A note about the notion of exp 10 (log 10 (modulo 1))(x)

Similar documents
Grade 6 correlated to Illinois Learning Standards for Mathematics

Grade 6 Math Connects Suggested Course Outline for Schooling at Home

Houghton Mifflin MATHEMATICS

Mathematics as we know it has been created and used by

Curriculum Guide for Pre-Algebra

Grade 7 Math Connects Suggested Course Outline for Schooling at Home 132 lessons

Georgia Quality Core Curriculum

Ramsey s belief > action > truth theory.

MISSOURI S FRAMEWORK FOR CURRICULAR DEVELOPMENT IN MATH TOPIC I: PROBLEM SOLVING

Macmillan/McGraw-Hill SCIENCE: A CLOSER LOOK 2011, Grade 4 Correlated with Common Core State Standards, Grade 4

Number, Part I of II

ON SOPHIE GERMAIN PRIMES

FOURTH GRADE. WE LIVE AS CHRISTIANS ~ Your child recognizes that the Holy Spirit gives us life and that the Holy Spirit gives us gifts.

NEJS 101a Elementary Akkadian-Fall 2015 Syllabus

Lecture 3. I argued in the previous lecture for a relationist solution to Frege's puzzle, one which

Rationalizing Denominators

6.041SC Probabilistic Systems Analysis and Applied Probability, Fall 2013 Transcript Lecture 3

2.1 Review. 2.2 Inference and justifications

McDougal Littell High School Math Program. correlated to. Oregon Mathematics Grade-Level Standards

COMPOSITIO MATHEMATICA

Math 10 Lesson 1 4 Answers

Artificial Intelligence: Valid Arguments and Proof Systems. Prof. Deepak Khemani. Department of Computer Science and Engineering

ORDINAL GENESIS 1:1/JOHN 1:1 TRIANGLE (Part 1)

Intersubstitutivity Principles and the Generalization Function of Truth. Anil Gupta University of Pittsburgh. Shawn Standefer University of Melbourne

Development of Writing

Hardback?18.00 ISBN

Foundations of World Civilization: Notes 2 A Framework for World History Copyright Bruce Owen 2009 Why study history? Arnold Toynbee 1948 This

The Roles of Mesopotamian Bronze Age Mathematics Tool for State Formation and Administration Carrier of Teachers Professional Intellectual Autonomy

4181 ( 10.5), = 625 ( 11.2), = 125 ( 13). 311 PPO, p Cf. also: All the errors that have been made in this chapter of the

COPYRIGHTED MATERIAL. Many centuries ago, in ancient Alexandria, an old man had to bury his son. Diophantus

ADAIR COUNTY SCHOOL DISTRICT GRADE 03 REPORT CARD Page 1 of 5

Circularity in ethotic structures

Number, Part I. Lesson 1. Rules and Definitions. Rules

Russell on Denoting. G. J. Mattey. Fall, 2005 / Philosophy 156. The concept any finite number is not odd, nor is it even.

Macmillan/McGraw-Hill SCIENCE: A CLOSER LOOK 2011, Grade 3 Correlated with Common Core State Standards, Grade 3

The Fixed Hebrew Calendar

Remarks on the philosophy of mathematics (1969) Paul Bernays

1. Lukasiewicz s Logic

ANGELS SPECIALIST SCHOOL INTERNATIONAL SCHEME OF WORK FOR MATHEMATICS (TERM 2) GRADE 3

Rational and Irrational Numbers 2

Truth and Simplicity F. P. Ramsey

9 Knowledge-Based Systems

MITOCW Lec 2 MIT 6.042J Mathematics for Computer Science, Fall 2010

I thought I should expand this population approach somewhat: P t = P0e is the equation which describes population growth.

But we may go further: not only Jones, but no actual man, enters into my statement. This becomes obvious when the statement is false, since then

Book Review. Pisa (Fabrizio Serra) ISBN pp. EUR Reviewed by Nathan Sidoli

Illustrating Deduction. A Didactic Sequence for Secondary School

Possibility and Necessity

Al-Sijistani s and Maimonides s Double Negation Theology Explained by Constructive Logic

Artificial Intelligence Prof. Deepak Khemani Department of Computer Science and Engineering Indian Institute of Technology, Madras

15 Does God have a Nature?

1 Central to the idea of the canon is Euclid s Sectio canonis. As the earliest complete treatise, probably dating from

SUMMARY COMPARISON of 6 th grade Math texts approved for 2007 local Texas adoption

Logical Omniscience in the Many Agent Case

Why Did Jesus Catch 153 Fish?

How should one feel about their place in the universe? About other people? About the future? About wrong, or right?

Pakistan International School Jeddah (English Section) Final Term Syllabus Outline Year 4. English. Science

Rethinking Knowledge: The Heuristic View

Chadwick Prize Winner: Christian Michel THE LIAR PARADOX OUTSIDE-IN

Lecture Notes on Classical Logic

Introduction Symbolic Logic

The Rightness Error: An Evaluation of Normative Ethics in the Absence of Moral Realism

Neurophilosophy and free will VI

Russell on Descriptions

The Decline of the Traditional Church Choir: The Impact on the Church and Society. Dr Arthur Saunders

175 Chapter CHAPTER 23: Probability

Bounded Rationality :: Bounded Models

computers Almost 4,000 years ago, a young The Genesis of the Electronic Pennsylvania Sumerian Dictionary by stephen j. tinney

The Epic of Gilgamesh The Great Man Who Did Not Want To Die by Helen Sader February 05, 2013

IN his paper, 'Does Tense Logic Rest Upon a Mistake?' (to appear

Since Michael so neatly summarized his objections in the form of three questions, all I need to do now is to answer these questions.

Prompt: Explain van Inwagen s consequence argument. Describe what you think is the best response

Are Miracles Identifiable?

Based on the translation by E. M. Edghill, with minor emendations by Daniel Kolak.

FIRST STUDY. The Existential Dialectical Basic Assumption of Kierkegaard s Analysis of Despair

Raphael The School of Athens. Hello Plato

On A New Cosmological Argument

AKC Lecture 1 Plato, Penrose, Popper

Surveying Prof. Bharat Lohani Department of Civil Engineering Indian Institute of Technology, Kanpur. Module - 7 Lecture - 3 Levelling and Contouring

Russell: On Denoting

Mesopotamian civilizations formed on the banks of the Tigris and Euphrates rivers in what is today Iraq and Kuwait.

correlated to the Massachussetts Learning Standards for Geometry C14

The Online Library of Liberty

Chapter 4 The Hebrew Alphabet

ORDINAL GENESIS 1:1/JOHN 1:1 TRIANGLE (Part 2) By Leo Tavares

Advanced Hebrew Open Book Quiz on Brotzman s Introduction

What is the Frege/Russell Analysis of Quantification? Scott Soames

Structural realism and metametaphysics

Math Matters: Why Do I Need To Know This? 1 Logic Understanding the English language

PHILOSOPHY 5340 EPISTEMOLOGY

Index. Part Part Part Page No.

to representationalism, then we would seem to miss the point on account of which the distinction between direct realism and representationalism was

Potten End Church of England Primary School Curriculum Map. Year 6

Philosophy 125 Day 21: Overview

Mesopotamian Civilization For use with pages 16 23

Conference on the Epistemology of Keith Lehrer, PUCRS, Porto Alegre (Brazil), June

IT is frequently taken for granted, both by people discussing logical

Predicate logic. Miguel Palomino Dpto. Sistemas Informáticos y Computación (UCM) Madrid Spain

A Priori Bootstrapping

Undergraduate Course Descriptions

Transcription:

A note about the notion of exp 10 (log 10 (modulo 1))(x) Concise observations of a former teacher of engineering students on the use of the slide rule Jens Høyrup Roskilde University Section for Philosophy and Science Studies http://www.akira.ruc.dk/~jensh Contribution au Séminaire SAW : Histoire des mathématiques, histoire des pratiques économiques et financières Séance du 6 janvier 2012 : «Usage de la position pratiques mathématiques, pratiques comptables»

As is well known among those who are interested in Babylonian mathematics or mathematical astronomy, the Babylonian sexagesimal place value system was a floating-point system, that is, the notation contained no indication of absolute order of magnitude. A number 1 25 might stand for any number 60 n (1 60+25), where n Z. [1] In the language of modern set theory and algebra, we may also say that it stands for the equivalence class of numbers whose logarithms (base 60) are congruent modulo 1 the set exp 60 (log 60 (modulo 1))(1 60+25). If we introduce the notation mod m for modulo with respect to the multiplicative group of positive rational numbers, we may instead write (1 60+25)(mod m 60) apparently simpler, but presupposing the whole apparatus of modern group theory. [2] Whatever the formulation, we are moving within second-order arithmetic. Those who taught mathematics to secondary school or engineering students during the first half of the twentieth century (indeed, until the early 1970s) knew a very similar instrument, the slide rule: The slide rule The principle was that numbers from 1 to 10 were mapped onto a unit length (on the standard specimen I show, 25 cm) according to their decadic logarithm: in consequence, multiplication of numbers corresponded to the 1 In order to avoid zeroes not written by the Babylonians, I adopt the convention of writing multiples of 10 in bold digits, multiples of 1 in normal font. What is traditionally written 1 20 (or with some indication of order of magnitude) thus becomes 1 2. 2 Since the Babylonian place value system was only used for numbers whose fractional part can be written as a finite sexagesimal fractions, it did not fill out this group; on the other hand, it was used to write irregular numbers, that is, numbers whose reciprocal cannot be written in this way, and therefore goes beyond the multiplicative group of regular numbers. It can be described as the multiplicative semi-group N 60 Z. -1-

geometric addition of lengths, while division became geometric subtraction. [3] Evidently, products might well fall within the interval from 10 to 100, that is, on the prolongation of the unit interval, of which only the beginning (from 10 to 11) is indicated on the slide rule; similarly, quotients might fall in the interval from 0.1 to 1, of which only the end (0.9 to 1) is indicated. However, shifting the endpoint of the tongue, corresponding to a division respectively a multiplication by 10, would give the correct digits of the product or quotient within the interval from 1 to 10. Only the distinctions between 1.1 and 11 and between 0.9 and 9 rule out an interpretation where numbers are mapped onto the unit interval according to the mantissa of their decadic logarithm, in which case (e.g.) 5 would have represented all numbers 5 10 n, n Z in other terms, the whole class 5 (mod m 10). A variant of the instrument was circular in shape: circular slide rule On this device, there can be no distinction between 1.1 and 11, and the mantissa-interpretation seems most adequate numbers with undetermined order of magnitude or equivalence classes (mod m 10). Some of us who taught the use of the device had been trained on Bourbaki-style algebra, Riemann surfaces and multi-valued functions. If it had been our job to teach abstract group theory, the slide rule might have been a perfect illustration of the notions of subgroups and cosets. However, I have never heard about any such use, which may have been deemed too technical and too bound to applications to please Bourbaki s spirit; nor did I use it myself for this purpose during the four years where I was an 3 I skip discussion of the various scales for powers and trigonometric functions. -2-

university instructor of algebra. The slide rule was taught in view of computation. How would one then teach the use of the slide rule? Certainly not in terms of equivalence classes in any formulation (including numbers with undetermined order of magnitude, which is just a way of dividing out the subgroup of powers of 10 and thus to produce the equivalence classes as cosets). If teaching students who already knew about logarithms, you might start by the additive analogue, showing how 3+4 can be found by means of two ordinary rulers: Addition and then go on with illustrative examples on the slide rule itself. But you might also go directly to these illustrations, as would anyhow be necessary in the teaching of students who did not know about logarithms for instance 2x2 Here, you might point out the miracle that the operation on 2 and 2 does indeed give 4 (or something very close to it), while that on 2 and 1.5 yields 3. In the next step, it could be explained that 2 and 1.5 might also stand for 20 and 15, and that the result would therefore have to stand for one -3-

of the other possible interpretations of 3 namely 300. But you would always stick to explanations that a reading n of the slide rule might stand for specific numbers differing by a factor 10 n, never that it stood for the whole class of such numbers. The difference is similar to the one between first- and second-order logic. Even introductory teaching of logic (as all logic until less than two centuries ago) starts by first-order-logic for instance ((p q) q) p, not by the trivial second-order embedding (S standing for the space of propositions ) (p,q S)(((p q) q) p). Even in mathematics, as we know, genuine second-order formulations were rare (not quite absent, but obviously difficult to think of even for gifted mathematicians) before Weierstraß. When calculating with the slide rule, students (or physicists, or engineers, etc.) had various ways to keep track of the intended order of magnitude. In simple cases it would just be known, as in this illustration of 11 11, determined as 1.1 1.1: 1.1 x 1.1 Nobody would need much reflection to pick the value 121 for the result most calculators probably would not even take note that the factors are 1.1, not 11, and that the immediate outcome is 1.21, not 121. In complex calculations, one would for instance divide out powers of 10 and write them down separately, multiply (and divide) the factors and observe when new factors 10 or 10 1 resulted, and in the end combine the digits resulting -4-

on the slide rule with the power 10 n resulting for the counting of powers [4] perhaps also reflecting on the verisimilitude of the outcome as an extra check when possible. [5] In conclusion, we may explain the structure of the Babylonian placevalue system as (a semigroup contained within) the quotient group of the group of positive rational numbers constituted by equivalence-classes (mod m 60) numbers deprived of sexagesimal order of magnitude. We should not believe the Babylonian calculators less intelligent than we are nor however that they were mathematically more bright than Euclid, who never got the idea to explain the doctrine of odd and even in terms of equivalence classes and groups, and who defined equality of ratios (Elements V, def. 5) almost as if it was done in first-order logic (current translations restitute a second-order formulation any... any, but Euclid s own words are much less clear). Second-order logic and its mathematical counterparts grew out not of a particular intelligence of our epoch but of a particular intellectual organization of university mathematics, deliberately separate from engineering applications (however much part of the outcome has then turned out to be highly relevant for advanced applications). Neither Babylonian scribe school students nor their teachers lived within a similar intellectual framework mutatis mutandis, their world corresponded to that of engineering students and their teachers of the nineteenth and earlier twentieth century, when the teachers had been 4 Within a sequence of multiplicative operations on the slide rule, the calculator would thus not necessarily keep track of orders of magnitude but just think of the intermediate result as, e.g., 3.56 or 35.6. 5 Errors were of course made, not only by students but also by working engineers. Around the age of ten I read a book by Negley Farson; the title is no longer in my memory, but it may have been a Danish translation of Going Fishing. The only thing I remember from the book is a story about an engineer who because of a slide-rule error used 100 times as much dynamite as he should for a supposedly minor work on a river, with the result that the river was completely barred, and a salmon species spawning just then in this river and nowhere else was almost eradicated. I used the story as a warning to my engineering students when they believed that errors concerning only the place of the decimal point were less serious than other errors. -5-

trained in the cours-d analyse, not the Bourbaki tradition. Until sources teach us differently and the sources are probably too meagre in this respect to tell us anything we should therefore believe their thought and training in the use of floating-point calculation to have been more similar to that of almost-contemporary engineering students than to that of Bourbaki. To render 1 25 as 1 25 (or 1;25, in an alternative notation) gives more information than warranted by what is written on the clay tablet, but it is hardly a betrayal of what was on the mind of the scribe who wrote the signs if only we keep in mind, as the scribe certainly did, that the signs taken in isolation might just as well mean 1 25 or 1`25, and that any interpretation will be legitimate as long as we stay within the context of the multiplicative group of rational numbers, though not within the corresponding defective additive-multiplicative semiring (to use words whose generality does not translate into anything a Babylonian calculator would recognize, but whose interpretation in the concrete case would not have told him anything new): once addition intervenes, at least the relative order of magnitude of addends has to be decided. When making a transliteration of a cuneiform text we do not behave differently. [6] Today, nobody would produce a string of uninterpreted 6 A brief and simplified explanation for non-assyriologists: The Mesopotamian script was created in the later fourth millennium BCE, and was originally purely ideographic and pictographic, for which reason we cannot know to which language it corresponded and in any case it was not used to render spoken language but for accounting. However, toward the mid-third millennium it started to be used in royal inscriptions and in literary texts (hymns, proverbs), that is, to render language namely Sumerian and the ideograms can now be understood as logograms, signs for particular words. Sometimes, simplification led to merger of original distinct signs, which could thus be read in several ways. In order to render language the scribes needed to indicate grammatical elements, and logograms were recycled for this purpose according to their approximate phonetic value for instance, the same sign might be used for the syllables /bi/, /be/, /pi/ and /pe/). In the earlier second millennium, Sumerian had died except as a scholarly language known by scribes, and the logograms where now mostly meant to be pronounced in the current Akkadian language (of which Babylonian and Assyrian were the main dialects), even though some Sumerian values were taken over as loan-words. The phonetic values were conserved and new were sometimes added. Moreover, from early times, some signs could serve as determinatives, which -6-

sign names: in as far as possible the transliteration has already decided upon the reading of each sign as a determinative, a logogram or a syllabogram (and which logogram respectively syllabogram). We know that the scribe knew about the ambiguities of the system, and also that our decision may sometimes be mistaken and is sometimes arbitrary the Akkadian loanword igûm shows that the sign i g i would on some occasions or in some environments be pronounced according to the Sumerian phonetic value, while occasional interlinear glosses make it clear that it would sometimes be thought of as a logogram for Akkadian pani, in front of. In any case, the transliteration renders a possible and even likely interpretation of the thought of the scribe, although it may at times not hit the point exactly; however, to render it as if the author of the text had thought of nothing but sign names would be much further off the mark. were not meant to be pronounced but indicated the semantic class of the following sign, thus facilitating its interpretation but adding another ambiguity. The sign lists that were used in scribal training indicate sign names for the signs, as a rule corresponding to a possible Sumerian logographic reading. -7-