If only I were, then I am. The Rational Imagination. By Ruth M.J. Byrne. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, pp. ISBN $32.

Similar documents
part one MACROSTRUCTURE Cambridge University Press X - A Theory of Argument Mark Vorobej Excerpt More information

Development Part III. Moral Reasoning

Phil 114, Wednesday, April 11, 2012 Hegel, The Philosophy of Right 1 7, 10 12, 14 16, 22 23, 27 33, 135, 141

Chapter 12: Areas of knowledge Ethics (p. 363)

Summary of Kant s Groundwork of the Metaphysics of Morals

Kant On The A Priority of Space: A Critique Arjun Sawhney - The University of Toronto pp. 4-7

Honours Programme in Philosophy

Aristotle and Aquinas

Theory of Knowledge Series

Kant and his Successors

Behavior and Other Minds: A Response to Functionalists

Treatise I,iii,14: Hume offers an account of all five causes: matter, form, efficient, exemplary, and final cause.

Belief, Rationality and Psychophysical Laws. blurring the distinction between two of these ways. Indeed, it will be argued here that no

Mathematics as we know it has been created and used by

DEPARTMENT OF PHILOSOPHY UNIVERSITY OF CALIFORNIA, RIVERSIDE. Graduate course and seminars for Fall Quarter

Saving the Substratum: Interpreting Kant s First Analogy

Department of Philosophy. Module descriptions 2017/18. Level C (i.e. normally 1 st Yr.) Modules

The Middle Path: A Case for the Philosophical Theologian. Leo Strauss roots the vitality of Western civilization in the ongoing conflict between

EPIPHENOMENALISM. Keith Campbell and Nicholas J.J. Smith. December Written for the Routledge Encyclopedia of Philosophy.

Aspects of Western Philosophy Dr. Sreekumar Nellickappilly Department of Humanities and Social Sciences Indian Institute of Technology, Madras

The Sea-Fight Tomorrow by Aristotle

EXERCISES, QUESTIONS, AND ACTIVITIES My Answers

PHILOSOPHY-PHIL (PHIL)

KANT, MORAL DUTY AND THE DEMANDS OF PURE PRACTICAL REASON. The law is reason unaffected by desire.

Ethical non-naturalism

SOCRATES, PIETY, AND NOMINALISM. love is one of the most well known in the history of philosophy. Yet some fundamental

DISTINCTIVE QUALITIES OF THE CATHOLIC SCHOOL (2ND ED.)

Department of Philosophy

Review of Thomas C. Brickhouse and Nicholas D. Smith, "Socratic Moral Psychology"

Structure and essence: The keys to integrating spirituality and science

A Graphical Representation of the Reconstructionist World-View (with a Mixture of Science Thrown in for Good Measure) by Ronald W. Satz, Ph.D.

Rethinking Knowledge: The Heuristic View

To be able to define human nature and psychological egoism. To explain how our views of human nature influence our relationships with other

CALVIN 02 TRINITY and TRUTH

Faults and Mathematical Disagreement

Virtue Ethics. A Basic Introductory Essay, by Dr. Garrett. Latest minor modification November 28, 2005

Reviewed Work: Why We Argue (and How We Should): A Guide to Political Disagreement, by Scott Aikin and Robert Talisse

Philosophy Courses Fall 2011

Chapter Six. Aristotle s Theory of Causation and the Ideas of Potentiality and Actuality

R. M. Hare (1919 ) SINNOTT- ARMSTRONG. Definition of moral judgments. Prescriptivism

The Unbearable Lightness of Theory of Knowledge:

Two books, one title. And what a title! Two leading academic publishers have

LEIBNITZ. Monadology

SYSTEMATIC RESEARCH IN PHILOSOPHY. Contents

Pihlström, Sami Johannes.

Hume s emotivism. Michael Lacewing

Simplicity and Why the Universe Exists

MY PURPOSE IN THIS BOOK IS TO PRESENT A

A Brief History of Thinking about Thinking Thomas Lombardo

Thinking and Reasoning

Reading the Nichomachean Ethics

Intro Viewed from a certain angle, philosophy is about what, if anything, we ought to believe.

A DILEMMA FOR JAMES S JUSTIFICATION OF FAITH SCOTT F. AIKIN

How to Live a More Authentic Life in Both Markets and Morals

How Gödelian Ontological Arguments Fail

THE STUDY OF UNKNOWN AND UNKNOWABILITY IN KANT S PHILOSOPHY

9 Knowledge-Based Systems

Two Kinds of Ends in Themselves in Kant s Moral Theory

The Mental and the Normative: a Non-psychological Account

Martha C. Nussbaum (4) Outline:

Knowing your right from your left: brain science and the future of Christian mission

THE COMMON GOOD IN FAMILY AND COMMUNITY. Paul Versluis (November 10, 2013)

Introduction. 1 Bertrand Russell, The Problems of Philosophy (Indianapolis: Hackett Publishing Company, n.d.), 7.

Practical Wisdom and Politics

ETHICAL THEORIES. Review week 6 session 11. Ethics Ethical Theories Review. Socrates. Socrate s theory of virtue. Socrate s chain of injustices

The Ontological Argument for the existence of God. Pedro M. Guimarães Ferreira S.J. PUC-Rio Boston College, July 13th. 2011

Personal Philosophy Paper. my worldview, metaphysics, epistemology and axiology which have traces of Neo-

Can A Priori Justified Belief Be Extended Through Deduction? It is often assumed that if one deduces some proposition p from some premises

Lecture 3. I argued in the previous lecture for a relationist solution to Frege's puzzle, one which

Habermas and Critical Thinking

J. L. Mackie The Subjectivity of Values

In Search of the Ontological Argument. Richard Oxenberg

RULES, RIGHTS, AND PROMISES.

Kripke s skeptical paradox

Rhetoric = The Art of Persuasion. The history of rhetoric and the concepts of ethos, pathos and logos began in Greece.

FUNDAMENTAL PRINCIPLES OF THE METAPHYSIC OF MORALS. by Immanuel Kant

A dialogical, multi-agent account of the normativity of logic. Catarin Dutilh Novaes Faculty of Philosophy University of Groningen

Phil Aristotle. Instructor: Jason Sheley

Deontological Perspectivism: A Reply to Lockie Hamid Vahid, Institute for Research in Fundamental Sciences, Tehran

How Subjective Fact Ties Language to Reality

From Necessary Truth to Necessary Existence

Divine omniscience, timelessness, and the power to do otherwise

FIRST STUDY. The Existential Dialectical Basic Assumption of Kierkegaard s Analysis of Despair

Philosophical Perspectives, 16, Language and Mind, 2002 THE AIM OF BELIEF 1. Ralph Wedgwood Merton College, Oxford

Robot como esclavos modernos

Reductio ad Absurdum, Modulation, and Logical Forms. Miguel López-Astorga 1

Welcome back to week 2 of this edition of 5pm Church Together.

18LOGICAL REASONING. sufficient assumption & supporting principle. fill the hole

Lecture 4.2 Aquinas Phil Religion TOPIC: Aquinas Cosmological Arguments for the existence of God. Critiques of Aquinas arguments.

Broad on Theological Arguments. I. The Ontological Argument

Plato s Concept of Soul

Marcel Sarot Utrecht University Utrecht, The Netherlands NL-3508 TC. Introduction

THE RELATIONSHIP BETWEEN SCIENCE, RELIGION AND ARISTOTELIAN THEOLOGY TODAY

IDHEF Chapter 2 Why Should Anyone Believe Anything At All?

INTRODUCTION TO A TRANSCENDENTAL CRITICISM OF PHILOSOPHIC THOUGHT 1

Dartmouth College THE DIVINE SIMPLICITY *

Chapter Summaries: Introduction to Christian Philosophy by Clark, Chapter 1

Thought is Being or Thought and Being? Feuerbach and his Criticism of Hegel's Absolute Idealism by Martin Jenkins

Rule-Following and the Ontology of the Mind Abstract The problem of rule-following

Integrated Studies 002: Human Morality and Emotions University of Pennsylvania Spring 2017

Transcription:

Citation: Hogan, M. J. (2005). If only I were, then I am. Review of Ruth M.J. Byrne The rational imagination. PsychCRITIQUES Contemporary Psychology: APA Review of Books (50) 49. If only I were, then I am. The Rational Imagination By Ruth M.J. Byrne Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 2005. 254 pp. ISBN 0-262-02584-1. $32.00 Reviewed by Michael Hogan Michael Hogan, Department of Psychology, NUI, Galway, Ireland. Email: michael.hogan@nuigalway.ie

If only I were rational, then I am rational. I m confused. We re confused! If only I were rational, then I would have better applied the possibilities imagined, the counterfactuals and semifactuals. If only! Even if! If only we had accepted that the supreme gift of life evolving is rationality, then we would have realized that it is a dialogue of reason we should have worked to master. Even if we d all read our Plato, Aristotle, Kant, Hegel, James, Dewey, and Kekes, the probability of calculating the optimal solution to our problem would have been difficult. If only we had merged the mythos of our ever-present past with the logos of our ever-present present, then we would have realized that it is imagination and reason that are one: it is a dialogue of imagination and reason that provides us with the solutions. If only the solutions were correct! Even if! Tell me, who says the logic of possibilities is rational? Some years ago, in the faint light of a December morning, the air crisp and cold, I recall sitting happily wrapped in a duffle coat, surrounded by fellow students who listened on, wistful and confused, as our kindly professor hammered out the art of logic. Even if our professor were a renaissance sculptor who equalled Leonardo Da Vinci in appetite and skill, he could not have shaped order from the chaos of conclusion-from-premises-proposed. Perhaps it was the abstract examples used, or the absence of warm porridge and tea in the belly, but logic became, for many, the greatest nightmare of modern living. Rather than depart with crafted minds - Vetruvian symmetry of thought and a love of rationality - many students marched to morning tea with a chip on their shoulder. Unfortunate is the conclusion that our logic seminars did not instil the pragmatic spirit of C.S Peirce, William James, John Dewey, or John Kekes. Little did we appreciate at the time that conformity to standards of rationality is not a matter of choice, for if one means to adapt to the

contingencies of the world, a policy against rationality cannot be pursued for long: It leads either to death or inconsistency. We apply our own selection pressure. Ruth Byrne and her colleagues have investigated the thinking process for over 20 years. In seeking to understand how people imagine alternatives to reality, Byrne has come to the conclusion that the human imagination is rational. This conclusion has been drawn from a unique perspective on the function of imagination, a perspective that emphasises how it is we apply our rational machinery when thinking about possibilities. It is argued that people make inferences by imagining alternative possibilities, and that the imagination is rational because counterfactual thoughts rely on thinking about possibilities. The research findings used to support this argument illustrate how rationality functions around the fault lines of reality - the subtle flutter between the real and the unreal, the factual and the counterfactual. The great significance of this research is the rewarding conclusion that imagination and rationality are one, even if they don t always appear to cooperate. In the spirit of Dewey (1910), Byrne s book, The Rational Imagination, tells us much about how we think. And in an era when good sentiment and good judgement are unjustly confused by another new generation of lay and academic psychologists, Byrne s book is beneficial: It is a book that tells us what it is we actually do rather than what it is we should do. What we do One of the primary reasons why human imagination is one of the last frontiers of the mind is because people differ; they differ in the efficiency and efficacy of their working memory computations, the visual-spatial and linguistic abilities that undergird their cognition, the dispositions, goals, and strategies shaping their action,

etc. At the same time, people share a common heritage and many common characteristics of action; they share a tendency to play - a predisposition rooted in a deep-seated goal a tendency to engage the world and adapt to the world. As Piaget well recognized, we learn from sensorimotor experience to conceive of the laws of action in the concrete world. Being active, we soon imitate and then invent our own action sequences, playing with all the permutations and combinations that we can muster. Our play is inherently rewarding: so much so that we are willing to accept the negatives that arrive with the positives. We accept shame with pride, misery with joy, fear with courage, and so on. Play opens the schema leading action into the realm of possibility. It is possibility that leads us into danger and away from danger. Every action is the realization of a possibility. Without a world where possibility co-exists with fact, imagination with reality, we would never think if only. We would never conjecture how things might have turned out differently, or experience a sense that something else almost happened. We would never consider alternatives to the facts of our past and we would find it difficult, if not impossible, to avoid the mistakes of the past. Emotions associated with hope, relief, regret, and guilt would be non-events. In essence, we would lack essential creativity and vital emotional experience in our practical day-today existence. Collectively, we wouldn t survive. The ability to create counterfactual alternatives to reality is a significant product of evolution. It is an ability that develops throughout childhood and adolescence and is impaired by injury to the frontal cortex. Byrne and colleagues have discovered that the kinds of possibilities people think about are guided by a set of principles that shape how the rational imagination manifests. If your friend John has a tendency to drive fast and you hear that he was in a car accident, you might

propose, if John was driving fast, he was injured (if A then B). From here, you are likely to imagine the true possibility, John was driving fast and he was injured (A and B), but not the false possibility, John was driving fast and he was not injured (A and not-b). Our first principle: we think about true possibilities. Second, people think about few possibilities. Given John s conditional (if A then B), we tend to think only about the most salient true possibility (A and B), not the less salient possibilities. It s possible that John was not driving fast and was not injured (not-a and not-b). It s also possible that John was not driving fast and was injured (not-a and B). Nonetheless, less salient means less accessible. Now, let s suppose you know the facts - John was not driving fast and he was not injured - and let s suppose you test Byrne s third principle by recounting the following counterfactual conditional to your friend, if John had been driving fast he would have been injured. The third principle states that some ideas require people to think about two possibilities. The counterfactual statement leads your friend to consider the conjecture, John was driving fast and he was injured, and the presupposed facts, John was not driving fast and he was not injured. The fourth principle harkens back to, and places a functional twist on, our reality principle: when people do think about dual possibilities, they often think about possibilities that once may have been true possibilities but can be true no longer. In other words, the rational imagination can work with false ideas as if they are true. This is the essential function of the counterfactual. We may assume that overriding the reality principle can be beneficial if correct. Byrne s research and insights, however, tell us less about the conditions under which counterfactual imagination is beneficial and correct in various contexts of adaptation.

The fifth principle tells us that people can readily imagine a counterfactual possibility for an idea that is mentally represented with a second possibility. If the local café sells not one, but two brands of tea, and you order the one that tastes like drain cleaner, then you are more likely to say if only I had ordered the other. More choice equals more counterfactuals. Many of our ecologically situated representations naturally capture the variety. The sixth principle refers to the logic of an obligation if you work a second job, you must inform the tax inspector. When people think about an obligation they think about two possibilities, the rule and the forbidden possibility. Combine choice and rules and the tree of imagined possibilities blossoms. The seventh principle is that the possibilities people keep in mind reflect the temporal order of events in the world: if you didn t declare that second job to the tax man, you ll find your name in his little black book. These seven principles, along with a number of related corollaries, form the basis for the argument that the counterfactual imagination is rational. A reasonable view of some of what we do. What we should do Many years after our December mornings of festive logic had faded from memory, I met again our kindly professor strolling by the sea. He said, Michael, I d like to build a model of the thinking brain. My first useful thought, after a variety of feelings, was to his logic, and his vision of logic as a process - a process indispensable to the art of philosophical thought. My second thought was to the brain, and my vision of the brain as embodying structure, process, and function. How to formulate a kindly word? Both thoughts, the products of a rational imagination, led to the conclusion

that our courageous professor would benefit from a thorough reading of cognitive neuroscience. After collecting three of the leading texts in the field at the time, I returned to his office bearing gifts. I haven t heard from him since. It has been four years! If there is any moral to be had from a story where the conclusion is inaction rather than action, then it might be that the logic of the philosopher and the logic of the psychologist are not necessarily constructed of the same stuff. This can make difficult the dialogue between how the mind works and how we think. Traditionally, the philosopher is less interested in the phylogenesis and ontogenesis of the human system and more interested in whether or not its leading process cognition can be usefully applied to the discovery of Truth. On the other hand, psychologists, accepting historical embeddedness, lifelong development, multidirectionality, multidimensionality, plasticity, contextualism, and multidisciplinarity, are more interested in working and re-working their partial view of the elements and relations within the human system that shape their mental model of how that system works, and tend to view the discovery of Truth as a secondary ideal. In other words, the aesthetics and sentiment of the philosopher and psychologist often differ. In order to bridge that divide we need to fashion a collective aesthetic and sentiment and apply our formal logic to first study how the developing brain, in contexts multifarious, conducts the process of thinking, how the outcome of this process is manifest in action, and how, in contexts multifarious, the action manifest is adaptively beneficial or not. Fundamentally, as we think about thinking, we should couch our focus within a broad developmental cognitive neuroscience view. From here, we accept that there are many levels and links in the chain of reason that bring us closer to understanding, to the truth about how the mind works, how we think, and how we

adapt. Byrne s carefully written and insightful book takes us direct to the midpoint, to how we think. Now, let s call for the dialogue to extend backward and forward, up and down, inside and out. Let s call for an end to confusion. If only! Even if! References Dewey, J. (1910/1991). How We Think. New York: Prometheus Books.