks. He hoped to find an account in which "the percept [does] not appear mysteriously at the end of a causal chain composed of events of a tota11y different nature", thereby improving "the metaphysical status of physics."14 He believed that he had achieved just such a theory and was dismayed that philosophers did not make more serious efforts to understand it. Department of Philosophy University of Arizona Merrilee H. Salmon 130ur KnowZedge of the ExternaZ WorZd, p. 83. 14The AnaZysis of M1:tter, p. 275. 20