Week 2: Freedom of Thought

Similar documents
On Liberty by John Stuart Mill

MILL ON LIBERTY. 1. Problem. Mill s On Liberty, one of the great classics of liberal political thought,

SINCE 9/11 Webinar. Freedom of Speech in the Classroom

The Paranormal, Miracles and David Hume

Moral Theory. What makes things right or wrong?

Creative Genius and the Rights of the Individual: From Romanticism to Utilitarianism

Phil 114, April 24, 2007 until the end of semester Mill: Individual Liberty Against the Tyranny of the Majority

Replies to Hasker and Zimmerman. Trenton Merricks. Molinism: The Contemporary Debate edited by Ken Perszyk. Oxford University Press, I.

Ethical non-naturalism

Ethics is subjective.

Richard L. W. Clarke, Notes REASONING

KANTIAN ETHICS (Dan Gaskill)

Chapter 2 Reasoning about Ethics

Charles Saunders Peirce ( )

Chapter 2: Reasoning about ethics

ALA - Library Bill of Rights

Stem Cell Research on Embryonic Persons is Just

Common Morality: Deciding What to Do 1

(i) Morality is a system; and (ii) It is a system comprised of moral rules and principles.

Criticizing Arguments

Evaluating actions The principle of utility Strengths Criticisms Act vs. rule

ADMINISTRATIVE REGULATIONS

What God Could Have Made

An Alternate Possibility for the Compatibility of Divine. Foreknowledge and Free Will. Alex Cavender. Ringstad Paper Junior/Senior Division

GS SCORE ETHICS - A - Z. Notes

2 FREE CHOICE The heretical thesis of Hobbes is the orthodox position today. So much is this the case that most of the contemporary literature

What should I believe? What should I believe when people disagree with me?

Précis of Democracy and Moral Conflict

AN EPISTEMIC PARADOX. Byron KALDIS

PROSPECTS FOR A JAMESIAN EXPRESSIVISM 1 JEFF KASSER

This document consists of 10 printed pages.

UNITED NATIONS EDUCATIONAL, SCIENTIFIC AND CULTURAL ORGANIZATION. Address by Mr Federico Mayor

There are various different versions of Newcomb s problem; but an intuitive presentation of the problem is very easy to give.

Mill s definition of truthful, factual objectivity in On Liberty

A Compatibilist Account of Free Will and Moral Responsibility

EPISTEMOLOGY for DUMMIES

Anselm of Canterbury on Free Will

Legal Positivism: the Separation and Identification theses are true.

Chapter 3 PHILOSOPHICAL ETHICS AND BUSINESS CHAPTER OBJECTIVES. After exploring this chapter, you will be able to:

What is the "Social" in "Social Coherence?" Commentary on Nelson Tebbe's Religious Freedom in an Egalitarian Age

Ima Emotivist (EM) X is good means Hurrah for X! Moral judgments aren t true or false. We can t reason about basic moral principles.

Basics of Ethics CS 215 Denbigh Starkey

Peter Singer, Famine, Affluence, and Morality

SUMMARIES AND TEST QUESTIONS UNIT 6

A Studying of Limitation of Epistemology as Basis of Toleration with Special Reference to John Locke

Who Has the Burden of Proof? Must the Christian Provide Adequate Reasons for Christian Beliefs?

PRÉCIS THE ORDER OF PUBLIC REASON: A THEORY OF FREEDOM AND MORALITY IN A DIVERSE AND BOUNDED WORLD

Oxford Scholarship Online

appearance is often different from reality, and it s reality that counts.

Justice and Ethics. Jimmy Rising. October 3, 2002

Philosophical Perspectives, 16, Language and Mind, 2002 THE AIM OF BELIEF 1. Ralph Wedgwood Merton College, Oxford

Ensuring equality of religion and belief in Northern Ireland: new challenges

Phil Aristotle. Instructor: Jason Sheley

THE QUESTION OF "UNIVERSALITY VERSUS PARTICULARITY?" IN THE LIGHT OF EPISTEMOLOGICAL KNOWLEDGE OF NORMS

Utilitarianism: For and Against (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1973), pp Reprinted in Moral Luck (CUP, 1981).

A CONSEQUENTIALIST RESPONSE TO THE DEMANDINGNESS OBJECTION Nicholas R. Baker, Lee University THE DEMANDS OF ACT CONSEQUENTIALISM

The Contribution of Religion and Religious Schools to Cultural Diversity and Social Cohesion in Contemporary Australia

THE MORAL ARGUMENT. Peter van Inwagen. Introduction, James Petrik

Chapter 2 Ethical Concepts and Ethical Theories: Establishing and Justifying a Moral System

EXERCISES, QUESTIONS, AND ACTIVITIES My Answers

MILL ON JUSTICE: CHAPTER 5 of UTILITARIANISM Lecture Notes Dick Arneson Philosophy 13 Fall, 2005

THE CONCEPT OF OWNERSHIP by Lars Bergström

Utilitarianism. But what is meant by intrinsically good and instrumentally good?

From They Say/I Say: The Moves that Matter in Academic Writing Gerald Graff and Cathy Birkenstein Prediction:

To Provoke or to Encourage? - Combining Both within the Same Methodology

PHI 1700: Global Ethics

Ayer s linguistic theory of the a priori

Does the Skeptic Win? A Defense of Moore. I. Moorean Methodology. In A Proof of the External World, Moore argues as follows:

In Defense of Culpable Ignorance

On the Origins and Normative Status of the Impartial Spectator

This handout follows the handout on The nature of the sceptic s challenge. You should read that handout first.

Bertrand Russell Proper Names, Adjectives and Verbs 1

DISCUSSION PRACTICAL POLITICS AND PHILOSOPHICAL INQUIRY: A NOTE

AN OUTLINE OF CRITICAL THINKING

In Defense of Pure Reason: A Rationalist Account of A Priori Justification, by Laurence BonJour. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press,

3. WHERE PEOPLE STAND

Thesis Statements. (and their purposes)

Is the Existence of the Best Possible World Logically Impossible?

Notes on Moore and Parker, Chapter 12: Moral, Legal and Aesthetic Reasoning

COMPARING CONTEXTUALISM AND INVARIANTISM ON THE CORRECTNESS OF CONTEXTUALIST INTUITIONS. Jessica BROWN University of Bristol

Nicomachean Ethics. Book VI

In his book Ethics: Inventing Right and Wrong, J. L. Mackie agues against

POLI 342: MODERN WESTERN POLITICAL THOUGHT

Argument Basics. When an argument shows that its conclusion is worth accepting we say that the argument is good.

Equality of Capacity AMARTYA SEN

Are There Moral Facts

IS ACT-UTILITARIANISM SELF-DEFEATING?

The view that all of our actions are done in self-interest is called psychological egoism.

Richard van de Lagemaat Relative Values A Dialogue

The Faith of Unbelief Dallas Willard

RESPONSIBLE JUDGMENT REASONABLENESS

Intelligence Squared U.S. Special Release: How to Debate Yourself

Epistemology. Theory of Knowledge

What Makes Someone s Life Go Best from Reasons and Persons by Derek Parfit (1984)

Adapted from The Academic Essay: A Brief Anatomy, for the Writing Center at Harvard University by Gordon Harvey. Counter-Argument

Introduction to Philosophy Philosophy 110W Spring 2011 Russell Marcus

Jeu-Jenq Yuann Professor of Philosophy Department of Philosophy, National Taiwan University,

Paradoxes of religious freedom in Egypt

Templates for Research Paper

Truth and Molinism * Trenton Merricks. Molinism: The Contemporary Debate edited by Ken Perszyk. Oxford University Press, 2011.

Transcription:

Week 2: Freedom of Thought 1. Introduction - Last week we ended by asking what really motivates Mill: a commitment to utilitarianism? Or a commitment to human flourishing even if this doesn t maximize happiness/pleasure? We ll return to this repeatedly. - This week going to work carefully through the arguments of Chapter 2 of On Liberty. Sometimes seen as an annoyance or distraction; a bit dull compared to what comes later. - I think that s a mistake. We need to pay close attention even if the arguments aren t always as clear or well-formulated as we d like them to be. 2. The set-up - Recall that Mill is very concerned with an allegedly new threat to liberty: enslavement of the soul itself via the influence of censorious majorities. Particularly a threat to minorities and those who are different. - In particular, Mill is perturbed by the rise of mediocrity in human life brought about by majority oppression. Against this he wants to erect a strong barrier of moral conviction to protect those who dissent in their ways of life. - Mill declares that instead of defending a general thesis, he ll take a particular case study. This he declares to be liberty of thought important because it cannot be separated from liberty of writing or speaking. - The grounds for the justification of liberty of thought, Mill claims, are poorly understood. But getting a better understanding of the liberty of thought will in turn crack open the wider issues he is concerned with. 3. The initial argument - Mill asks us to imagine an idealized world in which the forces of government are entirely at one with the views of the general public, all opinions coincide, and the state only uses its power in line with what believes to be the public voice. - This is clearly not the real world. But Mill wants to show how strong his argument is by proving that it works even in the extreme case he imagines, it will apply even more strongly in the real world. - So imagining the world of widespread agreement and consent, Mill imagines a solitary individual who dissents from the prevailing view(s). And to this he says: If all mankind minus one, were of one opinion, and only one person were of the contrary opinion, mankind would be no more justified in silencing that one person, than he, if he had the power, would be justified in silencing mankind. - And he follows this up with an even bigger claim: 1

The peculiar evil of silencing the expression of an opinion is, that it is robbing the human race; posterity as well as the existing generation; those who dissent from the opinion still more than those who hold it - These are big claims! Mill is saying that the real losers when opinions get suppressed are not those who have their opinions suppressed, but those who do the suppressing. - This is the core claim that the rest of the chapter essentially seeks to defend. - Unfortunately, Mill s subsequent defence isn t as clear as we might have hoped. - He claims that the reason that the suppressors (rather than the suppressed) are robbed when freedom of thought is stifled is because they are deprived of the opportunity for exchanging error for truth: if wrong, they lose, what is almost as great a benefit, the clearer perception and livelier impression of truth, produced by its collision with error. - Mill goes on to say that the rest of the chapter will be concerned with two alternatives as to why this is so. Unfortunately, he actually outlines three! In any case, these take up the bulk of Chapter 2. 4. The First Set of Reasons - Widespread liberty of thought, Mill begins by saying, should be granted because a suppressed opinion may in fact turn out to be true. - Humans tend to assume that their own opinions are right, and shut down the possibility that dissenting opinions are wrong especially if they don t like those dissenting opinions. - Individuals tend to assume, in practice if not in theory, that their own views are infallible, and hence others are simply wrong if they happen to disagree. - This is heavily bolstered by the prevailing opinions of an age. Which is unfortunate, because ages tend to be even more fallible than individuals (e.g. the Spartans with infanticide; Mary I and burning protestants). - Suppressing opinion is merely asserting infallibility. But nobody can know for sure that their opinion or judgement or belief is correct, because nobody is infallible. (Everybody admits this when pushed, Mill thinks.) So no opinions should be suppressed. - A counter-argument: all government action is potentially fallible, e.g. a bad tax may be levied. But the appropriate response is not to claim that the state should cease all such activities! What s so special about the case of freedom of thought? - Mill s reply: There is the greatest difference between presuming an opinion to be true, because, with every opportunity for contesting it, it has not been refuted, and assuming its truth for the purpose of not permitting its refutation. - I.e. governments make mistakes reply simply misses the point. [In technical philosophical parlance, it begs the question i.e. it assumes as true the very premise 2

they needs to be proved as true, in order for the argument to be correct.] - One cannot consistently say that something may not be subjected to disagreement because it s already known to be true, insofar as the only way one could know it to be true would be to have it subjected to disagreement. But that s precisely what is lacking, and what is being denied. - Taxes, legislation, foreign policy etc, don t work like that. They are about judgement calls regarding policy. The principle of protecting freedom of thought is of a different order entirely, hence requires a different kind of argument. - Another objection to Mill: it s OK to challenge some opinions, but matters must not be pushed to extremes. - Reply: who gets to decide what counts as extreme? That, after all, is part of what is up for debate! If one simply rules in advance that certain things are too extreme to countenance dissent regarding, this assumes knowledge of truth over what counts as too extreme. But in order to have that knowledge, one would have to have debated openly to discover it. Denying that debate instead means claiming being certain over certainty. But this is a claim to the sort of infallibility that Mill believes nobody can seriously make in good faith. - A tough case: what about a belief that many in Victorian Britain hold must be infallible: that there is a benevolent God who has ordered the universe and provided for a future state in which our immortal souls will be saved? Surely Mill won t deny that this belief is infallible? [Recall the context!] - Reply: Mill grants the premise belief in God is infallible. But he denies the conclusion: that dissent from this belief can never be tolerated. Why? Because the real problem is specifically the undertaking to decide that question for others, without allowing them to hear what can be said on the contrary side. - So the defence of free thought has been considerably refined, it turns out. The real problem with an assumption of infallibility is that it prevents others from making their own minds up for themselves. - And doing this, Mill thinks, is wrong for two kinds of reasons: 1) intrinstic : it s just bad in itself not to let people make up their own minds 2) instrumental : if people don t make up their own minds, their rational faculties become dulled, they lose their creativity, and society stagnates - And problem 2) leads to further bad consequences: the holders of dogmas tend to want to go around enforcing adherence to their views and history is replete with examples of how that turns out to lead to very nasty states of affairs, and a lot of human suffering. - Mill drives the point home with examples: Socrates, Marcus Aurelius, Jesus Christ himself. [Remember the power of these examples for his Victorian audience!] - He stresses also the positives associated with free and open expression, however. Even Newton s theories, if they were not openly debated and contested, would not be held with 3

vigour and liveliness. More generally, societies that debar open discussion and dissent quickly stagnate. Only where tolerance of dissent has been permitted are truly active and productive minds found. And only there is collective progress and improvement achieved. 5. The Second Set of Reasons - The first set of reasons bleeds heavily into the second: that even if a dissenting opinion is false, mankind is still the loser by suppressing it. - The core of Mill s claim is that however true an opinion may be, if it is not fully, frequently, and fearlessly discussed, it will be held as a dead dogma, not a living truth. - It s not enough to believe something that is true you have to believe if for the right kind of reasons, in the right kind of ways. And that often means experiencing confrontation with those who disagree. - Mill is scornful of the view that so long as an opinion is true, how one learns it is irrelevant. - Simply believing something because an authority figure prescribes it is no better than superstition. This is not befitting of a rational animal. And protestants ought to recognize their duty to improve their God-given faculties which requires learning the grounds of one s opinion. [Note the rhetorical power of this in context!] - Against arguments from restricted debate (i.e. that some people may freely debate some issues, but not the wider masses). Again, this argument collapses upon itself: who gets to decide what is in and what is out for discussion? For Mill, it s all or nothing if we are to hold our opinions for the right reasons, in the right kinds of ways. - However, for Mill not all forms of knowledge, and not all beliefs, are the same. It s OK to learn e.g. mathematics or geometry by rote (at least at an early stage). But these are special cases. In science, encountering rival theories can be crucial to proper understanding of a putatively correct theory. - In morals and politics, however, we are dealing with a completely different form of knowledge to science of mathematics and so we need different grounds for attaining certainty regarding them. - Mill goes on: one can never really know the grounds of one s belief and thus know its truth in the right way and for the right reasons unless one encounters genuine opponents. Pretend teachers of devils advocate opponents offer only a weak simulation. [Is this true? It seems dubious; Mill presents it as an uncontroversial empirical fact. It isn t!] - Similarly, Mill insists that opinions are only truly fit for purpose if invested with living power feeling the force of what one believes because one has forceful reasons to believe it. And that again requires genuine opponents. - Example: most Christians are, he thinks, complacent believers, and their faith thus fails to govern their actual practice. Even though they are sincere believers, their belief lacks living power. He compares this to the early Christians, and the power of their convictions and what it allowed them to do. [Again, rhetorical force!] 4

- So a big claim is being staked by Mill: in order to really know why one believes what one believes, and to believe it in the right kind of way, with the right kinds of effects upon one s life, one needs to hold one s beliefs in active opposition to genuine opponents. - Problem: but if knowledge is continuously progressing and human affairs becoming more enlightened (as Mill wants to claim that they are), won t we then need to keep a subclass of society permanently misinformed so that they can challenge sincerely! the views of others, helping to provide lively illumination of truth?! - Alternatively, a paradox threatens: as we achieve more refined levels of knowledge, we will simultaneously lose the ability to really know truth, because there is no effective opposition to challenge us! Truth seems to perish at its own victory! - Regarding the first problem, Mill does NOT want to artificially keep some people in error to preserve lively conflicts of opinion. He is explicit about this but shies away from giving an argument as to why. - It would probably be impossible to pull it off anyway. But let s imagine it could be done, e.g. via drugs or propaganda or whatever. If it would be wrong to do so, why? What if doing so increased aggregate utility would Mill then be in favour of it? Or would he still rule it out. (The tension between his vision of man as a progressive being, versus the principle of utility, is just below the surface.) Mill does not give a clear answer. - Interestingly, however, Mill does seem to think that there will be a sort of cost to society in terms of the dulling of truth through the withering away of lively open debate as knowledge progresses, and this may be a price to pay. - This cuts against the popular view of him as an unalloyed optimist about freedom of thought and expression. He here follows through on the more hardheaded implications of his position, going where the arguments take him even if those aren t pretty. - Certainly Mill s presentation is sloppy. He runs together belief, opinion, truth, knowledge, as if these are obvious terms, often interchangeable, and the connections between them obvious. This is not so! But the core point is that for Mill, moral and political knowledge has a particular character, or nature, and that having it requires holding it in opposition to those who disagree and that this makes it different from other (e.g. scientific) forms of knowledge. - He thus points us to the potential plurality of human enquiry and experience. Mill s view is controversial. Whether you are attracted to or repulsed by it, it s worth thinking more about. 6. The Third Set of Reasons - In actual fact, it is very rarely the case, Mill says, that one side or another has a monopoly on truth or falsity: usually there is a mix on both sides. - Interestingly, Mill wants to say that his earlier arguments still apply even in the messier more typical mixed cases. Hence, if his earlier arguments work, they should have 5

maximum practical applicability. So the structure of the chapter may be neater than it first appears. - A Victorian objection: some beliefs cannot be considered as only partially true those relating to the Christian gospel! - Mill has to tread carefully; he needs to convince a Christian audience. - His reply is that the Gospels need to be taken alongside other social and moral facts of life. They are to remind people of already-existing moral duties. - So the teachings of the Gospel are all true they re just not enough by themselves. (Think of all the wisdom to be gleaned from the Ancient writers, etc.) - Mill doesn t deny that in religious matters, however, free thought and opinion can lead to sectarianism and mania as like-minded extremists fuel each other. Free thought may produce bigots. - But this is to be tolerated, as the price worth paying for the benefits to wider society yielded by free thought. It is not on the impassioned partisan, it is on the calmer and more disinterested bystander, that this collision of opinions works its more salutary effect. Note again that Mill is perhaps therefore a tougher, more hardheaded, thinker here than often given credit for. - Mill closes the chapter by recapping the main line of argument that allowing free thought and its expression benefits everyone and then confronts a final challenge: that heterodox opinions must only be expressed in temperate ways, so as not to excessively disturb the tranquility of others. - This, however, is wrongheaded in two ways according to Mill: 1) Holders of received opinion typically take any dissent as automatically intemperate. The standards of moderation are themselves partly what is at issue cannot be impartially ruled in advance! 2) If minority views want to get themselves heard, we know that they already tend to selfmoderate so as to avoid the ire of powerful and entrenched dominant interests (and thus dominant views). In reality it is the established view which needs to err towards moderation, as it is the one likely to engage in oppression and silencing of unpopular opinions. - In any case, it s simply incoherent (Mill thinks) to try and lay down in advance what the appropriate bounds of discussion and thought are. - His position is thus ultimately rather combative. He wants people to bash up against each other; to argue and debate vigorously; to challenge and rethink. - He seems to think it is necessary and even desirable for people to shock and even offend each other, on a fairly regular basis. -And this is necessary if we re going to develop our most important mental faculties in 6

the rights kinds of way, in turn living in healthy and vibrant societies that experience progress. - Hence, back to the questions raised last week. The end of Chapter 2 seem to indicate that if Mill is a utilitarian, he is a very unusual one. At any rate, his understanding of human happiness is a far richer and more complex thing than Bentham or James Mill s crude insistence on the maximization of pleasure. - And given Mill s insistence on developing the right capacities in the right kinds of ways, to create a certain sort of individual in a certain sort of soceity, we might wonder if this is really a maximizing view at all. And if it isn t, can Mill really be a utilitarian? More on this, next week 7