There are two common forms of deductively valid conditional argument: modus ponens and modus tollens.

Similar documents
The Problem of Induction and Popper s Deductivism

Session 10 INDUCTIVE REASONONING IN THE SCIENCES & EVERYDAY LIFE( PART 1)

The problems of induction in scientific inquiry: Challenges and solutions. Table of Contents 1.0 Introduction Defining induction...

Chapter 1. What is Philosophy? Thinking Philosophically About Life

MCQ IN TRADITIONAL LOGIC. 1. Logic is the science of A) Thought. B) Beauty. C) Mind. D) Goodness

Academic argument does not mean conflict or competition; an argument is a set of reasons which support, or lead to, a conclusion.

Sydenham College of Commerce & Economics. * Dr. Sunil S. Shete. * Associate Professor

PHIL2642 CRITICAL THINKING USYD NOTES PART 1: LECTURE NOTES

Lecture 3 Arguments Jim Pryor What is an Argument? Jim Pryor Vocabulary Describing Arguments

Establishing premises

Philosophy 12 Study Guide #4 Ch. 2, Sections IV.iii VI

Semantic Entailment and Natural Deduction

CHAPTER THREE Philosophical Argument

Richard L. W. Clarke, Notes REASONING

Philosophy of Science. Ross Arnold, Summer 2014 Lakeside institute of Theology

Critical Thinking 5.7 Validity in inductive, conductive, and abductive arguments

What is an argument? PHIL 110. Is this an argument? Is this an argument? What about this? And what about this?

Business Research: Principles and Processes MGMT6791 Workshop 1A: The Nature of Research & Scientific Method

Also, in Argument #1 (Lecture 11, Slide 11), the inference from steps 2 and 3 to 4 is stated as:

Logic Appendix: More detailed instruction in deductive logic

Unit. Categorical Syllogism. What is a syllogism? Types of Syllogism

Philosophy 1100: Introduction to Ethics. Critical Thinking Lecture 1. Background Material for the Exercise on Validity

A R G U M E N T S I N A C T I O N

Chapter 8 - Sentential Truth Tables and Argument Forms

Conditionals II: no truth conditions?

In view of the fact that IN CLASS LOGIC EXERCISES

Artificial Intelligence: Valid Arguments and Proof Systems. Prof. Deepak Khemani. Department of Computer Science and Engineering

Philosophical Arguments

Scientific Method and Research Ethics Questions, Answers, and Evidence. Dr. C. D. McCoy

Tutorial A03: Patterns of Valid Arguments By: Jonathan Chan

PHI 1500: Major Issues in Philosophy

What is the Nature of Logic? Judy Pelham Philosophy, York University, Canada July 16, 2013 Pan-Hellenic Logic Symposium Athens, Greece

Ilija Barukčić Causality. New Statistical Methods. ISBN X Discussion with the reader.

PHILOSOPHY 102 INTRODUCTION TO LOGIC PRACTICE EXAM 1. W# Section (10 or 11) 4. T F The statements that compose a disjunction are called conjuncts.

LOGIC LECTURE #3: DEDUCTION AND INDUCTION. Source: A Concise Introduction to Logic, 11 th Ed. (Patrick Hurley, 2012)

CLASS #17: CHALLENGES TO POSITIVISM/BEHAVIORAL APPROACH

Argumentative Analogy versus Figurative Analogy

Recall. Validity: If the premises are true the conclusion must be true. Soundness. Valid; and. Premises are true

A. Problem set #3 it has been posted and is due Tuesday, 15 November

Introduction to Philosophy

Chapter 1. Introduction. 1.1 Deductive and Plausible Reasoning Strong Syllogism

Appendix: The Logic Behind the Inferential Test

Verificationism. PHIL September 27, 2011

Ayer on the criterion of verifiability

Introducing Our New Faculty

Logic: The Science that Evaluates Arguments

INDUCTION. All inductive reasoning is based on an assumption called the UNIFORMITY OF NATURE.

Falsification or Confirmation: From Logic to Psychology

The Roman empire ended, the Mongol empire ended, the Persian empire ended, the British empire ended, all empires end, and none lasts forever.

CONTENTS A SYSTEM OF LOGIC

A Critique of Friedman s Critics Lawrence A. Boland

Study Guides. Chapter 1 - Basic Training

Key definitions Action Ad hominem argument Analytic A priori Axiom Bayes s theorem

Selections from Aristotle s Prior Analytics 41a21 41b5

HOW TO ANALYZE AN ARGUMENT

Popper s Falsificationism. Philosophy of Economics University of Virginia Matthias Brinkmann

Logic. A Primer with Addendum

complete state of affairs and an infinite set of events in one go. Imagine the following scenarios:

Phil 1103 Review. Also: Scientific realism vs. anti-realism Can philosophers criticise science?

T. Parent. I shall explain these steps in turn. Let s consider the following passage to illustrate the process:

Informalizing Formal Logic

Module 1: Science as Culture Demarcation, Autonomy and Cognitive Authority of Science

Can A Priori Justified Belief Be Extended Through Deduction? It is often assumed that if one deduces some proposition p from some premises

Philosophy 1100: Ethics

1. To arrive at the truth we have to reason correctly. 2. Logic is the study of correct reasoning. B. DEDUCTIVE AND INDUCTIVE ARGUMENTS

Lecture 2.1 INTRO TO LOGIC/ ARGUMENTS. Recognize an argument when you see one (in media, articles, people s claims).

Thinking and Reasoning

Lecture 6 Keynes s Concept of Probability

Intro Viewed from a certain angle, philosophy is about what, if anything, we ought to believe.

The poverty of mathematical and existential truth: examples from fisheries science C. J. Corkett

Logic Book Part 1! by Skylar Ruloff!

Revisiting the Socrates Example

Falsification of Popper and Lakatos (Falsifikace podle Poppera a Lakatose)

VERIFICATION AND METAPHYSICS

Announcements. CS243: Discrete Structures. First Order Logic, Rules of Inference. Review of Last Lecture. Translating English into First-Order Logic

PHILOSOPHIES OF SCIENTIFIC TESTING

Does Deduction really rest on a more secure epistemological footing than Induction?

Philosophy Epistemology. Topic 3 - Skepticism

Logic: Deductive and Inductive by Carveth Read M.A. CHAPTER IX CHAPTER IX FORMAL CONDITIONS OF MEDIATE INFERENCE

Example Arguments ID1050 Quantitative & Qualitative Reasoning

Unit. Science and Hypothesis. Downloaded from Downloaded from Why Hypothesis? What is a Hypothesis?

1. Introduction Formal deductive logic Overview

Criticizing Arguments

In Search of the Ontological Argument. Richard Oxenberg

Karl Popper & The Philosophy of Science. What Makes a Theory Scientific?

Inductive inference is. Rules of Detachment? A Little Survey of Induction

Experimental Design. Introduction

SAMPLE ESSAY 1: PHILOSOPHY & SOCIAL SCIENCE (1 ST YEAR)

Exercise Sets. KS Philosophical Logic: Modality, Conditionals Vagueness. Dirk Kindermann University of Graz July 2014

Chapter 5: Ways of knowing Reason (p. 111)

Courses providing assessment data PHL 202. Semester/Year

26:010:685 Social Science Methods in Accounting Research

In a previous lecture, we used Aristotle s syllogisms to emphasize the

L4: Reasoning. Dani Navarro

PHILOSOPHICAL RAMIFICATIONS: THEORY, EXPERIMENT, & EMPIRICAL TRUTH

Ayer and Quine on the a priori

Revista Economică 66:3 (2014) THE USE OF INDUCTIVE, DEDUCTIVE OR ABDUCTIVE RESONING IN ECONOMICS

Basic Concepts and Skills!

Chapter 3: Basic Propositional Logic. Based on Harry Gensler s book For CS2209A/B By Dr. Charles Ling;

1.5 Deductive and Inductive Arguments

Transcription:

INTRODUCTION TO LOGICAL THINKING Lecture 6: Two types of argument and their role in science: Deduction and induction 1. Deductive arguments Arguments that claim to provide logically conclusive grounds for their conclusion are deductive arguments (here the conclusion is claimed to lead down from the premises). Where the premises do indeed guarantee the conclusion, the argument is held to be deductively valid. 1.1 Deductive validity Where the premises guarantee with certainty the conclusion, the relation between premises and conclusion is referred to as deductive validity. Consider this argument: All jumblies have two moggs Sam is a jumblie So Sam has two moggs Notice the conclusion follows logically from (i.e., to be entailed by) the premises here. 1.2 The different forms of deductive argument Typically, a deductive argument comes in the form of a syllogism (an argument with two premises and a conclusion, and there is a single term which appears in both premises (as in all the examples we have used so far): All A are B X is A Therefore X is B One common type of syllogism is the hypothetical syllogisms. This includes a hypothetical or conditional statement in one of the premises "If... then...". They are not asserting two statements they are only asserting a single statement. The proposition which follows the "If" is called the "antecedent", and the proposition which follows the "then" is called the consequent. There are two common forms of deductively valid conditional argument: modus ponens and modus tollens. Modus ponens ( putting or asserting the antecedent ) Premise 1: If you are a mother, then you are female Premise 2: A You are a mother Conclusion: Therefore B Therefore you are female antecedent = A = you are a mother consequent = B = you are female Modus tollens ( taking away or denying the consequent ): Not B You are not female Therefore not A Therefore you are not a mother antecedent = A = you are a mother consequent = B = you are female However, if you assert the consequent or deny the antecedent, your argument will be not valid. We have an error or fallacy in the argument: Fallacy of asserting the consequent B Therefore A You are female Therefore you are a mother

Fallacy of denying the antecedent: Not A Therefore not B You are not a mother Therefore you are not female Another common type of syllogism is what is called argument by elimination. Here the syllogism involves a disjunctive statement in the premises. A disjunctive statement is an "Either... or..." statement: Either A or B Not A Therefore B Either he is sleeping or he is watching TV He is not sleeping Therefore he is watching TV We can also have deductively valid forms in which the premises are a mixture of hypothetical and disjunctive statements: Either A or B If A then C If B then C Therefore C Either he's sleeping or he's watching TV If he's sleeping then he's breathing If he's watching TV then he's breathing Therefore he's breathing 2. Inductive arguments "Inductive means "to bring forward". In inductive arguments, the premises support the conclusion to a greater or less extent, so we are looking at degrees of likeliness or probability. For example: Many smokers die of lung cancer. John is a smoker. Therefore John will die of lung cancer. Here, even if the premises are true, the conclusion is not guaranteed, because the first premise, by saying "many", allows that some smokers won't die of lung cancer. John could be one of those. There may be something about John which puts him in the low-risk category, such that it is not even probable that he will die of lung cancer. Now consider this argument: I have 1000 balls in this bag. 999 are red and 1 is black. Therefore, when I put my hand in and draw out one ball, it will be red Here, the relationship between premises and conclusion is very strong indeed, meaning that the conclusion is very likely. However, it is still not guaranteed, because there is an outside chance that I'll draw out the single black ball. With inductive arguments, we never have logical validity in the deductive sense; the conclusion is never entailed by the premises. So all inductive arguments are logically invalid. Instead, what we have is degrees of strength or plausibility. Varieties of inductive argument Inductive arguments come in different forms, but they all involve stating the premises and then moving beyond them. - Predictive argument: we make a prediction based on the past or present (e.g., The logic exam has always been 2 hours long. Therefore, it will be 2 hours long next year ). - Causal reasoning: we infer a causal relation from past experience (e.g., I can t log on. Therefore, the network must be down ). - Statistical generalisation: we observe statistical trends in a sample and then project these onto the population. Eg: if 70% of our sample first year students are female, then we might conclude inductively that 70% of all first years are female. - Argument from analogy: we conclude something based on a comparison/similarity between two things. Eg: John and Mary are registered psychologists, and they both practice. Lee also a registered psychologist. Therefore, Lee is likely to be in practice.

3. Deduction and induction: advantages and disadvantages 3.1 Deduction + The advantage of valid deductive arguments is: If the premises are true, the conclusion follows "truth preserving". - This same benefit, however, is bought at a high price the price of emptiness. They do not give us any new knowledge that isn't already in the premises. 3.2 Induction + It does give new information in the conclusion which is not already contained in the premises. - But this advantage is bought at a price, the price of fallibility. The disadvantage of induction is that the truth of the premises does not guarantee the truth of the conclusion. 4. The role of induction and deduction in science The word "science" means knowledge. Science is the careful and systematic search for knowledge. In this search for knowledge, we need to find evidence for or against our hypotheses about the world. Here is a view of science from Cohen and Nagel, the authors of one of the most famous texts on logic and scientific method: If we look at all the sciences we find that the constant and universal feature of science is its general method, which consists in the persistent search for truth, constantly asking: Is it so? To what extent is it so? Why is it so? And this can be seen on reflection to be the demand for the best available evidence, the determination of which we call logic. Scientific method is thus the persistent application of logic as the common feature of all reasoned knowledge. From this point of view scientific method is simply the way in which we test impressions, opinions or surmises b y examining the best available evidence for and against them... in essence scientific method is simply the pursuit of truth as determined by logical considerations (emphasis added). (Cohen & Nagel, 1957, p. 192) It is worth bearing in mind that, science is amongst the most open of methods, provided that it is properly conducted (i.e., in the true spirit of critical inquiry). Cohen and Nagel examine non-scientific methods like dogma, relying on authority, intuition, etc. and they say that these methods: are all inflexible, that is, none of them can admit that it will lead us into error. Hence none of them can make provision for correcting its own results. What is called scientific method differs radically from these by encouraging and developing the utmost possible doub t, so that what is left after such doubt is always supported by the best available evidence. As new evidence or new doubts arise it is the essence of scientific method to incorporate them... Its method, then, makes science progressive because it is never too certain about its results. (Cohen & Nagel, 1957, p. 195) This is what is meant by identifying science as critical inquiry. Science is self-critical, in that it accepts that we are fallible, and attempts to employ the best error-detection mechanisms that we have. Now, in scientific inquiry, we meet both kinds of argument inductive and deductive. How we evaluate an argument depends to some extent on what kind of argument it is. 4.1 Induction in science Science is generally an inductive process of searching for knowledge, a process of discovery. In science, all forms of induction are used: inductive generalisation, predictive argument, etc. The conclusions of scientific arguments are expressed as contingent statements (i.e., statements which may be either true or false, such as: "Smoking causes lung cancer"). Science proposes theories and attempts to support these theories via evidence. However, the theories are themselves the result of experience and observations i.e., the result of inductive processes. Therefore, scientific reasoning cannot yield certainty. This is what is meant by saying that science does not prove theories. Evidence plays the role of the premises in an inductive argument. For example, if we find that, the % of people contracting lung cancer is consistently and significantly higher in smokers than in nonsmokers, we use those observations as evidence for our inductive conclusion. If we want to be cautious, we conclude not that smoking causes lung cancer, but that smoking increases the risk of contracting lung cancer and simply make a statement about the observed correlation.

4.2 Deduction in science Evidence will also play a role in the way deductive arguments are used in science. Here, we need to know about background events in the history of science. Early last century, philosophers of science were arguing that science proceeds inductively by verification (i.e., showing that the theory is true). That is, we propose a theory, and then find instances and evidence which support that theory. But Karl Popper, said that this method is flawed, because no matter how many supporting instances we find, we can never prove true a general theory. For example, imagine that our theory is: "All crows are black". This theory is based on our past observations. Instead, according to Popper, we attempt to falsify the theory, because we can falsify a general theory. A single observation of a nonblack crow would falsify our theory. So Popper introduced falsificationism as a scientific approach, and falsifiability (instead of verifiability) as the criterion for a scientific theory. According to Popper, whatever your theory is, you must be able to specify what observation would in principle make it false. If your theory is consistent with any actual or possible state of affairs, then your theory is unfalsifiable, and so it is not scientific. This is where deduction comes in, because falsification is done via a deductive argument. It uses the familiar form of modus tollens (denying the consequent): Not B Therefore not A If the theory is true, we shall observe X (e.g., If all crows are black, then the crow around the corner will be black) We do not observe X (The crow around the corner is not black) Therefore the theory is not true (Therefore, not all crows are black) But notice that the first premise in the above crow argument is itself a deduction. All crows are black. There is a crow around the corner. The crow around the corner will be black In other words, our hypothesis, the observation which we propose to make to support the theory is logically entailed by the theory. This is part of the hypothetico-deductive method, and is essential to sound theory testing. In Step 1 we begin with our theory (e.g., All crows are black ) and in Step 2 we logically/deductively derive a hypothesis from the theory (e.g., The crow around the corner will be black ). It is this hypothesis that we empirically test in Step 3. Because of the logical validity of modus tollens, disconfirming evidence is stronger than confirming evidence (just as Popper argued). Obviously, if a theory is true, it will never be falsified. But Popper was not claiming that we should actually falsify our scientific theory. He was insisting that we make clear what observation would falsify our theory if our theory were false. A common problem is that it s not clear sometimes how the researcher's hypothesis is derived from the theory that is supposedly being tested. Also, when we put a hypothesis to empirical test in psychology, we typically use a sample drawn from a larger population of interest. Therefore, we deal with probabilities in our statistical test, and these probabilities are included in our argument s premises. So even if we use modus tollens, our conditional first premise has reference to likeliness in the consequent. As we ll see, this means that we never actually falsify the hypothesis that we are testing. (These issues are crucial for the way in which we go about doing scientific psychology, and we are just flagging them here; we ll return to them later) Conclusion In conclusion, evidence can be used to either support (via induction) or disconfirm (via deduction) a theory. And we use deduction to derive a testable hypothesis from our theory. In the next lecture, we begin to look at this process of evaluating arguments. References Cohen, M. R. & Nagel, E. (1957). An introduction to logic and scientific method. London: Routledge & Kegan Paul.