T. Parent. I shall explain these steps in turn. Let s consider the following passage to illustrate the process:

Similar documents
Suppressed premises in real life. Philosophy and Logic Section 4.3 & Some Exercises

PHI 1500: Major Issues in Philosophy

HANDBOOK. IV. Argument Construction Determine the Ultimate Conclusion Construct the Chain of Reasoning Communicate the Argument 13

Also, in Argument #1 (Lecture 11, Slide 11), the inference from steps 2 and 3 to 4 is stated as:

HANDBOOK (New or substantially modified material appears in boxes.)

Artificial Intelligence: Valid Arguments and Proof Systems. Prof. Deepak Khemani. Department of Computer Science and Engineering

PHILOSOPHY 102 INTRODUCTION TO LOGIC PRACTICE EXAM 1. W# Section (10 or 11) 4. T F The statements that compose a disjunction are called conjuncts.

There are two common forms of deductively valid conditional argument: modus ponens and modus tollens.

Philosophy 1100: Ethics

Criticizing Arguments

Selections from Aristotle s Prior Analytics 41a21 41b5

Basic Concepts and Skills!

Revisiting the Socrates Example

Conditionals II: no truth conditions?

Explanatory Indispensability and Deliberative Indispensability: Against Enoch s Analogy Alex Worsnip University of North Carolina at Chapel Hill

Recall. Validity: If the premises are true the conclusion must be true. Soundness. Valid; and. Premises are true

Study Guides. Chapter 1 - Basic Training

What is an argument? PHIL 110. Is this an argument? Is this an argument? What about this? And what about this?

In view of the fact that IN CLASS LOGIC EXERCISES

HOW TO ANALYZE AN ARGUMENT

Does the Skeptic Win? A Defense of Moore. I. Moorean Methodology. In A Proof of the External World, Moore argues as follows:

The cosmological argument (continued)

Tutorial A03: Patterns of Valid Arguments By: Jonathan Chan

Logic Appendix: More detailed instruction in deductive logic

Introduction to Philosophy. Spring 2017

What is the Nature of Logic? Judy Pelham Philosophy, York University, Canada July 16, 2013 Pan-Hellenic Logic Symposium Athens, Greece

Semantic Entailment and Natural Deduction

CHAPTER THREE Philosophical Argument

Announcements. CS243: Discrete Structures. First Order Logic, Rules of Inference. Review of Last Lecture. Translating English into First-Order Logic

Announcements. CS311H: Discrete Mathematics. First Order Logic, Rules of Inference. Satisfiability, Validity in FOL. Example.

The antecendent always a expresses a sufficient condition for the consequent

Handout 1: Arguments -- the basics because, since, given that, for because Given that Since for Because

Royal Institute of Philosophy

Proofs of Non-existence

What would count as Ibn Sīnā (11th century Persia) having first order logic?

HANDBOOK (New or substantially modified material appears in boxes.)

b) The meaning of "child" would need to be taken in the sense of age, as most people would find the idea of a young child going to jail as wrong.

Statements, Arguments, Validity. Philosophy and Logic Unit 1, Sections 1.1, 1.2

The Problem of Induction and Popper s Deductivism

Portfolio Project. Phil 251A Logic Fall Due: Friday, December 7

Leibniz, Principles, and Truth 1

Précis of Empiricism and Experience. Anil Gupta University of Pittsburgh

The Little Logic Book Hardy, Ratzsch, Konyndyk De Young and Mellema The Calvin College Press, 2013

2. Refutations can be stronger or weaker.

Philosophy 5340 Epistemology Topic 4: Skepticism. Part 1: The Scope of Skepticism and Two Main Types of Skeptical Argument

Exercise Sets. KS Philosophical Logic: Modality, Conditionals Vagueness. Dirk Kindermann University of Graz July 2014

Thinking and Reasoning

Follow Will of the People. Your leftist h. b. ave often d1sgusted b h

Lecture 3 Arguments Jim Pryor What is an Argument? Jim Pryor Vocabulary Describing Arguments

Philosophical Arguments

Informalizing Formal Logic

Introduction to Logic

Chapter 2 Analyzing Arguments

Chapter 9- Sentential Proofs

Cognitivism about imperatives

Paley s Inductive Inference to Design

Denying the antecedent and conditional perfection again

REASONING ABOUT REASONING* TYLER BURGE

Introducing Our New Faculty

9 Methods of Deduction

BELIEF POLICIES, by Paul Helm. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, Pp. xiii and 226. $54.95 (Cloth).

Lecture 8 Property Dualism. Frank Jackson Epiphenomenal Qualia and What Mary Didn t Know

WHO'S IN CHARGE? HE'S NOT THE BOSS OF ME. Reply. Dear Professor Theophilus:

Chapter 1. Introduction. 1.1 Deductive and Plausible Reasoning Strong Syllogism

Can A Priori Justified Belief Be Extended Through Deduction? It is often assumed that if one deduces some proposition p from some premises

The way we convince people is generally to refer to sufficiently many things that they already know are correct.

Syllogism. Exam Importance Exam Importance. CAT Very Important IBPS/Bank PO Very Important. XAT Very Important BANK Clerk Very Important

Logic: A Brief Introduction. Ronald L. Hall, Stetson University

A Puzzle about Knowing Conditionals i. (final draft) Daniel Rothschild University College London. and. Levi Spectre The Open University of Israel

PLEASE DO NOT WRITE ON THIS QUIZ

A solution to the problem of hijacked experience

Deductive Forms: Elementary Logic By R.A. Neidorf READ ONLINE

IA Metaphysics & Mind S. Siriwardena (ss2032) 1 Personal Identity. Lecture 4 Animalism

General Philosophy. Dr Peter Millican,, Hertford College. Lecture 4: Two Cartesian Topics

Introduction to Logic

MATH1061/MATH7861 Discrete Mathematics Semester 2, Lecture 5 Valid and Invalid Arguments. Learning Goals

Session 10 INDUCTIVE REASONONING IN THE SCIENCES & EVERYDAY LIFE( PART 1)

24.09x Guide to Logic and Argumentation

MCQ IN TRADITIONAL LOGIC. 1. Logic is the science of A) Thought. B) Beauty. C) Mind. D) Goodness

Chapter 8 - Sentential Truth Tables and Argument Forms

PHILOSOPHY ESSAY ADVICE

Session Two. The Critical Thinker s Toolkit

Artificial Intelligence Prof. P. Dasgupta Department of Computer Science & Engineering Indian Institute of Technology, Kharagpur

4.1 A problem with semantic demonstrations of validity

Learning is a Risky Business. Wayne C. Myrvold Department of Philosophy The University of Western Ontario

Part II: How to Evaluate Deductive Arguments

ON QUINE, ANALYTICITY, AND MEANING Wylie Breckenridge

Phil 3304 Introduction to Logic Dr. David Naugle. Identifying Arguments i

MPS 17 The Structure of Persuasion Logos: reasoning, reasons, good reasons not necessarily about formal logic

Instructor s Manual 1

Introduction. I. Proof of the Minor Premise ( All reality is completely intelligible )

The paradoxical associated conditional of enthymemes

Lecture 17:Inference Michael Fourman

The Philosopher s World Cup

Module 5. Knowledge Representation and Logic (Propositional Logic) Version 2 CSE IIT, Kharagpur

A. Problem set #3 it has been posted and is due Tuesday, 15 November

Unit VI: Davidson and the interpretational approach to thought and language

Helpful Hints for doing Philosophy Papers (Spring 2000)

Overview of Today s Lecture

C. Exam #1 comments on difficult spots; if you have questions about this, please let me know. D. Discussion of extra credit opportunities

Transcription:

Reconstructing Arguments Argument reconstruction is where we take a written argument, and re-write it to make the logic of the argument as obvious as possible. I have broken down this task into six steps: Step 1. Identify premises and conclusions. Step 2. Regiment the language. Step 3. Make explicit suppressed premises. Step 4. Group premises with their conclusions. Step 5. Make the deductive form apparent (where applicable). Step 6. Above all, be fair and charitable in interpreting the argument I shall explain these steps in turn. Let s consider the following passage to illustrate the process: Each particular thought is valueless if it is the result of irrational causes. Obviously, then, the whole process of human thought, what we call Reason, is equally without worth if it is the result of unreasoned causes. Hence every theory of the universe which makes the human mind a result of irrational forces is nonsense. (C.S. Lewis, Miracles) Step One 1. Identify Premises and Conclusions. Underline the Main Conclusion of a passage, and identify any sub-conclusions. Then, note which sentence(s) support(s) the Main Conclusion. Do the same for each sub-conclusion. Note that a sub-conclusion will also be a premise for some other conclusion (assuming it is not just tangential). Our Example (Changes to the passage are in red; also, I use (Pn) for the nth premise, and (Cn) for the nth conclusion): (P1) Each particular thought is valueless if it is the result of irrational causes. Obviously, then, (P2/C1) the whole process of human thought, what we call Reason, is equally without worth if it is the result of unreasoned causes. (C2) Hence every theory of the universe which makes the human mind a result of irrational forces is nonsense. (C.S. Lewis, Miracles)

Step Two 2. Regiment the Language. Copy down the premises and conclusions, keeping the literal wording of the passage EXCEPT to make the following revisions: a. Eliminate unnecessary verbiage (repetition, hedges, tangents, etc.) b. Make the language uniform (e.g., given a particular concept, use the same word to express that concept throughout). The Same Example Continued: (P1) A thought is valueless if it is the result of irrational causes. (P2/C1)So, the whole process of human thought is valueless if it is the result of irrational causes. (C2) So, a theory which makes the whole process of human thought a result of irrational forces is false. Step Three 3. Make Explicit Suppressed Premises Charity is crucial here; see 6. You should add to the list of premises only if it is obvious that the author was implicitly assuming it or if it clearly improves the argument. Deleted: Each particular Deleted: Obviously, then, Deleted:, what we call Reason, Deleted: equally without worth Deleted: unreasoned Deleted: Hence Deleted: every Deleted: of the universe Deleted: mind Deleted: nonsense The Same Example Continued Further: (P1) A thought is valueless if it is the result of irrational causes. (P2) If (P1), then the whole process of human thought is valueless if it is the result of irrational causes. (C1) So, the whole process of human thought is valueless if it is the result of irrational causes. (P3) If (C1), then a theory which makes the whole process of human thought a result of irrational forces is false. (C2) So, a theory which makes the whole process of human thought a result of irrational forces is false. Deleted: P2/ Step Four 4. Group Premises with Their Conclusions. List together a conclusion with its premises: Don t interrupt a conclusion s list of premises with other stuff, even if the passage does that.

In more detail: First list all and only the premises that support the first conclusion. Then write down the conclusion. Next (if applicable) list the additional premises which support the second conclusion. Continue in this way until you reach the Main Conclusion. That Same Example Again: (P1) A thought is valueless if it is the result of irrational causes. (P2) If (P1), then the whole process of human thought is valueless if it is the result of irrational causes. (C1) So, the whole process of human thought is valueless if it is the result of irrational causes. (P3) If (C1), then a theory which makes the whole process of human thought a result of irrational forces is false. (C2) So, every theory which makes the whole process of human thought a result of irrational forces is false. Step Five 5. Make the Deductive Form Apparent, when applicable. Optional: Indicate next to a conclusion what form the argument has (e.g., MP for modus ponens, HS for hypothetical syllogism, etc.). You can also indicate here which premise(s) figure into the argument-form. Even if the argument does not have one of the famous forms, you can still indicate next to the conclusion that it follows deductively. This is done by writing, e.g., from 3, 4 if the conclusion deductively follows from the sentences you numbered as 3 and 4. Yet Again with That Example: (P1) A thought is valueless if it is the result of irrational causes. (P2) If (P1), then the whole process of human thought is valueless if it is the result of irrational causes. (C1) So, the whole process of human thought is valueless if it is the result of irrational causes. [(P1),(P2), MP] (P3) If (C1), then a theory which makes the whole process of human thought a result of irrational forces is false. (C2) So, every theory which makes the whole process of human thought a result of irrational forces is false. [(C1),(P3), MP] Formatted: Indent: First line: 0.25"

Step Six 6. Above all, be fair and charitable in interpreting an argument. Do not make the language uniform at the cost of distorting the author s intentions or making the argument less plausible. The same rule applies when attributing suppressed premises. This means: a. Your revisions do not make the argument of a different type than what the author intends. (See the handout on the Five Argument Types.) b. Your revisions clearly make the premises more supportive of the conclusion. That is, if we grant the revised premises, the conclusion is clearly more likely than with the unrevised premises. c. Your revisions do not make the argument any more controversial overall. The Example, One More Time: (P1) If a thought is the result of irrational causes, then it is worthless. (P2) If (P1), then if the whole process of human thought is the result of irrational causes, then it is worthless. (C1) So, if the whole process of human thought is the result of irrational causes, then it is worthless. (P3) The whole process of human thought is not worthless.. (C2) So, it is false that the whole process of human thought a result of irrational forces. [(C1),(P3), MT] Here, I revised (P3) significantly, and changed the last inference to Modus Tollens. This is because the new (P3) is plausible, whereas the old (P3) was a bit convoluted. It is also more likely that the author had the new (P3) in mind when making the argument. Deleted: If (C1), then a theory which makes the whole process of human thought a result of irrational forces is false Deleted: a theory which makes Deleted: is false Deleted: MP

Another Example. Step 1: Identify premises and conclusions. (P1) The only proof capable of being given that an object is visible, is that people actually see it; the only proof that a sound is audible, is that people hear it: and so of the other sources of our experience. (P2/C1) In like manner, I apprehend, the sole evidence it is possible to produce that any thing is desirable, is that people do actually desire it (P3/C2) No reason can be given why the general happiness is desirable, except that each person, so far as he believes it to be attainable, desires his own happiness. This, however, being a fact, (C3) we have not only all the proof which the case admits of, but all which it is possible to require, that happiness is a good. (J.S. Mill, Utilitarianism) Step 2: Regiment the language. sound is audible is that people hear it. (C1/P2) So, the only proof that anything is desirable is that people desire it (C2/P3) So, the only proof that the general happiness is desirable is that people desire it. (C3) So, we have the only proof that the general happiness is desirable. Deleted: capable of being given Deleted:, Deleted: actually Deleted:, Deleted: : and so of the other sources of our experience Deleted: In like manner, I apprehend, the sole evidence Deleted: it is possible to produce Deleted: Deleted:, Deleted: do actually Deleted: No reason can be given why Deleted:, except that each person, so far as he believes it to be attainable, desires his own happiness Deleted: This, however, being a fact, Deleted: not only all Deleted: which the case admits of, but all which it is possible to require, Deleted: a good

Step 3: Make explicit suppressed premises. sound is audible is that people hear it. (C1) So, the only proof that anything is desirable is that people desire it. (C2) So, the only proof that the general happiness is desirable is that people desire it. (P2) People desire the general happiness. (C3) So, we have the only proof that the general happiness is desirable. Deleted: /P2 Deleted: /P3 Step 4: Group premises with their conclusions. sound is audible is that people hear it. (C1) So, the only proof that anything is desirable is that people desire it. (C2) So, the only proof that the general happiness is desirable is that people desire it. (P2) People indeed desire the general happiness. (C3) So, we have the only proof that the general happiness is desirable. Formatted: Indent: Left: 0", Hanging: 0.25" Step 5: Make the deductive form apparent (where applicable). sound is audible is that people hear it. (C1) So, the only proof that anything is desirable is that people desire it. [By analogy, (P1)] (C2) So, the only proof that the general happiness is desirable is that people desire it. [from(c1)] (P2) People desire the general happiness. (C3) So, we have the only proof that the general happiness is desirable. [from(c2),(p2)]

Step 6: Above all, be fair and charitable in interpreting the argument sound is audible is that people hear it. (C1) So, the only proof that anything is desirable is that people desire it. [By analogy, (P1)] (C2) So, if people desire the general happiness, we have the only proof that the general happiness is desirable. [from(c1)] (P2) People desire the general happiness. (C3) So, we have the only proof that the general happiness is desirable. [(C2),(P2), MP] Formatted: Indent: First line: 0" Deleted: is that people desire it Deleted: from There s no real need to revise the argument any further after step 5. However, I have reworked the inference to (C3) as a case of Modus Ponens, just to make clearer that the claim really does follow from (C2) and (P2). Along with this, I rephrased (C2), so that it is explicitly in the form of a conditional.