Armstrong et al. on inner sense

Similar documents
spring 05 topics in philosophy of mind session 7

The readings for the course are separated into the following two categories:

PHL340 Handout 8: Evaluating Dogmatism

Wittgenstein on the Fallacy of the Argument from Pretence. Abstract

Wright on response-dependence and self-knowledge

PHILOSOPHY 5340 EPISTEMOLOGY

Moral Argumentation from a Rhetorical Point of View

THE VARIETIES OF SELF-KNOWLEDGE. A Thesis ANTON SERGEEVICH KABESHKIN

UNDERSTANDING, JUSTIFICATION AND THE A PRIORI

KNOWLEDGE ON AFFECTIVE TRUST. Arnon Keren

A Priori Bootstrapping

McDowell and the New Evil Genius

Moore s paradoxes, Evans s principle and self-knowledge

Can A Priori Justified Belief Be Extended Through Deduction? It is often assumed that if one deduces some proposition p from some premises

Behavior and Other Minds: A Response to Functionalists

Seigel and Silins formulate the following theses:

Has Nagel uncovered a form of idealism?

Varieties of Apriority

In Defense of Radical Empiricism. Joseph Benjamin Riegel. Chapel Hill 2006

Experience and Foundationalism in Audi s The Architecture of Reason

Speaking My Mind: Expression and Self-Knowledge by Dorit Bar-On

Higher-Order Approaches to Consciousness and the Regress Problem

Testimony and Moral Understanding Anthony T. Flood, Ph.D. Introduction

INTERPRETATION AND FIRST-PERSON AUTHORITY: DAVIDSON ON SELF-KNOWLEDGE. David Beisecker University of Nevada, Las Vegas

WHAT DOES KRIPKE MEAN BY A PRIORI?

Seeing Through The Veil of Perception *

Moral requirements are still not rational requirements

Philosophical Perspectives, 16, Language and Mind, 2002 THE AIM OF BELIEF 1. Ralph Wedgwood Merton College, Oxford

The Department of Philosophy and Classics The University of Texas at San Antonio One UTSA Circle San Antonio, TX USA.

Skepticism and Internalism

ALTERNATIVE SELF-DEFEAT ARGUMENTS: A REPLY TO MIZRAHI

Epistemic Contextualism as a Theory of Primary Speaker Meaning

1 What is conceptual analysis and what is the problem?

Markie, Speckles, and Classical Foundationalism

Choosing Rationally and Choosing Correctly *

Martin s case for disjunctivism

Outsmarting the McKinsey-Brown argument? 1

Reply to Pryor. Juan Comesaña

Unit VI: Davidson and the interpretational approach to thought and language

Logical behaviourism

Bayesian Probability

Aboutness and Justification

Epistemological Externalism and the Project of Traditional Epistemology. Contemporary philosophers still haven't come to terms with the project of

Rule-Following and the Ontology of the Mind Abstract The problem of rule-following

Saul Kripke, Naming and Necessity

Tony Chadwick Essay Prize 2006 Winner Can we Save Qualia? (Thomas Nagel and the Psychophysical Nexus ) By Eileen Walker

Comments on Lasersohn

what makes reasons sufficient?

Mohammad Reza Vaez Shahrestani. University of Bonn

PHILOSOPHY OF MIND (7AAN2061) SYLLABUS: SEMESTER 1

Can Rationality Be Naturalistically Explained? Jeffrey Dunn. Abstract: Dan Chiappe and John Vervaeke (1997) conclude their article, Fodor,

Overcoming Cartesian Intuitions: A Defense of Type-Physicalism

III Knowledge is true belief based on argument. Plato, Theaetetus, 201 c-d Is Justified True Belief Knowledge? Edmund Gettier

Nested Testimony, Nested Probability, and a Defense of Testimonial Reductionism Benjamin Bayer September 2, 2011

Knowledge is Not the Most General Factive Stative Attitude

Hitoshi NAGAI (Nihon University) Why Isn t Consciousness Real? (2) Day 2: Why Are We Zombies?

Evidence and armchair access

Privileged Access to the Mind: What It Is and How It Can Fail. Johannes L. Brandl

Boghossian & Harman on the analytic theory of the a priori

EPISTEMOLOGY for DUMMIES

RESPECTING THE EVIDENCE. Richard Feldman University of Rochester

Transparency and Reflection Matthew Boyle, Harvard University

THE TWO-DIMENSIONAL ARGUMENT AGAINST MATERIALISM AND ITS SEMANTIC PREMISE

The knowledge argument

Received: 30 August 2007 / Accepted: 16 November 2007 / Published online: 28 December 2007 # Springer Science + Business Media B.V.

Coordination Problems

time poses challenging problems. This is certainly true, but hardly interesting enough

Externalism and Self-Knowledge: Content, Use, and Expression

by Blackwell Publishing, and is available at

a0rxh/ On Van Inwagen s Argument Against the Doctrine of Arbitrary Undetached Parts WESLEY H. BRONSON Princeton University

Chapter 5: Freedom and Determinism

24.09 Minds and Machines Fall 11 HASS-D CI

Matthew Parrott. In order for me become aware of another person's psychological states, I must observe her

ZAGZEBSKI ON RATIONALITY

Consciousness Without Awareness

Précis of Empiricism and Experience. Anil Gupta University of Pittsburgh

3. Knowledge and Justification

Lecture 6 Objections to Dualism Princess Elisabeth of Bohemia Correspondence between Descartes Gilbert Ryle The Ghost in the Machine

Against Phenomenal Conservatism

Wittgenstein and Moore s Paradox

Philosophy 5340 Epistemology Topic 4: Skepticism. Part 1: The Scope of Skepticism and Two Main Types of Skeptical Argument

General Philosophy. Dr Peter Millican,, Hertford College. Lecture 4: Two Cartesian Topics

What does McGinn think we cannot know?

Imprint. Self-Knowledge and the Phenomenological Transparency of Belief. Markos Valaris. Philosophers. University of New South Wales

Contextualism and the Epistemological Enterprise

Norman Malcolm ( )

Chalmers says Too Hard ; Dennett says Too Easy

The Externalist and the Structuralist Responses To Skepticism. David Chalmers

The Self and Other Minds

Self-ascription, self-knowledge, and the memory argument

Millian responses to Frege s puzzle

Is it Reasonable to Rely on Intuitions in Ethics? as relying on intuitions, though I will argue that this description is deeply misleading.

Cartesian Rationalism

ON EPISTEMIC ENTITLEMENT. by Crispin Wright and Martin Davies. II Martin Davies

INTUITION AND CONSCIOUS REASONING

Propositions as Cognitive Acts Scott Soames Draft March 1, My theory of propositions starts from two premises: (i) agents represent things as

spring 05 topics in philosophy of mind session 10


Philosophy 5340 Epistemology. Topic 6: Theories of Justification: Foundationalism versus Coherentism. Part 2: Susan Haack s Foundherentist Approach

Cartesian Rationalism

Transcription:

H4 (v1), 24.805 F15, Byrne and Paul Armstrong et al. on inner sense 1: Recap: infallibility, self-intimation, and inner sense Infallibility: In A Necessarily, if S avows, with sincerity and understanding, I am in phenomenal state M, then she is in M. Everyday counterexamples. The fearful ex-tinnitus-sufferer; the hypochondriac complaining of sore feet. Pathological cases. Blindness denial, alien hand syndrome, Cotard delusion. There appear to be very few limits on the absurd things people can believe, given the right sort of neurological damage. Burge counterexamples. People sometimes make mistakes about color ranges. They may correctly apply a color term to a certain color, but also mistakenly apply it to shades of a neighboring color they give in when other speakers confidently correct them in unison. (Burge 1979: 100) Imagine someone, Scarlett, who misapplies red as Burge describes. Scarlett says That is red, looking at and demonstrating a reddish orange carrot in good light. Her utterance expresses her belief that the carrot is red; the carrot is not red, so she speaks and believes falsely. She also says That looks red to me, looking at and demonstrating the carrot. Her utterance expresses her belief that the carrot looks red to her; the carrot does not look red to her, but rather reddish orange, so she speaks and believes falsely. Since That looks red to me should evidently be included on Wright s list of phenomenal avowals, this is a counterexample to this instance of In A : In A(RED) Necessarily, if S avows, sincerely and with understanding, x looks red to me, then x does look red to her. Scarlett avows, sincerely and with understanding, that the carrot looks red to her, but it doesn t. Exercise: evaluate the reply that this is not a counterexample, on the grounds that Scarlett does not avow That looks red to me with understanding. After all, Burge himself comments that this style of thought experiment crucially relies on the possibility of attribut[ing] a mental state or event whose content involves a notion that the subject incompletely understands (107). Self-intimation (positive version): S-I A Necessarily, if S is in phenomenal state M, then S believes/knows that she is in M (and so, assuming the appropriate linguistic capacities, is disposed to avow I am in M ). Everyday counterexamples. Inattention to ringing in ears; exercise: try to find a counterexample involving dreaming. Pathological cases. Arguably, something may look red to a blindsighter, despite his refusal to avow that it does. Luminosity. The knowledge version of S-I A (obtained by deleting believes from believes/knows ) is tantamount to the claim that phenomenal states (and their absences) Burge, Tyler. Individualism and the Mental. Midwest Studies in Philosophy 4: 73-122. Blackwell Publishing, 1979. Blackwell Publishing. All rights reserved. This content is excluded from our Creative Commons license. For more information, see http://ocw.mit.edu/help/faq-fair-use/.

2 are (in the terminology of Williamson 2000: ch. 4) luminous, against which Williamson mounts some serious arguments. Williamson s criticisms depend on a feature of knowledge that is not shared by belief, so a retreat to the belief version of S-I A is formally on the cards. But it is not very well motivated. To the extent that S-I A is tempting, it is in its stronger knowledge version (which is the one Wright himself endorses). To see this, note that the initially tempting thought can be put this way. If I am in phenomenal state M then my avowal I am in M is not merely true: rather, it is also permissible for me to avow I am in M, thereby asserting that I am in M. But, given the widely accepted thesis that it is permissible to assert P only if one knows P, the initially tempting thought amounts to the knowledge version of S-I A. 2: Recap: groundlessness and baselessness One of McDowell s main complaints is that Wright has conflated avowals being groundless (non-inferential) with their being baseless: As [Wright] says, How can you tell? is always inappropriate ; and there is nothing upon which such claims are based (p. 14). Now Wright takes it that the essence of the Cartesian conception attacked by Wittgenstein is the idea that the authority of avowals can be understood on the model of observational authority. And the authority of observations is indeed non-inferential. But it is precisely not baseless. (McDowell 2000: 48) So the inner observation model does not respond to the difficulty at all: Suppose someone claims to have a philosophical problem that finds expression in asking: How is it possible that our knowledge of our own inner lives is baseless? I am going to urge (section III below) that such a form of words fails to present us with any determinate philosophical difficulty; but for now the mere claim to have a difficulty that can be expressed like this will serve my purpose. If someone claims to have such a difficulty, it is obviously unhelpful to respond by giving a picture that merely leaves the baselessness out. But that is what the observational picture does. (48) But what is baselessness? Distinguish two ways of taking How can you tell? (or How did you know? : (a) By what means or method did you know? (b) By what evidence did you know? Example: how did you know that Bob was in his office? (a) by looking; (b) by the fact that his light was on. Baselessness corresponds to the first way, and groundlessness to the second. Baselessness, first attempt: The claim that p is baseless iff By what means or method did you know that p? is always inappropriate. But what does inappropriate mean? Obviously not impolite, but neither is the question odd in the manner of Do colorless green ideas sleep furiously? Rather, inappropriateness seems simply amount to the fact that the question usually prompts I don t know. (If you ask Churchland, he will be more forthcoming.) This gives us two versions of baselessness: Williamson, Timothy. Knowledge and Its Limits. Oxford University Press, 2000. Oxford University Press. All rights reserved. This content is excluded from our Creative McDowell, John. Response to Crispin Wright. Knowing Our Own Minds. Oxford University Press, 2000. Oxford University Press. All rights reserved. This content is excluded from our Creative Commons license. For more information, see http://ocw.mit.edu/help/faq-fair-use/.

3 The claim that p is weakly-baseless iff By what means or method did you know that p? can t be (positively, knowingly(?), ) answered. Note baselesness is poor terminology, because the idea that it is not known what the base is, not that there isn t one. The terminology is a better fit for: The claim that p is strongly-baseless iff it is known that p and there is no means or method by which it is known. Granting that avowals are weakly-baseless, this would hardly seem to be a problem. On the other hand, if avowals are strongly-baseless, surely something should be said to make this palatable. But we have been given no reason to think that they are strongly-baseless. Q: what kind of baselessness does McDowell have in mind? Aren t the other two marks obviously puzzling? McDowell seems to accept that they are marks, yet does not discuss them. Q: why? 3: Armstrong: some quotes from ch. 15 Kant s description of introspection as inner sense is perfectly justified. Perception is not logically dependent on language for its existence, as is shown by the fact that animals and young children can perceive although they cannot speak. In the same way, there seems no reason to think that introspection is logically dependent on language. In the case of perception, we must distinguish between the perceiving, which is a mental event, and the thing perceived, which is something physical. In the case of introspection we must similarly distinguish between the introspecting and the thing introspected. Confusion is all the more easy in the latter case because both are mental states of the same mind. If we make the materialist identification of mental states with material states of the brain, we can say that introspection is a self-scanning process in the brain. In the case of most forms of sense-perception we say that we perceive with certain parts of the body. These parts of the body we call sense-organs.the so-called proprioceptors, stimulation of which gives rise to bodily perception, are not organs in the fullest sense because their operation is not under the direct control of the will. In bodily perception there is nothing we perceive with. Bodily perception has the further peculiarity that its object our own body is private to each perceiver. If each of us were confined to bodily sense, there would be no overlap between our sense-fields, in the way that there is overlap in the case of the other senses. This privacy is purely empirical, and we can imagine having the same direct perceptual access to states of other people s bodies that we now have to our own. These two features of bodily perception make it an appropriate model for introspection conceived of as inner sense. In the first place, when we are aware of happenings in our own minds, there is nothing that we are aware with. (If there were an organ involved it would be something whose operation was under the direct control of our will. This, in turn, would demand a power of gaining direct Armstrong, D. M. A Materialist Theory of the Mind. Routledge and Kegan Paul, 1968. Routledge and Kegan Paul. All rights reserved. This content is excluded from our Creative

4 awareness of the different states of this introspective organ. At some point there would have to be a direct awareness that did not involve the use of an organ.) In the second place, our introspective awareness is confined to our own minds. It was argued elsewhere that it is only an empirical fact that our direct awareness of mental states is confined to our own mind. We could conceive of a power of acquiring non-verbal non-inferential knowledge of current states of the minds of others. This would be a direct awareness, or perception, of the minds of others. Indeed, when people speak of telepathy it often seems to be this they have in mind. Perception may be erroneous. Contrary to what might be called the Cartesian tradition, it is equally possible for introspection to be erroneous. This does not mean that introspective awareness may not in fact regularly satisfy the conditions for knowledge. The only further topic to be recapitulated is that concerning the biological value of introspection. If there are to be purposive trains of mental activity, then there must equally be some means by which we become apprised of our current mental state. Only so can we adjust mental behaviour to mental circumstances. For instance, if we are doing a calculation in our head we will need to become aware of the current stage in the mental calculation that we have reached. Only if we do become so aware will we know what to do next. So there must be a way of becoming aware of our current mental state, which means that there must be introspection. The biological value of purposive mental activity is, of course, obvious. It permits of a far more sophisticated response to stimuli if we can think before we act. But such thinking must be purposive thinking to be of real value. What, then, does constitute the unity of the group of happenings that constitute a single mind? We are back at the problem that proved Hume s downfall I do not see any way to solve the problem except to say that the group of happenings constitute a single mind because they are all states of, processes in or events in, a single substance In taking the mind to be a substance, then, the Cartesian Dualists show a true understanding of the formal features of the concept of mind. Their view that the mind is a spiritual substance is, however, a further theory about the nature of this substance, and, while it is an intelligible theory, it is a singularly empty one Modern materialism is able to put forward a much more plausible (and much more easily falsified) theory: the view that the mind is the brain. But we must however grant Hume that the existence of the mind is not something that is given to unaided introspection. All that inner sense reveals is the occurrence of individual mental happenings. 1 This is the difficulty from which this section started. I suggest that the solution is that the notion of a mind is a theoretical concept: something that is postulated to link together all the individual happenings of which introspection makes us aware. In speaking of minds, perhaps even in using the word I in the course of introspective reports, we go beyond 1 Odd. Why does Armstrong think this? Cf. Nichols and Stich on handout 5. Armstrong, D. M. A Materialist Theory of the Mind. Routledge and Kegan Paul, 1968. Routledge and Kegan Paul. All rights reserved. This content is excluded from our Creative

5 what is introspectively observed. Ordinary language here embodies a certain theory. The particular nature of this substance is a further theoretical question, but when ordinary language speaks of minds it postulates some sort of substance. 4: Telepathy In introspection we have direct, non-inferential, awareness of our own mental states.it is perfectly conceivable that we should have direct awareness of the mental states of others. In Materialist terms, we have scanners that can scan some of our own inner states, but [as a matter of contingent fact] no scanners that can scan the inner states of others. (Armstrong 1968: 124) The inner-sense theory offers a picture of self-knowledge as a kind of mindreading applied to oneself, a faculty that happens to be aimed in one direction rather than another. However, our ordinary self-knowledge [is] different from this sort of self-telepathy ; if someone s self-knowledge were produced by a reliable self-scanner, there is still a sense in which such a person would remain opaque to himself (Moran 2001: 91). [N]othing short of fullfblown Cartesianism can explain the asymmetries in anything like the same way there can be no scaledfdown observational model of selffknowledge which preserves the advantages of the Cartesian account while direct witness of another s mental states. avoiding its unaffordable costs. The problem is that the kind of authority I have over the avowable aspects of my mental life is not transferable to others: there is no contingency or, none of which we have any remotely satisfactory concept* whose suspension would put other ordinary people in a position to avow away on my behalf, as it were. (Wright 2000: 24) *In particular, I do not think that we have any satisfactory concept of what it would be to be in touch with others mental states telepathically. I do not mean, of course, to rule it out that someone might prove, by dint of his own occurrent suspicions and afflictions, to be a reliable guide to the states of mind of another. But that possibility falls conspicuously short of the idea that a subject might share direct witness of another s mental states. Consider again my pronouncement that my legs are crossed. Here it does seem that, although I may rely on no evidence or inference or observation, so there is an epistemic third-person/first-person contrast in terms of the basis on which the pronouncement is made, still, my word is no better than that of an observer. On a given occasion, my body could clearly be in a state that my proprioceptive mechanism cannot distinguish from the state of my legs being crossed. I could also prove to be very unreliable in reporting my limb positions or bodily movements with my eyes closed. Furthermore, in addition to the possibility of an observer simply looking to see whether my legs are crossed (a possibility that is already in place), we can easily conceive of someone else gaining knowledge of my limb position proprioceptively (say, if her brain was so hooked up to my limbs as to receive direct information about their position). Such a person could have a non-observational facility for telling where my limbs are that is equal to mine. Under the circumstances, it seems that there would be no residual difference between the status of my pronouncements on my limb positions and hers. Armstrong, D. M. A Materialist Theory of the Mind. Routledge and Kegan Paul, 1968. Routledge and Kegan Paul. All rights reserved. This content is excluded from our Creative Moran, Richard. Authority and Estrangement. Princeton University Press, 2001. Princeton University Press. All rights reserved. This content is excluded from our Creative Wright, Crispin. Self-knowledge: the Wittgensteinian legacy. Knowing Our Own Minds. ed. C. Wright, B. C. Smith and C. Macdonald. Oxford University Press, 2000. Oxford University Press. All rights reserved. This content is excluded from our Creative

6 But now suppose that someone else became able to ascribe to me reliably and correctly present mental states without relying on any observation or evidence. It does not seem as though this would suffice for her pronouncements to inherit the status of my avowals. For one thing, establishing her reliability in ascribing occurrent mental states to me would at least partly depend on finding a regular match between her ascriptions and my avowals. But, more importantly, so long as there was no question about my grasp of the language or my sincerity, it seems that my avowals would continue to have a much stronger prima facie claim to being correct. If disagreement broke out between us over what is now going on in my mind, her consistent past success in reading my mind would not be sufficient ground for taking her word over mine. It seems, rather, that we would take the disagreement as signaling the waning of her mind-reading powers. Similar remarks would apply to the imaginary scenario in which an external brain-scanner is set up to replace one s own self-scanning mechanism and render verdicts on one s present mental states. Suppose our subject persistently denies feeling hunger, and there is no behavioral evidence that goes against her denials. That is to say, the subject s behavior and her no-hunger avowals line up. It seems that we would sooner question the reliability of the brain-scanner that appeared to register hunger sensation than reject the subject s denial. If so, then the special status normally assigned to avowals would seem to survive even as we envisage a brain science allowing observers to look inside and see. (Bar-On 2004: 100-1) Let telepathy be a way of non-inferentially knowing about others mental states. (We should add a restriction to rule out ordinary cases of seeing that she is angry to count as telepathy, because that might be non-inferential too. Exercise: what?) Then one could argue against the inner sense theory in either Wright s style or Moran s and Bar-On s. Wright P1. If the inner-sense theory is true, telepathy is possible. P2. Telepathy is not possible. C. The inner-sense theory is not true. Moran/Bar-On P1. If the inner-sense theory is true, self-knowledge has feature F (because it s the result of self-telepathy). P2. Self-knowledge does not have feature F. C. The inner-sense theory is not true. Exercise: what is the most plausible filling for F? Bar-On, Dorit. Speaking My Mind: Expression and Self-Knowledge. Oxford University Press, 2004. Oxford University Press. All rights reserved. This content is excluded from our Creative Commons license. For more information, see http://ocw.mit.edu/help/faq-fair-use/.

H4 (v1), 24.805 F15, Byrne and Paul References Armstrong, D. M. 1968. A Materialist Theory of the Mind. London: Routledge and Kegan Paul. Bar-On, D. 2004. Speaking My Mind: Expression and Self-Knowledge. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Burge, T. 1979. Individualism and the mental. Midwest Studies in Philosophy 4: 73-122. Page reference to the reprint in Burge 2007. Burge, T. 2007. Foundations of Mind. Oxford: Oxford University Press. McDowell, J. 2000. Response to Crispin Wright. Knowing Our Own Minds. ed. C. Wright, B. C. Smith and C. Macdonald. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Moran, R. 2001. Authority and Estrangement. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press. Williamson, T. 2000. Knowledge and Its Limits. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Wright, C. 2000. Self-knowledge: the Wittgensteinian legacy. Knowing Our Own Minds. ed. C. Wright, B. C. Smith and C. Macdonald. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

MIT OpenCourseWare http://ocw.mit.edu 24.805 Topics in Epistemology: Self-Knowledge Fall 2015 For information about citing these materials or our Terms of Use, visit: http://ocw.mit.edu/terms.