The Logic of Uddyotakara The conflict with Buddhist logic and his achievement

Similar documents
The Problem of Major Premise in Buddhist Logic

A (Very) Brief Introduction to Epistemology Lecture 2. Palash Sarkar

THE FORM OF REDUCTIO AD ABSURDUM J. M. LEE. A recent discussion of this topic by Donald Scherer in [6], pp , begins thus:

Indian Philosophy Prof. Satya Sundar Sethy Department of Humanities and Social Sciences Indian Institute of Technology, Madras

On The Logical Status of Dialectic (*) -Historical Development of the Argument in Japan- Shigeo Nagai Naoki Takato

Anumāna as Analogical Reasoning A Critical Analysis

2. Refutations can be stronger or weaker.

C. Exam #1 comments on difficult spots; if you have questions about this, please let me know. D. Discussion of extra credit opportunities

Semantic Entailment and Natural Deduction

Commentary on Sample Test (May 2005)

CLARIFYING MIND An Introduction to the Tradition of Pramana

1.6 Validity and Truth

6AANA016 Indian Philosophy: The Orthodox Schools Syllabus Academic year 2012/3

An Introduction to. Formal Logic. Second edition. Peter Smith, February 27, 2019

Logic: Deductive and Inductive by Carveth Read M.A. CHAPTER VI CONDITIONS OF IMMEDIATE INFERENCE

What is the Nature of Logic? Judy Pelham Philosophy, York University, Canada July 16, 2013 Pan-Hellenic Logic Symposium Athens, Greece

Unit. Buddhist Formal Logic. Downloaded from The Buddhist Theory of ANUM NA (Inference) Downloaded from

Logic & Philosophy. SSB Syllabus

CLARIFYING MIND - PART TWO An Introduction to the Tradition of Pramana DUDRA: THE COLLECTED TOPICS LORIK: THE CLASSIFICATIONS OF MIND

Aquinas' Third Way Modalized

The Sea-Fight Tomorrow by Aristotle

Study Guides. Chapter 1 - Basic Training

Mark Anthony D. Abenir, MCD Department of Social Sciences & Philosophy University of Santo Tomas

Chapter 9- Sentential Proofs

LESSON PLAN EVEN SEMESTER 2018 Session: 2 nd January, 2018 to 20 th April, 2018 PHIL 402: Indian Logic (Tarkasaṁgraha); UG, 4 th Semester

A Liar Paradox. Richard G. Heck, Jr. Brown University

North Orissa University Sriram Chandra Vihar Takatpur, Baripada Mayurbhanj

PHILOSOPHY IAS MAINS: QUESTIONS TREND ANALYSIS

1/12. The A Paralogisms

NEW BOOK> The Golden Age of Indian Buddhist Philosophy

Knowledge. Internalism and Externalism

MCQ IN TRADITIONAL LOGIC. 1. Logic is the science of A) Thought. B) Beauty. C) Mind. D) Goodness

Reductio ad Absurdum, Modulation, and Logical Forms. Miguel López-Astorga 1

Chapter 8 - Sentential Truth Tables and Argument Forms

Indian Philosophy Paper-I

Appendix: The Logic Behind the Inferential Test

1. Introduction Formal deductive logic Overview

AMONG THE HINDU THEORIES OF ILLUSION BY RASVIHARY DAS. phenomenon of illusion. from man\- contemporary

prohibition, moral commitment and other normative matters. Although often described as a branch

The Power of Critical Thinking Why it matters How it works

Has Logical Positivism Eliminated Metaphysics?

Lecture Notes on Classical Logic

B.A./Alankar First Year

Instructor s Manual 1

Deccan Education Society s FERGUSSON COLLEGE, PUNE (AUTONOMOUS) SYLLABUS UNDER AUTONOMY FIRST YEAR B.A. LOGIC SEMESTER I

INTERMEDIATE LOGIC Glossary of key terms

Noncognitivism in Ethics, by Mark Schroeder. London: Routledge, 251 pp.

Fr. Copleston vs. Bertrand Russell: The Famous 1948 BBC Radio Debate on the Existence of God

Semantic Foundations for Deductive Methods

Studies in Buddhist Philosophy by Mark Siderits (review)

IS THE SYLLOGISTIC A LOGIC? it is not a theory or formal ontology, a system concerned with general features of the

The Greatest Mistake: A Case for the Failure of Hegel s Idealism

A BRIEF INTRODUCTION TO LOGIC FOR METAPHYSICIANS

Philosophy of Science. Ross Arnold, Summer 2014 Lakeside institute of Theology

Symbolic Logic Prof. Chhanda Chakraborti Department of Humanities and Social Sciences Indian Institute of Technology, Kharagpur

A Review of Norm Geisler's Prolegomena

Courses providing assessment data PHL 202. Semester/Year

Anumāna as interpreted in Sāṁkhya-Yoga philosophy: A brief study

Indian Philosophy Prof. Satya Sundar Sethy Department of Humanities and Social Sciences Indian Institute of Technology, Madras

Genesis Numerology. Meir Bar-Ilan. Association for Jewish Astrology and Numerology

Basic Concepts and Skills!

Informalizing Formal Logic

OSSA Conference Archive OSSA 3

Replies to Hasker and Zimmerman. Trenton Merricks. Molinism: The Contemporary Debate edited by Ken Perszyk. Oxford University Press, I.

Epistemic Reduction: The Case of Arthāpatti

Why There s Nothing You Can Say to Change My Mind: The Principle of Non-Contradiction in Aristotle s Metaphysics

Experience and Foundationalism in Audi s The Architecture of Reason

HAVE WE REASON TO DO AS RATIONALITY REQUIRES? A COMMENT ON RAZ

Logic: Deductive and Inductive by Carveth Read M.A. CHAPTER IX CHAPTER IX FORMAL CONDITIONS OF MEDIATE INFERENCE

Intuitive evidence and formal evidence in proof-formation

Philosophy 5340 Epistemology. Topic 6: Theories of Justification: Foundationalism versus Coherentism. Part 2: Susan Haack s Foundherentist Approach

5.6.1 Formal validity in categorical deductive arguments

A Problem for a Direct-Reference Theory of Belief Reports. Stephen Schiffer New York University

An Inferentialist Conception of the A Priori. Ralph Wedgwood

Indian Philosophy Prof. Satya Sundar Sethy Department of Humanities and Social Sciences Indian Institute of Technology, Madras

Philosophy 1100: Introduction to Ethics. Critical Thinking Lecture 1. Background Material for the Exercise on Validity

FIRST STUDY. The Existential Dialectical Basic Assumption of Kierkegaard s Analysis of Despair

Indian Philosophy. Prof. Dr. Satya Sundar Sethy. Department of Humanities and Social Sciences. Indian Institute of Technology, Madras. Module No.

2 FREE CHOICE The heretical thesis of Hobbes is the orthodox position today. So much is this the case that most of the contemporary literature

Part I: The Structure of Philosophy

Can Negation be Defined in Terms of Incompatibility?

CONTENTS A SYSTEM OF LOGIC

Selections from Aristotle s Prior Analytics 41a21 41b5

semantic-extensional interpretation that happens to satisfy all the axioms.

Quantificational logic and empty names

Williams on Supervaluationism and Logical Revisionism

Boghossian & Harman on the analytic theory of the a priori

The Ontological Argument for the existence of God. Pedro M. Guimarães Ferreira S.J. PUC-Rio Boston College, July 13th. 2011

In Defense of Radical Empiricism. Joseph Benjamin Riegel. Chapel Hill 2006

SAVING RELATIVISM FROM ITS SAVIOUR

out in his Three Dialogues and Principles of Human Knowledge, gives an argument specifically

Kant and the Problem of Metaphysics 1. By Tom Cumming

Artificial Intelligence Prof. P. Dasgupta Department of Computer Science & Engineering Indian Institute of Technology, Kharagpur

Logic & Philosophy Sample Questions

ISSA Proceedings 1998 Wilson On Circular Arguments

Building Systematic Theology

4.1 A problem with semantic demonstrations of validity

Commentary on Feteris

EXCERPTS FROM GANGESA'S (WISH-FULFILLING) JEWEL OF REFLECTION ON THE TRUTH (ABOUT EPISTEMOLOGY) S. Phillips

7.1. Unit. Terms and Propositions. Nature of propositions. Types of proposition. Classification of propositions

Transcription:

1 The Logic of Uddyotakara The conflict with Buddhist logic and his achievement 0 Introduction 1 The Framework of Uddyotakara s Logic 1.1 Nyāya system and Uddyotakara 1.2 The Framework of Uddyotakara s Logic 2 Aspects of Uddyotakara s Logic 2.1 Dharma-Dharmin-Framework 2.2 Trairūpya-Theory and Logical Necessity 2.3 The Usage and the Logical Structure of vyatirekin 3 An Aspect of Prasaṅga-demonstration A Genealogy of Avīta 3.1 The Development of Vīta and Āvīta Theory 3.2 Uddyotakara s Theory of Avīta 4 Conclusion Appendix Japanese Translation and Elucidation of Nyāyavārttika A Theory of Inference: under NS 1. 1. 5 B Theory of Demonstration: under NS 1. 1. 32 39 C Theory of Debate: under NS 1. 2. 1 3 D Theory of Fallacy: under NS 1. 2. 4 9 E General Introduction to NV: under NS 1. 1. 1 The aim of this article is to clarify Uddyotakara s theories of inference and demonstration by examining mainly from the logical point of view, their position in the development of early Indian logic. In this article I devote attention to the following two points: 1 the relation between an inferential object and its valid reason, or the conditions for the valid reasons, 2 the demonstrative schemata called vyatirekin or avīta. In the case of Uddyotakara, the relation between an inferential object and its valid reason has been sometimes said to be samavāya. This view would be based on Uddyotakara s criticism of Diṅnāga s avinābhāva and Uddyotakara s unique interpretation of the inference of fire. However, I disagree on the grounds that the above portions must be interpreted in other way, and that the relation called avyabhicāra should afford the key to understanding the validity of reason in Uddyotakara s logical system. The vyatirekin has been generally said to be a reason having no similar instance sapakṣa or an inference based on such a reason. This explanation is due to Uddyotakara s definition. On the other hand, the vyatirekin that is listed in Uddyotakara s three types of inferences or sixteen classification of valid and invalid reasons has a strange form. Its reason is represented in terms of -prasaṅgāt it would be absurdity that... It is parallel to reductio ad absurdum. In the tradition of Indian logic, this kind of demonstration is hardly found in the five-membered or three-membered demonstrative schemata, and has

2 Summary called the attention of some scholars, for example, Hadano, Katsura and Matilal. However, we are still dubious as to whether the vyatirekin alway has such a form. Even if it is true, the theoretical basis for vyatirekin and its historical background must be clarified. In preparation for the above investigation, I have examined the historical context of Nyāyavārttika, and clarified the framework of his descriptions of logic in the 1st chapter. Firstly I have examined the historical context of Nyāyavārttika. He sometimes criticizes Vātsyāyana s interpretations of Nyāya doctrine, and alters them. These facts imply Uddyotakara s re-systematization of Nyāya, which includes the integration of Vaiśeṣika ontology into Nyāya system. Secondly I have investigated the framework of Uddyotakara s logic. I have traced the historical development of the relation between the means of valid knowledge pramāṇa and the demonstration throughout this investigation. It also concerns the integration of vāda debate -tradition and pramāṇa the means of valid knowledge -tradition. From historical point of view, it can be classified into two groups: 1 integrating the means of valid knowledge into the demonstration, 2 integrating the demonstrative schema into the theory of inference. The view 2 might be originated with Diṅnāga. He divides the inference into inference for myself svārthānumāna and that for others parārthānumāna. The former is the inference as a means of knowledge, and the latter is the demonstration. This view finally have prevailed over the later Indian logicians, although there are some varieties of this view. Uddyotakara, however, does not adopt this view. Rather he seems to follow Vātsyāyana who would belong to 1. They maintain that each means of valid knowledge corresponds to the formula of demonstrative schema respectively. In this view, the reason is connected with inference, and the most important member of demonstration, although it differs from the view, which is advocated by Carakasaṃhitā or Asaṅga, that every means of valid knowledge are integrated into the reason. Therefore, the inference described under NS 1. 1. 5 and the demonstration under NS 1. 1. 32 39 must be treated in different way. The further treats the epistemological or psychological process of inference, the latter does the validity of demonstration, which was concluded by my investigation. The trairūpya-theory three conditions for valid reason concerns the latter. Both the inference and the demonstration, however, have the common basic structure. It is the dharma-dharmin property and its substratum -structure. I have begun 2nd chapter by examining the dharma-dharmin-structure. In the history of Nyāya school, the dharma-dharmin-structure might be used in the description of the demonstration or the debate since early times. Especially, Vātsyāyana s description of five-membered demonstrative schema is clearly based on this structure, but that of the inference does not make reference to it. The first Nyāya scholar who describes

3 the inference in the framework of dharma-dharmin can be placed in the period of pre-uddyotakara. Uddyotakara, succeeding to his or their thought, has established a basis for the description of inference and demonstration. In his theory, a property of reason sādhanadharma and its substratum dharmin are always perceptible, but the property of the inferential object sādhyadharma is not. I have made it possible to interpret the inference of fire in this framework. Although most of the dharma and dharmin can be interpreted as conjunctional or inherent relata saṃyogin/samavāyin, these concepts seems to be used in epistemological sense. Uddyotakara s threefold classifications of the inferences are mainly concerned with the variety of the property of inferential objects sādhyadharma. It must be especially noticed that Uddyotakara divides the property of inferential object into three types: 1 affirmative vidhīyamāna, 2 negative pratiṣidhyamāna and 3 independent svatantra. This classification makes us possible to enlarge the concept of dharma, and also to develop the possibilities of the inference and the demonstration. Secondly, I have examined the influence of the trairūpya-theory upon Uddyotakara s interpretations on Nyāyasūtra. It is well-known that he incorporated the trairūpya-theory or its developed version into the threefold classification of inference under NS 1. 1. 5. He classifies the inferences into three on the basis of the developed trairūpya-theory and interpreted the three word in Nyāyasūtra as the three conditions of trairūpya-theory In this case, however, his interpretation seems to be tentative, at least one of the interpretations on Nyāsūtra. On the other hand, his interpretation on NS 1. 1. 34 and 35 is clearly influenced from the trairūpya-theory, and his own fixed view. As a matter of fact, we can not find other interpretations on them. This fact that the trairūpya-theory or its developed version is used in the definition of the reason implies that Uddyotakara s logical basis for the validity of demonstration is the developed version of trairūpya-theory, because the validity of reason warrants it. In addition, the reason is directly concerned with the relation between an inferential object and its reason in the context of early Nyāya logic. The relation named avyabhicāra is used in Uddyotakara s explanation of the negative reason vyatirekin under NS 1. 1. 35.. He says that the affirmative reason anvayin is not based on mere association anvaya but on the infallibility of association anvayāvyabhicāra, and that the negative reason is not based on mere dissociation vyatireka but on the infallibility of dissociation vyatirekāvyabhicāra. It follows from this description that avyabhicāra is the relation similar to vyāpti pervasion, warranting the validity of reason. Besides the same view is shown under NS 3. 1. 3.. To clarify the conditions for valid reason, we should firstly grasp the concept of avyabhicāra and verify the conditions that follow from the definition of avyabhicāra in the sixteen classification of valid and invalid reasons, which is a check list of valid reason.

4 Summary It is not difficult to define the concept of avyabhicāra, since we can easily collect the descriptions concerning vyabhicāra and its antonym from Nyāyavārttika under NS 1. 1. 23 the definition of doubt and 1. 2. 5 the definition of savyabhicāra-pseudo reason. To sum up those descriptions, we can define S-avyabhicārin H as H is limited to S or H exists in S and its similar instances but not in others. The latter forms the conjunction of three conditions for valid reason trairūpya advocated by Buddhist logicians. It can be formulated as follows: x Hx Sx x Hx Sx (1) If S and H stand for the property of an inferential object and that of its reason respectively, the formula 1 functions as one condition for valid reason in the sixteen classification of valid and invalid reasons. The four reasons, two affirmative-negative reasons anvayavyatirekin and two affirmative reasons anvayin only fulfill this condition. We can safely say that the formula 1 is the meaning of anvayāvyabhicāra. For convenience, I will, henceforth, express formula 1 in term of H S On the other hand, there remains the meaning of vyatirekāvyabhicāra. The discussion about an unique pseudo reason asādhāraṇa-hetvāsa under NS 1. 1. 35 and NS 3. 1. 3 offers the key to solve this problem. An unique pseudo reason is described as follows: ad NS 1. 1. 35 H is fallibly concluded with both S and non-s. ad NS 3. 1. 3 H is excluded from both S and non-s. If the latter means that both S H and S H hold, vyatirekāvyabhicāra means that S H holds but S H not. This functions as the other conditions for valid reason. As a matter of fact, only the three reasons listed in the sixteen classification of valid and invalid reasons, two anvayavyatirekin and one vyatirekin fulfill this condition. To sum up our discussion, the conditions for the valid reasons are summarized as follows: anvayāvyabhicāra H S holds vyatirekāvyabhicāra S H holds but S H not Thirdly, I have examined the formulae and schemata that named vyatireka or avīta in Nyāyavārttika, which resulted in the followings: 1 The statements pratijñā are mainly expressed in negative or double-negative form. 2 The reasons have prasaṅga-form or a somewhat negative form. It follows from these facts and my logical analysis that we can regard each vyatirekin or avīta as reductio ad absurdum. In addition, I have found an example of demonstration that is called vyatirekin but not kevalavyatirekin. This means that the term vyatirekin mainly refers to the sort of demonstrative form or logical structure, but not the reason without similar instances. The reasons without similar instances are always vyatirekin, but its converse is not true.

5 In the 3rd chapter, I have examined the historical background of avīta. First of all I have examined some examples of classical Sāṃkhya. Having observed them cited in Jaina Dvādaśāraṃ Nayacakra and its commentary, we can guess the process of āvīta as follows: 1st stage 2nd stage 3rd stage 4th stage 5th stage 6th stage 7th stage To illustrate the absurdity in the case when the hypothetical proposition is supposed To explain the reason why the absurdity is concluded Re-illustration of the absurdity To illustrate the inapplicability to this subject The conclusion that the hypothetical proposition is negated The deduction based on elimination pariśeṣa The final conclusion In classical Sāṃkhya, especially Ṣaṣṭitantra, the following points must be noticed. The āvīta is subordinate to vīta, which is positive and consists of five formulae. The concept of pariśeṣa plays an important role in the āvīta. On the other hand, it contains prasaṅga formulation, and defined as a negation of other s view. These two points are common to Uddyotakara s vyatirekin The most significant difference between Uddyotakara s avīta and Sāṃkhya s one lies on the independency of āvīta. In the 3rd chapter of Pramāṇasamuccayavṛtti, Diṅnāga criticizes āvīta. The āvīta cited in Pramāṇasamuccayavṛtti consists three formulae, and contains a negative statement and a prasaṅga-form reason. We can regards it as an independent three membered demonstrative schema. Diṅnāga insists that the negative statement and the prasaṅga-form reason must be transformed to positive ones. He argues that the cited āvīta does not fulfill the first condition for valid reason(pakṣadharmatā: being a property of inferential object), and that the association does not hold in some cases. Uddyotakara solves these criticized points by introducing the concept of vyatirekāvyabhicāra and the negative property. Then, differing from Diṅnāga, he accepts āvīta as its original form. Uddyotakara s contribution to Indian logic is establishing a theory where prasaṅga-form demonstration is possible.