The Origin of Interrogation Marks in the Medieval Manuscripts of Plato s Republic and Its Significance in the Tradition of Plato s Dialogues 1

Similar documents
Prentice Hall Literature: Timeless Voices, Timeless Themes, Silver Level '2002 Correlated to: Oregon Language Arts Content Standards (Grade 8)

Prentice Hall Literature: Timeless Voices, Timeless Themes, Bronze Level '2002 Correlated to: Oregon Language Arts Content Standards (Grade 7)

CONTENTS A SYSTEM OF LOGIC

Edinburgh Research Explorer

"Fuldensis, Sigla for Variants in Vaticanus and 1Cor 14:34-5" NTS 41 (1995) Philip B. Payne

Omanson, A Textual Guide to the Greek New Testament ISBN Preface (pgs. 7-9) 1 Cor. 4:17 (pgs ) 1 Cor. 7:34 (pgs.

PAGE(S) WHERE TAUGHT (If submission is not text, cite appropriate resource(s))

Government 203 Political Theorists and Their Theories: Plato Spring Semester 2010 Clark University

Houghton Mifflin English 2004 Houghton Mifflin Company Level Four correlated to Tennessee Learning Expectations and Draft Performance Indicators

Plato's Parmenides and the Dilemma of Participation

What it is and Why it Matters

Does the Third Man Argument refute the theory of forms?

Based on the translation by E. M. Edghill, with minor emendations by Daniel Kolak.

Illustrating Deduction. A Didactic Sequence for Secondary School

On Interpretation. Section 1. Aristotle Translated by E. M. Edghill. Part 1

Logic: Deductive and Inductive by Carveth Read M.A. CHAPTER IX CHAPTER IX FORMAL CONDITIONS OF MEDIATE INFERENCE

What are Truth-Tables and What Are They For?

Vol 2 Bk 7 Outline p 486 BOOK VII. Substance, Essence and Definition CONTENTS. Book VII

, and Imperfect Verbs

On The Logical Status of Dialectic (*) -Historical Development of the Argument in Japan- Shigeo Nagai Naoki Takato

Houghton Mifflin Harcourt Collections 2015 Grade 8. Indiana Academic Standards English/Language Arts Grade 8

CHAPTER 10 NEW TESTAMENT TEXTUAL CRITICISM

Russell: On Denoting

FORMATTING IN M.L.A. FOR THE JUNIOR ESSAY

CHAPTER 2 THE LARGER LOGICAL LANDSCAPE NOVEMBER 2017

PHI 1500: Major Issues in Philosophy

that lived at the site of Qumran, this view seems increasingly unlikely. It is more likely that they were brought from several sectarian communities

DO WE HAVE EARLY TESTIMONY ABOUT JESUS? Chapter Nine

NT1000 Introduction to the New Testament

THE FOUNDATIONS OF MODERN SCIENCE IN THE MIDDLE AGES

Williams on Supervaluationism and Logical Revisionism

C228 Argumentation and Public Advocacy. Essay #2 Defense of a Propositional Value: Oppositional Research

THE CHICAGO STATEMENT ON BIBLICAL INERRANCY A Summarization written by Dr. Murray Baker

Commentary on Sample Test (May 2005)

WTJ 47 (1985)

Constructing A Biblical Message

Scriptural Promise The grass withers, the flower fades, but the word of our God stands forever, Isaiah 40:8

BOOK 1 OF PLATO S REPUBLIC: A WORD BY WORD GUIDE TO TRANSLATION (VOL 2: CHAPTERS 13 24) BrownWalker.com

GRAMMAR IV HIGH INTERMEDIATE

Templates for Writing about Ideas and Research

WALK. Copyright. All Saints Press. This Way. Stations of the Cross. for Children

College of Arts and Sciences

A-LEVEL Religious Studies

But we may go further: not only Jones, but no actual man, enters into my statement. This becomes obvious when the statement is false, since then

Correlation. Mirrors and Windows, Connecting with Literature, Level II

A Primer on Logic Part 1: Preliminaries and Vocabulary. Jason Zarri. 1. An Easy $10.00? a 3 c 2. (i) (ii) (iii) (iv)

Presuppositions (Ch. 6, pp )

On the epistemological status of mathematical objects in Plato s philosophical system

centuries. The first is Henry A. Sanders s 1912 study on W032 and the last Tommy Wasserman s work on early Greek manuscripts in Matthew, published in

Lecture 71. Paul's Mission. 1 Cor 2:1-5

The Book of Mormon: The Earliest Text

Raphael The School of Athens. Hello Plato

THE RELATION BETWEEN THE GENERAL MAXIM OF CAUSALITY AND THE PRINCIPLE OF UNIFORMITY IN HUME S THEORY OF KNOWLEDGE

Introduction to New Testament Interpretation NTS0510.RETI Spring 2015 Dr. Chuck Quarles

The Problem of Major Premise in Buddhist Logic

OLD TESTAMENT QUOTATIONS IN THE NEW TESTAMENT: A TEXTUAL STUDY

Resemblance Nominalism and counterparts

The Chicago Statements

REASONS AND ENTAILMENT

Meno. 70a. 70b. 70c. 71a. Cambridge University Press Meno and Phaedo Edited by David Sedley and Alex Long Excerpt More information

BOOK REVIEW. Thomas R. Schreiner, Interpreting the Pauline Epistles (Grand Rapids: Baker Academic, 2nd edn, 2011). xv pp. Pbk. US$13.78.

How to Use Quotations in Your Research Paper 1

Final Paper. May 13, 2015

Ancient New Testament Manuscripts Understanding Variants Gerry Andersen Valley Bible Church, Lancaster, California

Bertrand Russell Proper Names, Adjectives and Verbs 1

Sermon Notes for April 8, The End? Mark 16:9-20

Plato and the art of philosophical writing

Plato's Epistemology PHIL October Introduction

LISTENING AND VIEWING: CA 5 Comprehending and Evaluating the Content and Artistic Aspects of Oral and Visual Presentations

1 Clarion Logic Notes Chapter 4

CULTIC PROPHECY IN THE PSALMS IN THE LIGHT OF ASSYRIAN PROPHETIC SOURCES 1

Lecture 14 Rationalism

ZHANG Yan-qiu, CHEN Qiang. Changchun University, Changchun, China

Plato & Socrates. Plato ( B.C.E.) was the student of Socrates ( B.C.E.) and the founder of the Academy in Athens.

Continuum for Opinion/Argument Writing Sixth Grade Updated 10/4/12 Grade 5 (2 points)

Integrating Quotations into Your Essay. "By necessity, by proclivity, and by delight, we all quote." -Ralph Waldo Emerson

1. Read, view, listen to, and evaluate written, visual, and oral communications. (CA 2-3, 5)

1. Lukasiewicz s Logic

INTRODUCTION TO THE Holman Christian Standard Bible

The Dead Sea Scrolls. Core Biblical Studies. George J. Brooke University of Manchester Manchester, United Kingdom

TO THE GOSPEL OF LUKE. I. THE CRITICISM OF THE GOSPEL. INTRODUCTION

Duns Scotus on Divine Illumination

Sermon Preparation Worksheet - Poetry (Last Updated: November 22, 2017)

404 Ethics January 2019 I. TOPICS II. METHODOLOGY

Plato s Legacy: Whether the Republic or the Timaeus Reigns Supreme. Thomas Arralde, 2013

Moral Objectivism. RUSSELL CORNETT University of Calgary

DO YOU WANT TO WRITE:

Logic Appendix: More detailed instruction in deductive logic

Understanding the Bible

270 Now that we have settled these issues, we should answer the first question [n.

SB=Student Book TE=Teacher s Edition WP=Workbook Plus RW=Reteaching Workbook 47

Yarchin, William. History of Biblical Interpretation: A Reader. Grand Rapids: Baker

Molnar on Truthmakers for Negative Truths

What conditions does Plato expect a good definition to meet? Is he right to impose them?

Review of Aristotle on Knowledge and Learning: The Posterior Analytics by David Bronstein

Two Kinds of Ends in Themselves in Kant s Moral Theory

IS THE NEW TESTAMENT RELIABLE?

StoryTown Reading/Language Arts Grade 3

Bitter Knowledge: Socrates and Teaching by Disillusionment Appendix A - the Protagoras

What would count as Ibn Sīnā (11th century Persia) having first order logic?

Transcription:

The Origin of Interrogation Marks in the Medieval Manuscripts of Plato s Republic and Its Significance in the Tradition of Plato s Dialogues 1 Akitsugu Taki 1. Introduction In Constantinople, in the Byzantine Empire, in the ninth century CE, a number of Greek ancient literary texts were copied in a newly invented script, minuscule, from the exemplars in uncial script. Meantime, a comma-shaped mark was newly invented and added to the punctuation (see Pl. 1). Pl. 1 Parisinus gr. 1807 fol. 71 r col. 2 ll. 26-27 (Rp. 507d12-e1) However, this mark, often called a question mark, has been disregarded except when describing manuscripts. Plato had no punctuation or other marks. The mark added is not fixed in the text. The rule was not stipulated. It is scarce and not consistently placed. Placing a mark is of little help towards analysing the speaker s meaning. These ideas may have justified disregarding the mark. However, seen against the historical background, it will be understood better. In what follows I will try to shed light on its meaning. 2. What Was the Comma-shaped Mark in Plato s Manuscripts? 2.1 A Short History of the Comma-shaped Mark Exactly how Plato wrote nobody knows. However, if he had had some additional marks, they would have been transmitted through his school, the Academy, since his works were several times edited by scholars. 1 Sigla: O = cod. Vaticanus gr. 1 (saec. X); A = cod. Parisinus gr. 1807 (saec. IX); B = cod. Bodleianus E.D. Clarke 39 (895 CE); T = Venetus Marcianus gr. append. Class. IV 1 (saec. X); P = cod.vaticanus Palatinus gr. 173 (saec. X-XI); W = cod. Vindobonensis suppl. gr. 7 (saec. XI); D = cod. Venetus 185 (saec. XII); Δ = Vaticanus gr. 225 (saec. XIII?); Θ = codex Vaticanus gr. 226 (saec. XIII?); F = cod. Vindobonensis suppl. gr. 39 (saec. XIV); M = Cesena, Bibliotheca Malatestiana D XXVIII, 4 (saec. XIV?).

In some excavated second-and-third-century papyri of Plato s works, a two-dot mark for a change of speakers sometimes can be observed but almost no others can. 2 Also, in fourth-to-fifth-century Bible majuscule manuscripts, there is no punctuation. Furthermore, Proclus discussed whether Socrates is asking a question or making a statement, but he did not mention any punctuation. 3 Therefore Plato probably had no additional marks. In the minuscule manuscripts from the ninth century on, however, a dependent comma-shaped mark appears besides single-dot or two-dot marks at the end of a clause, sentence or speech. For example, after Pilate s question to Jesus Christ in the Gospels, there had been no comma-shaped mark in majuscule manuscripts, but there was in ninth-to-tenth-century minuscule manuscripts. Also the twist was added in Plato s extant ninth-to-tenth-century manuscripts, B, A, O, T and P. 4 Therefore it was probably invented in the ninth century. 5 However, its transmission varied among authors. It is sometimes embedded in the punctuation of single-dot or double-dot marks and sometimes in that of single-dot marks alone. Among Bible minuscule manuscripts the punctuation probably changed from the former to the latter. It did also among Plato s manuscripts, as conjectured from a scribe s practice in M of changing two-dot marks for a change of speaker in the exemplar to single-dot counterparts. 6 However, in Aristotle s tenth-century manuscripts the scribes used single-dot or two-dot marks alone. A comma-shaped mark is not used for Wh-questions or Yes-No questions. 7 2.2 Was the Comma-shaped Mark Inconsistent in Plato s Manuscripts? Question marks in modern editions are placed consistently. For example, in Republic I, there are 71 direct Wh-questions; eight of them are rhetorical, like πῶς γὰρ οὐ, as a reply to a Yes-No question, and 19 of them are introductory formulae such as τί δέ, followed mostly by Yes-No questions. Slings marks all of them and also 167 other Yes-No questions. The latter include every sentece with an interrogative particle such as ἆρα. Slings is consistent in using this punctuation. 8 However, the question marks in Plato s medieval manuscripts are in many respects inconsistent. For example, the sentence ἦ γάρ is not always marked. Such is also the case with other interrogative features, 2 Flock, 1908. 3 Taki, 2009d. 4 Taki, 2008a, 2009a, 2010a. 5 Cf. Flock, 1908. 6 Taki, 2010a. 7 E.g. around Physics, E6, 230b, Codex J (cod. Vind. 100) or in the end of the De Anima, II, Codex E (cod. Paris. gr. 1853). 8 Slings 2003.

even in two adjacent sentences. Slings edition has 238 comma-shaped marks, for example, in Republic I, whereas A 141, T 80, D 24, Θ 116, F 25, W 105 and M 126. This statistical contrast, as confirmed in other works, is enough to place in doubt the consistency in use. Also, their distribution is often not uniform. For example, F has 20 of them in Republic V but none in Book Six; their distribution in the First Alcibiades is much more localized in B than in P, W and M. 9 The placement in a sentence is often inconsistent. When two clauses are coordinated in a single interrogative sentence, only the first clause is marked. From these inconsistencies, how could the marks reasonably be classified under a single category? There was one consistency, though. Wh-questions in Republic I are almost never marked in A except when interrogatives appear in the middle of a clause or speech 10. Just once a sentence with an interrogative pronoun at the head is marked. 11 This practice can be observed in Books Five, Six and Nine in the codices I examined, D, Θ, F and M. It is also the case in Plato s Socratic dialogues and the Platonic First Alcibiades in the codices I examined, B, T, P, W, D, and M. Therefore our mark highly probably implies a non-wh-question. Nor are the reply forms ναί or ἀληθῆ λέγεις ever marked there. Therefore the comma-shaped marks are not so consistently placed as to be categorized under Yes-No question but one may reasonably regard them as interpretative reminders of the speaker s implication of a non-statement and a non-wh-question. 3. The Origin of the Comma-shaped Mark in the Republic in Plato s Manuscripts 3.1 Was the Comma-Shaped Mark Unfixed in the Text? Marks added to the fixed letter-sequence cannot be fixed in the text. In general correctors can add any additional mark at any time later. Especially, comma-shaped marks, additionally placed under the already established single-dot or two-dot marks, are hard to date, unless the composition of their ink is chemically identified. Therefore it may be risky to discuss their transmission along with the transmission of the text. I am not expert in chemical analysis. So I will just make suggestions on some graphical characteristics of the marks under discussion. Under closer observation, some two-dot marks for a change of speaker, when they have a comma-shaped mark under them, are placed a little higher than others without one, the wrinkles or warps of the materials well considered. Therefore the two-dot mark was very likely so placed as to make space for a 9 Taki, 2010a. 10 334c1, 3, 332c7, d3, 333c7, 337b8, 345b7. 11 349e4.

comma-shaped mark. In the text of the Republic, such cases are frequently observed in Θ, eleven times in Book One in T and only once in D. Although Boter observed a difference in ink (see, e.g. Pl. 1), 12 I have found four such cases in A so far. 13 Also, in the Republic in A, the ink of the beginning stroke of a comma-shaped mark sometimes infiltrates upward into the ink of the ending stroke of the last letter of the sentence; 14 and the ink at the end of the last stroke of a sentence sometimes infiltrates downward into the ink at the end of a comma-shaped mark; 15 the ink of the beginning stroke of a comma-shaped mark sometimes connects to the ink at the end of the ending stroke of the last letter at the end of a sentence. 16 Those appearnces at present seem to suggest some coincidence in the date of writing between the text and the comma-shaped mark, unless the infiltration chemically can arise at any later time. This coincidence still cannot justifiably be generalised but it would be rash to disregard the mark under discussion because they are not fixed in the text. 3.2 The Origin of the Comma-shaped Mark in the Republic Some of A s comma-shaped marks in the Republic were possibly placed not long after the text was copied. This is the only direct evidence for the origin of the marks in the Republic. However, they are not the oldest. The graphical displacement also suggests that they were not deliberately newly added but were simply copied from the exemplar. The existence of those marks in A s exemplar is supported by B. Comma-shaped marks can be seen there and are placed almost exactly just under the two-dot mark for a change of speaker as if the whole were a unit. B was produced by John the calligrapher for Arethas in 894 CE. So John did not first add the mark but probably someone else in B s exemplar. Whether John, who copied the text of Tetralogies I-VI for B, knew the second volume containing Tetralogies VIII-IX, now lost with the first volume, is not certain, for he ended with the Meno, not the end of Tetralogy VII. However, T, a tenth-century manuscript in A s family, reads at the end of Tetralogy VII, The end of the first book. Therefore the second volume s existence most likely had been known when A was made. And there was another copy of this volume other than A. Codex O, a tenth-century manuscript, beginning with the Laws, does not contain the Republic now but the numbering of its quaternions suggests 12 Boter, 1989, 81-86. 13 346d8 (fol. 11 r col. 1. l. 7), 456a5 (fol. 51 r col. 2 l. 41), 495a2 (fol. 66 r col. 1 l. 33), 559c1 (fol. 90 r col. 1 l. 2). 14 459a4 (fol. 52 v col. 1 l. 41), 467b11 (fol. 56 r col. 1 l. 32), 476e2 (fol. 60 r col. 1 l. 34), 587b13 (fol. 100 v col. 2 l. 26). 15 552e3 (fol. 87 r col. 2 l. 42), 573d8 (fol. 95 r col. 2 l. 18). 16 590a3 (fol. 101 v col. 2 l. 35).

that it did. O is still thought to be A s direct copy in the part after Laws 746b8 but my recent observation suggests that the variant readings there come from some editorial work of more than a single source. 17 And the preceding part is proved to be independent of A. Therefore the lost text of the Republic preceding the Laws would have been another copy. Also the tenth-to-eleventh-century hand in O mentions the Patriarch s Book and other sources, which suggests that in the ninth century there were a number of copies of the Laws and, since the Republic would have been contained with the Laws in the lost second volume if it had existed, that there was more than one copy of the Republic. And in the citation of the Patriarch s Book in the scholion to Laws III 685b5 (see Pl. 2) there is a third mark on the left-hand side of the two-dot mark for a change of speaker which is similar in position to A and O. 18 Pl. 2 Vaticanus gr. 1 fol. 24 v sinistra According to Boter s observation in situ, most of A s comma-shaped marks were placed later in different ink but there were likely to be comma-shaped marks in more than one copy of the Republic when A was made. 3.3 The Codices Interrelation with regard to the Comma-Shaped Mark Tables: The number of sentences with a comma-shaped mark at their ends common to two codices: Notes on the Tables The figure in the round bracket is the number of sentences with a comma-shaped mark at their ends in a codex. For Republic I, I surveyed six manuscripts (see note 1). W s hand in the Republic is not of the twelfth, but of the fourteenth, century. 17 Taki, 2010a, b. 18 See also fol. 79 r l. 5 dextra (Laws 821b7).

For Republic V, VI and IX, I surveyed five manuscripts. T s hand in the Republic is not of the tenth century but later. Two hands appear alternately in M and a third hand appears in the Republic VII. In the tables above, however, I do not distinguish the hands. I had expected an increase in the mark s appearance in a question-and-answer session on philosophers in Books Five and Six but there is no significant increase there. Hence I aggregated the statistics of Books Five, Six and Nine. Table 1. the Republic I T Θ D F W M A (141) 76 97 18 20 83 101 T (80) 69 10 12 58 61 Θ (116) 16 19 80 84 D (24) 2 13 19 F (25) 15 19 W (105) 67 M (126) Table 2. the Republic V, VI and IX Θ D F M A (246) 103 9 13 166 Θ(141) 4 6 100 D (16) 0 7 F (20) 10 M (213) (1) No two codices agree in the mark under discussion. Any two codices are relatively inter-independent. For Republic I, however, more than 80 percent of the marks under discussion in each codex agree with those in A. Above all, 95 per cent of the marks in T, along with its text, would come from A, if those in A were placed not long after the copying of the text. At least, A, Θ, M and in Book One T and W, will form a family in the mark under discussion. This is also the case with A, Θ and M in the other Books. (2) As in the similar surveys I conducted on Plato s other works, D and F are each relatively different in tradition of the comma-shaped mark from A and the others. Their remarkable scarcity in using the mark

suggests their deviation from the rise of the practice in the ninth century, although in Plato s other works the scarcity in D may be more or less related along with its text to B s family. However, as in other works, neither D s nor F s criteria by which to place the mark deviate from the other traditions. (3) Since comma-shaped marks as in their history above arose from nil and would have been proliferated with other additional marks, one may reasonably assume that the later, the more, which the surveys of other medieval manuscripts show. The marks are truly scarce in B. Why in the Republic is A the mother of our marks? In Laws I-III, where O has readings independent of those in A, A has 81 marked sentence ends, while O 73. They agree at 71 sentence ends, especially at the end of ἦ γάρ unlike in B s family. Who was the author of our mark, Photius or Arethas, is not certain but the study on Plato arising amid the transcription from majuscule to minuscule in A s family in the ninth century would have paved the way for the development of our mark. 3.3 Grammatical Characteristics of the Sentence with a Comma-shaped Mark at its End As I mentioned above, our mark in Plato s works is at most a reading reminder but under closer examination it is instructive for modern interpreters. The marked sentences are characterised not only by interrogative particles such as ἆρα and ἦ but also by colloquially interrogative features: (1) negatives for denying the interlocutor s possible ideas, (2) opinion verbs in the second person singular or the first person plural for referring to the respondent s intention, (3) ellipsis, disjunctive conjunction or particles for referring to the interlocutor s previous response or possible ideas such as καί, δέ, ἀλλά, οὐκοῦν, ἄρα and γάρ; (4) adverbs and parenthetical opinion verbs for weakening assertiveness such as που, δήπου, ὠς ἔοικε, οἶμαι and λέγω; (5) (post-clause mark) confession of ignorance; (6) (post-clause mark) conditional or causal clause. 4. The Contribution of the Comma-shaped Mark to Interpreting Plato s Republic (1) ἄρα and γάρ In a series of question-and-answer exchanges, the questioner s linkage so, referring to the respondent s preceding speech, implies either admission of the proposition embodied in the previous question or else its hypothesizing like if so. For example, if a series of the respondent s answers forms a reductio ad impossibile, the questioner may appear as examiner, but if the series forms a proof, the questioner may appear as advocate. Hence Plato s use of ἄρα is quite different from Euclid s. Plato would have been well aware that the particle ἄρα in question-and-answer exchange, compared with any other clear expression for the

questioner s intention, forms an ambiguous stream of conversation. So Proclus discussed the questioner s commitment in Socrates elenchos in relation to demonstration by asking questions in his commentary on the First Alcibiades; and both Burnet and Slings sometimes place a question mark at the end of a sentence with ἀρα and sometimes not. Likewise, the questioner s use of the particle γἀρ after a Yes-No question sometimes implies admission or hypothesizing in developing a reason for the proposition embodied in the previous question. This would also be Plato s literary device. (2) λέγω and οἶμαι Some opinion verbs in the first person present indicative, the so-called performative verb, such as I say and I suppose are certainly expressions necessary for statement, but whether in parenthetical use or not, their effect of weakening a claim to universal validity or assertion can elicit in context the respondent s commitment, thus working indirectly as a question. Comma-shaped marks at the sentence ends with such literary effect may be visualising Plato literary device, too. 19 (3) οἶσθα and συνοίει Grammatical characteristics of the marked sentence ends under discussion in general suggest the ninth-century scholars underlying interest in illuminating the respondent s, and also dismissing the discussion leader s, commitment. This possible practice is in accordance with Proclus respondent-centred reading practice discussed in his commentaries on the First Alcibiades and Parmenides. 20 However, it might go back further to Plato s idiosyncratic literary devices. In the Apology Socrates describes himself as an examiner by asking questions but as an expositor like the sophists as well (33b); also he admits that his audience thought he knew what he was asking about (23a). If Plato had been literarily developing Socrates self-portrait, he would have embedded in dramatized conversation a variety of literary devices to signal this impression gap. Plato is, compared with other ancient authors in the classical age, idiosyncratic, for example, in using the reply form ἀληθῆ λέγεις and the like. Other ancient writers use this form in reply to a statement, not to a question. 21 Also, Plato in his narrative dialogues exploits the ambiguity between inter-agreement and admission in reply forms in indirect discourse ὡμολόγει, συνέφη and others. 22 And the parenthetical adverbial clause ὠς with opinion verbs such as φημί often has an ambiguous implication as to the speaker s 19 Taki, 2008b, 2009b. 20 Taki, 2009d. 21 Taki, 2008c. 22 Taki, 2006.

commitment in Plato s dialogues. 23 If those literary devices served to signal the Socratic impression gap, Plato s use of οἶσθα in a question and συνοίει in Socrates speeches in the Republic would also point to the similar literary trick, since Socrates in the Republic is deliberately theorising an exact distinction between belief and knowledge. Works Cited G. Boter, The Textual Tradition of Plato s Republic, Leiden, 1989. G. Flock, De Graecorum interpunctionibus, Bonn, 1908. S.R. Slings, Platonis Respublica, Oxford, 2003. A. Taki, What was Inter-agreement for Socrates?: an enquiry of the reply forms in indirect discourse in Plato s narrative dialogues Bulletin of the Department of Classics, University of Tokyo (= BDCUT), 2 (2006) 27-44. 2008a - A Survey on the Interrogation Marks in Plato s Byzantine Manuscript, Parisinus graecus 1807, fol. 1 r col. 1 fol. 14 r col. 1 (Text and Title in Japanese) Bulletin, Faculty of Humanities, Josai International University (= BFH), 16-2 (2008) 73-103. 2008b - A Thorn in the Flesh of Doctrinal Readers of Plato: a note on signum interrogandi at the end of an οἶμαι sentence, Rp. 335d. Philologica, 3 (2008) 79-87. 2008c - A Chasm underneath the Smoothed Consensus: A Note on Plato s Idiosyncratic Use of ἀληθῆ λέγεις BDCUT, 4 (2008) 83-93 2009a - A Survey of the interrogation marks in Plato s Socratic Dialogues (the Gorgias, Meno, Hippias Major, Hippias Minor, Ion, Republic I) in Vindobonensis suppl. gr. 39 (Codex F) in Comparison with Those in His Other Major Manuscripts. Material Culture Studies, Josai International University (=MCSJIU), 6 (2009) 1-21 2009b - The Punctuation and Speech-Division at Meno 78c (Text and Title in Japanese), Philologica, 4 (2009), 47-53 2009c - Unsimple Talk Manners: a note on Plato s Socratic use of the correlative adverb with opinion verbs BDCUT, 5 (2009) 2009d - Proclus Reading of Plato s Sokratikoi logoi: Proclus observations on dialectic at Alcibiades I, 112d-114e and elsewhere (unpublished) 2010a - A Survey of the interrogation marks in the Major Manuscripts of the Platonic Alcibiades I MCSJIU, 7 (2010) 2010b - A Palaeographical Note on the Corrections at the Pseudo-Platonic Demodocus 380b in Its Two Oldest Manuscripts A and O Philologica, 5 (2010) 21-32 2010c - A Note on the Relation of Plato s Manuscripts A and O in the Text of the Definitions (unpublished) 23 Taki, 2009c.

(Josai International University)