Published Citation Sealey, Kris. (2011). Desire as Disruption, Journal for Cultural and Religious Theory, Vol. 11(3), Fall 2011, pp

Similar documents
The Other Half of Hegel s Halfwayness: A response to Dr. Morelli s Meeting Hegel Halfway. Ben Suriano

Death and Discourse: An Inquiry into Meaning and Disruption James R. Goebel California State University, Fullerton

Contemporary Theology I: Hegel to Death of God Theologies

SIMONE DE BEAUVOIR: ARE WOMEN COMPLICIT IN THEIR OWN SUBJUGATION, IF SO HOW?

1. The mystery of Eros. The encounter of love. The mystery of sought alterity.

Introducing Levinas to Undergraduate Philosophers

FIRST STUDY. The Existential Dialectical Basic Assumption of Kierkegaard s Analysis of Despair

In Search of a Political Ethics of Intersubjectivity: Between Hannah Arendt, Emmanuel Levinas and the Judaic

obey the Christian tenet You Shall Love The Neighbour facilitates the individual to overcome

VULNERABILITY AND SALVATION: LEVINAS AND ETHICAL TEACHING

3 Supplement. Robert Bernasconi

Man and the Presence of Evil in Christian and Platonic Doctrine by Philip Sherrard

Spinoza on God, Affects, and the Nature of Sorrow

Process Thought and Bridge Building: A Response to Stephen K. White. Kevin Schilbrack

On happiness in Locke s decision-ma Title being )

The Psychoanalyst and the Philosopher

Chapter 25. Hegel s Absolute Idealism and the Phenomenology of Spirit

Canadian Society for Continental Philosophy

The Greatest Mistake: A Case for the Failure of Hegel s Idealism

The Episcopal Diocese of Kansas

Phil 114, Wednesday, April 11, 2012 Hegel, The Philosophy of Right 1 7, 10 12, 14 16, 22 23, 27 33, 135, 141

Levinas on the 'Origin' of Justice: Kant, Heidegger, and a Communal Structure of Difference

THE STUDY OF UNKNOWN AND UNKNOWABILITY IN KANT S PHILOSOPHY

Statement on Inter-Religious Relations in Britain

Kant and the Problem of Metaphysics 1. By Tom Cumming

A Philosophical Critique of Cognitive Psychology s Definition of the Person

borderlands e-journal

Has Nagel uncovered a form of idealism?

FUNDAMENTAL PRINCIPLES OF THE METAPHYSIC OF MORALS. by Immanuel Kant

Meursault s Ethical Transcendence : A Žižekian Reading of The Stranger. What does it mean to be displaced, separated from the ever-present sense of

At the Frontiers of Reality

The Human Deficit according to Immanuel Kant: The Gap between the Moral Law and Human Inability to Live by It. Pieter Vos 1

Testimony and Moral Understanding Anthony T. Flood, Ph.D. Introduction

Absolute Difference and Social Ontology: Levinas Face to Face with Buber and Fichte

Andrea Westlund, in Selflessness and Responsibility for Self, argues

DEONTOLOGY AND MORAL RESPONSIBILITY

Review of The Monk and the Philosopher

Lecture 4. Simone de Beauvoir ( )

METAPHYSICS IN DERRIDA AND LEVINAS

Two Kinds of Ends in Themselves in Kant s Moral Theory

Can Christianity be Reduced to Morality? Ted Di Maria, Philosophy, Gonzaga University Gonzaga Socratic Club, April 18, 2008

Summary of Kant s Groundwork of the Metaphysics of Morals

Purple Haze: The Puzzle of Consciousness

EXISTENTIALISM. Course Number PHIL Meeting Times MW 2:00-3:15. Instructor John V. Garner, Ph.D.,

Eric Schliesser Philosophy and Moral Sciences, Ghent University ª 2011, Eric Schliesser

Pedagogical Responsibility and the Third: Levinasian Considerations for Social Justice Pedagogies

Why I Am Not a Property Dualist By John R. Searle

Saving the Substratum: Interpreting Kant s First Analogy

John Scottus Eriugena: Analysing the Philosophical Contribution of an Forgotten Thinker

proper construal of Davidson s principle of rationality will show the objection to be misguided. Andrew Wong Washington University, St.

RUNNING HEAD: Philosophy and Theology 1. Christine Orsini RELS 111 Professor Fletcher March 21, 2012 Short Writing Assignment 2

A Review of Lack and Transcendence: The Problem of Death and Life in Psychotherapy, Existentialism, and Buddhism

Understanding the burning question of the 1940s and beyond

Fabrizio Luciano, Università degli Studi di Padova

Levinas and the Visibility of God: A "Seeing" That Does Not Know What it Sees

Concepts of God: Yielding to Love pages 24-27

Take Home Exam #2. PHI 1700: Global Ethics Prof. Lauren R. Alpert

Investigating the concept of despair and its relation with sin in Kierkegaard's view

The Middle Path: A Case for the Philosophical Theologian. Leo Strauss roots the vitality of Western civilization in the ongoing conflict between

Follow links for Class Use and other Permissions. For more information send to:

The Social Nature in John Stuart Mill s Utilitarianism. Helena Snopek. Vancouver Island University. Faculty Sponsor: Dr.

Response to The Problem of the Question About Animal Ethics by Michal Piekarski

Phenomenology Religion in the I and Thou of Martine Buber

Heidegger s Unzuhandenheit as a Fourth Mode of Being

Happiness and Personal Growth: Dial.

The Relationship between Rhetoric and Truth. Plato tells us that oratory is the art of enchanting the soul (Phaedrus).

Whole Person Caring: A New Paradigm for Healing and Wellness

The Singularity of the Self

What Is Existentialism? COPYRIGHTED MATERIAL. Chapter 1. In This Chapter

J. Aaron Simmons and Bruce Ellis Benson, The New Phenomenology: A Philosophical Introduction (New York: Bloomsbury, 2013)

Rationalism. A. He, like others at the time, was obsessed with questions of truth and doubt

To Provoke or to Encourage? - Combining Both within the Same Methodology

The Supplement of Copula

Immanence, Difference, and the Overcoming of Metaphysics

Follow this and additional works at: Part of the Philosophy Commons

The Soul Journey Education for Higher Consciousness

Towards Guidelines on International Standards of Quality in Theological Education A WCC/ETE-Project

THE FICHTEAN IDEA OF THE SCIENCE OF KNOWLEDGE. by Jean Hyppolite*

How to Live a More Authentic Life in Both Markets and Morals

Beauvoir s Politics of Ambiguity Dr. Christine Daigle, Philosophy Department, Brock University

Levinas, Meaning, and Philosophy of Social Science: From Ethical Metaphysics to Ontology and Epistemology

François Laruelle and the Non-Philosophical Tradition

The Grounding for Moral Obligation

Reality. Abstract. Keywords: reality, meaning, realism, transcendence, context

Friedrich Nietzsche and European Nihilism Paul van Tongeren

1 Hans Jonas, The Imperative of Responsibility: In Search of an Ethics for the Technological Age (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1984), 1-10.

To my most precious YOU DESERVE TO KNOW WHO YOU REALLY ARE. The Planet Earth Guide, August 2016.

Response to Gregory Floyd s Where Does Hermeneutics Lead? Brad Elliott Stone, Loyola Marymount University ACPA 2017

Violence as a philosophical theme

Thought is Being or Thought and Being? Feuerbach and his Criticism of Hegel's Absolute Idealism by Martin Jenkins

From Levinas radio interview, The Face

A HOLISTIC VIEW ON KNOWLEDGE AND VALUES

The Early Church worked tirelessly to establish a clear firm structure supported by

1/13. Locke on Power

GOD'S SILENCE IN THE DIALOGUE ACCORDING TO MARTIN BUBER

"Can We Have a Word in Private?": Wittgenstein on the Impossibility of Private Languages

CRITIQUE OF PETER SINGER S NOTION OF MARGINAL UTILITY

Review of The use of bodies by Giorgio Agamben, translated by Adam Kotsko

STATEMENT OF EXPECTATION FOR GRAND CANYON UNIVERSITY FACULTY

Structure and essence: The keys to integrating spirituality and science

Transcription:

Fairfield University DigitalCommons@Fairfield Philosophy Faculty Publications Philosophy Department 10-1-2011 Desire as Disruption Kris Sealey Fairfield University, ksealey@fairfield.edu Copyright 2011 Sealey, Kris and Journal for Cultural and Religious Theory Peer Reviewed Repository Citation Sealey, Kris, "Desire as Disruption" (2011). Philosophy Faculty Publications. 12. http://digitalcommons.fairfield.edu/philosophy-facultypubs/12 Published Citation Sealey, Kris. (2011). Desire as Disruption, Journal for Cultural and Religious Theory, Vol. 11(3), Fall 2011, pp. 30-36. This Article is brought to you for free and open access by the Philosophy Department at DigitalCommons@Fairfield. It has been accepted for inclusion in Philosophy Faculty Publications by an authorized administrator of DigitalCommons@Fairfield. For more information, please contact digitalcommons@fairfield.edu.

KRIS SEALEY Fairfield University DESIRE AS DISRUPTION D rew Dalton s analysis in Longing for the Other does the much needed work of situating Levinas alongside other figures in the canon of Western philosophy. 1 In so doing, he raises the kinds of questions through which we get a clear picture of the uniqueness of Levinas philosophical position. By juxtaposing his account of metaphysical desire alongside thinkers like Plato, Heidegger and Fichte (to name a few), Dalton establishes the sense in which Levinas is both of the tradition and in dialogue with the tradition, but from precisely the outside. Given the way Levinas conceptualizes the difference between desire and need, one wonders if desire (on Levinas terms) can ever be anything other than metaphysical. Said otherwise, his position seems to be that desire categorically stands on (or, at the very least, prepares the way for) a radical breaking up of interiority onto that which is beyond. Dalton illustrates this quite successfully in his analysis. He traces the opposition between desire and what might be more accurately described as a relation across need, establishing that the latter presupposes a kind of inner life that, though not complete, projects toward a fulfillment of itself, or seeks a larger and more enriched version of itself. There is no object of my desire upon which my identity could feed in this kind of way. As he brings Levinas into dialogue with Plato s account of eros, Dalton illustrates the sense in which desire desires that which is not only outside the subject, but more importantly, beyond the subject as well. This beyond takes on an overtly ethical import, but for the moment, the nuance of this distinction (between what might be outside without necessarily being beyond) captures what, I believe, is particular to the Levinasian framework. It helps us to understand why, for instance, 1 Drew M. Dalton, Longing for the Other: Levinas and Metaphysical Desire (Pittsburgh: Duquesne University Press, 2009). JCRT 11.3 Fall 2011 30

SEALEY: Desire as Disruption 31 a Sartrean formulation of consciousness, as an intentional projection of self, does not come to Levinas as a genuine transcendence, insofar as it does not open up onto the metaphysical. 2 The Sartrean subject, as a negation of being, is always empty of self. The subject is for itself, and as such, never coincident with her self. Instead, out of an ontological necessity, consciousness moves toward a self that is always on the outside. If, by transcendence, Sartre means a journey toward that which is outside, then the dynamic between consciousness and its self would suffice. But if, along with Levinas, we recognize transcendence as a move toward the metaphysical, then my projection toward a self with which I can never coincide would be a failed transcendence. The Sartrean self might be on the outside, but it is not, by any means, beyond. Dalton s analysis plays with these levels in order to illustrate Levinas unique way of accounting for metaphysical desire. Exteriority, he says, can either be other and on the same level, or it can be other and above. Metaphysical desire would indicate the kind of exteriority, and thus derive its signification from, that which is both outside and above. Hence, in the end, Sartre s non-coincidence might be read as a lost immanence, which Dalton rightly aligns with the order of need and not desire. To be sure, this lost immanence references a sort of interruption (at worst, or maybe a minor inconvenience, at best). But it is not yet what Levinas captures in his tropes of metaphysical desire, or what Dalton wants to establish as the core of human longing. In his re-reading of Plato s eros, Dalton determines that, though the catalyst of the erotic movement is regarded as good, it is precisely not good for the subject who moves toward the object of her love. Again, we have another distinction, between that which is good (proper) and that which might be good for me, that highlights the structures that are unique to Levinas conception of desire, identity, and ultimately, alterity. In eros, I am transported into a version of myself that is truer, and in a sense, more complete. Nevertheless, Dalton wants to differentiate the object of this Platonic love from the destination of a need-inspired journey. He quotes another Drew (Hyland), who describes eros as a movement toward a wholeness which it has never before been. 3 So even though love takes me into a new perfection, it is very much the case that I encounter, in that new perfection, a radical unfamiliarity. So, in the sense that love brings us into relation with something with which we have never been acquainted, there is compelling evidence for resonance between Plato s rendition of eros and a Levinasian account of metaphysical desire. This is insofar as Levinas determines the metaphysical in desire to rest on a homelessness, and Dalton determines that eros is impossible as a homecoming. [It] would seem that according to Plato no soul can erotically transcend by way of the homely no soul can erotically transcend without becoming alienated from the homely, without diverging from the paths familiar to it. 4 Hence, the transport must be toward an elsewhere, or toward a self that is higher and completely otherwise than we know ourselves to be. 2 For Sartre s complete analysis on this issue, see Jean-Paul Sartre, The Transcendence of the Ego: An Existentialist Theory of Consciousness (New York: Hill and Wang, 1991). 3 Dalton, 36 4 Dalton, 35

SEALEY: Desire as Disruption 32 However, insofar as Levinas reads Plato s conception of eros as something that eventually ends, like consumption, in the satisfaction of the subject, he disqualifies love as a movement of transascendence. So it is clear that at least part of what is essential to his account of metaphysical desire is that the subject remains dis-satisfied, or un-satiated. Dalton argues that in eros, we actually find that (1) the subject s desire actually deepens, and doesn t become shallower, the more she pursues the end of eros, and that (2) as a result, the end of eros doesn t promise the possibility of satisfaction. In that regard, the new perfection that eros promises, or the more complete version of myself that I encounter upon being transported, should not reinforce or support my integrity as a subject. In other words, I should not expect, from love, that better, or less-than-finite being against which Levinas warns in his own account of genuine transcendence. Metaphysical desire, in its opposition to need, leaves the subject exposed to that which is both outside and beyond. What becomes apparent in Levinas collapsing of the metaphysical and the ethical is that this exposure is, in every sense, a wounding in the name of what is outside and beyond. So any resonance between eros and metaphysical desire also means that wholeness, completion and perfection are never good for me, even if, as Dalton points out, it is good. He reminds us that [not] everything which is outside the subject carries the weight of the metaphysical, which is to say that not everything outside is necessarily beyond. 5 Perhaps we should also note that metaphysical desire indicates a beyond that must remain on the outside. The end of metaphysical desire is entirely otherwise and elsewhere. So when Drew Hyland describes eros as a movement toward a wholeness which [the subject] has never been, we must bear in mind that this subject never is the wholeness which eros promises. The consequence of this more perfect version of herself is that she is entirely otherwise (than being), or denied the kind of integral identity that might reincorporate the beyond into the inside. To this end, Levinas identifies the ethical as metaphysical desire s necessary deflection. It is the social, or an encounter with the Other that secures the necessary break-up of the desiring subject of the metaphysical desire. In other words, though we speak in terms of the object of eros (to return to Dalton s Plato/Levinas analysis), the break-up of the subject, through this (affective) transcendence means that metaphysical desire is no longer in terms of an object in the true sense of the term. So in detouring toward the Other as an obsessive responsibility for the Other, metaphysical desire operates outside the field of intentionality, where subject and object poles, at least remotely, apply. As the desiring self is propelled toward the Other, the world no longer appears through mechanisms of objectification and thematization. Instead of there being a manifestation for me, the Other is a kind of super bright phenomenon which outshines all the intelligible powers of the subject. 6 I find this way of phrasing the Other s absence to be quite informative, since it captures the sense in which the trace of alterity is felt, despite its never being a manifestation. To a degree, the Other presents himself as the absence of light for me. But his entrance into my site (or sight) precisely overwhelms the parameters of that site. In other words, even though my eyes are blind to alterity s mode of signification, I am affected by 5 Dalton, 20 6 Dalton, 39

SEALEY: Desire as Disruption 33 that which my eyes are unable to see. Dalton makes this clear when he explains that it is not that the Other stands entirely outside of my field. If he did then the subject could not even feel the pull that the Good exercises as the Other. 7 Instead of saying that the Other is an absence of meaning, it is perhaps more accurate to say that the Other is the presence of meaninglessness. She is the light in which things appear, if by light we understand the groundlessness (or trans-phenomenological, to borrow from Sartre) upon which we engineer our networks of signification. 8 This brings to mind a novel by José Saramago, which describes a certain plague sweeping across an entire community that results in a sudden and unexplainable loss of sight. 9 But unlike most cases of blindness, in which the individual is engulfed in a sea of darkness, this community succumbs to an uninterrupted wave of white light when they become blind. Perhaps we could employ this as Levinasians, and read Saramago s account as a metaphor of the plague of ethical obsession. To be sure, this sudden and unexplainable blindness results in a kind of debilitation that compromises the very possibility of existence, very similar to how Levinas describes the subject s inversion (or impossibility of identity) as she is propelled by the Good, and toward the Other, in metaphysical desire. To a large extent, Saramago s blindness gives way to a restructured social relation, insofar as individuals must approach each other, and interact with each other, without seeing. To be sure, apprehending one s world across intentionality does not, in the least, rely on the sense of sight. But perhaps the narrative in Saramago s novel serves as a metaphor for an intentional projection significantly compromised upon encountering the Face. Caught up in too much light, I am compelled to see the Other without seeing, or in way that is radically otherwise (than intentionality). In a similar sense, Dalton s descriptions capture the ethical moment, whereby the subject is overcome by the Other-as-light, and has to cope with the Face, who expresses without manifesting. In that regard, metaphysical desire maintains the Other as he who is made present without being given. So when this movement becomes the lived moment of shame, it is at least partly because the Other halts my power to thematize, manifest and make meaningful. However, we must be careful not to read this ethical diversion of metaphysical desire solely in terms of a cognitive failure on the part of subjectivity. Upon encountering the Face, I am called to be for the Other (in substitution) in a way that transcends my choices and decisions. But this election is not quite against my will, but rather, prior to the instantiation of my will. So it is important to recognize that Levinas analysis of shame does not restrict itself to a transcend or be transcended overture, whereby one subject becomes an object for another subject. To be sure, Dalton captures the significance of shame for Levinas analysis of metaphysical desire, when he writes, Indeed, it is this very power of the experience of shame to cast consciousness back upon itself as an object for another this power to objectify the subject which makes it of such 7 Dalton, 38 8 Dalton, 39 9 José Saramago, Blindness (Harvest Books, 1999).

SEALEY: Desire as Disruption 34 vital importance for [Levinas]. 10 But at the same time, Levinas claim is not that the anguish of shame lies in my imprisonment in an (objectified) being for the Other that I can never be for myself. Said otherwise, my shame does not result from my inability to apprehend myself the way I am apprehended by the Face. So even though I might describe myself as objectified in a moment of shame, it is on a uniquely qualified sense of the term. According to Levinas, I am cast back upon myself, in this position of vulnerability, in a way that is already beyond subject and object dichotomies. The identity from which I cannot escape (the one with which shame acquaints me most intimately) is neither (or no longer) a spontaneous subjectivity, nor reified objectivity. My passivity, Levinas says, is more passive than the passivity of a stone, and in that regard, I don t think shame s sting is quite a consequence of the Other s power to objectify me. Indeed, shame is, upon Levinas analysis, shame of myself. But [shame s] whole intensity, everything it contains that stings us, consists precisely in our inability not to identify with this being who is already foreign to us 11 It is that nascent reminder that we are strangers to ourselves, in a way that will always deny us the kind of autonomy and sovereignty needed for that subject/object distinction to bear relevance to our human condition. If it was the case that, in shame, I find myself reduced to an object, wouldn t it also be the case that the Other is the subject for whom I am reduced? And if so, wouldn t this be tantamount to situating my being, and the being of the Other along the same plane, instead of what Levinas intends, which is that the Other comes to me (or, sure enough, accuses me ) from a Height? Dalton s descriptions of shame as not only a kind of passive experience of the subject [but] also an illumination of the way in which the subject is fundamentally passive seems to clarify this ambiguity. 12 In this regard, my being an object for the Other indicates an affectivity of having been open and exposed, [and] reveals the way in which the subject is not hermetically closed in on itself. 13 Hence, the sting of shame does not lie in my taking on a reified object-identity. Rather, shame allows for that most unmistakable realization that I am without identity, abandoned to the ontological but already opened up onto the metaphysical. Drew describes this turn as one toward a (truer) freedom, whereby I choose to be responsible for the Other instead of choosing the pleasure of enjoyment and self-preservation. This ethical dimension indicates, somewhat retroactively, that my ontological freedom is really a prison. This explains why, in shame, I am appalled by the density, or fullness of my being. The bond to my being appears in the form of shackles, which hold me back from that truer freedom the freedom to visit the possibility of sacrifice. To be sure, this would save Levinas conception of shame from being read as an experience of alienation, whereby my being is stolen from me by the Other. If the subject is invited to choose responsibility for the Other, then my 10 Dalton, 119 11 Levinas, On Escape, trans. Bettina Bergo (Stanford: Stanford University Press, 2003), 63. 12 Dalton, 126-127 13 Dalton, 127

SEALEY: Desire as Disruption 35 substitution is what I choose, and the subsequent loss of self is not a theft. 14 Nevertheless, it seems hasty to describe the passivity of being substituted (or the passivity of being called to responsibility) in terms of choice, and possibility. Levinas own analysis distinguishes substitution from a form of alienation or enslavement to the Other, and I read this as the point of Dalton s clarification when he reminds us that [through] the Other one is freed from the demands of need one is free to devote oneself to the Other. 15 But to describe this in terms of an ethical potentiality might run the risk of undermining the radical affectivity/passion upon which Levinas grounds this drama of substitution. 16 In other words, to read, in substitution, the end of a movement that arrives at a higher and entirely novel, but nevertheless more complete, expression of [the subject s] potential might be to retain what Levinas reads as a Heideggarian formulation of death as yet another possibility (of, now, impossibility). 17 Hence, the question for us might be, Can ethical potential be something other than a potential that is already mine? In the typical sense of potential, perhaps not. But this typical understanding is precisely what Levinas attempts to transcend in his formulation of the Infinite within the finite. Like the Infinite, (our) ethical potential is something that is within us which could not have been produced by us [and as such, is no longer a modulation of spontaneity]. 18 In this regard, Dalton pertinently employs a term like possession, which establishes the trace of the Other as something by which we are not enslaved, but undeniably as something that slips into us, unbeknownst to us. In that regard, we should understand ethical potential as a birth of a new self that is never up to me, but not alienating either. Dalton makes this clear in his pronouncement that [the] accusation of the Other does not overpower the ego and wrestle it into submission. 19 Nevertheless, shame makes clear that the subject is, in every sense, traumatized by the appearance of the Other. So even though responsibility, as Dalton puts it, frees me from the tyranny of being, 20 it remains important to remember that my newfound freedom to be at the service of the Other is, indeed, a difficult freedom. It is to be under an obsession, or to undergo a dying without quite being able to die. Relative to the prison of identity, in which I am enslaved to self-interest, my substitution for the Other is not a violating force, and is, to a degree, quite liberating. But it is still the case that shame rests on a breach of subjectivity. This is the breach through which metaphysical desire travels, very similar to the way love, on Dalton s analysis, lays the subject open to that which is elsewhere. Levinas account of metaphysical desire very much requires his phenomenology of shame, to demonstrate that the subject is already without identity, or broken open by its primordial grounding in the otherwise. 14 Dalton, 133 15 Dalton, 41 16 Dalton, 42 17 Dalton, 43 18 Dalton, 45 19 Dalton, 133 20 Dalton, 134

SEALEY: Desire as Disruption 36 Hence, in understanding human longing as a travelling toward some final self, through which we become truly human, it is of imperative importance to retain the severity of this breach in subjectivity (a breach that is not, to be sure, a violation). To be truly human, or to take up my obligation to be at the service of the Other, is to let go of a subjectivity to which the categories of completion and actuality can never apply. It is to live my responsibility (for the Other) as an incomplete response, or one that is never enough, or one that fails to close in on itself (even in some bittersweet guilt for not being able to respond sufficiently to the Other s demands). But this seems to be the wound upon which Levinas radical sense of the metaphysical rests, as well as the obsessive content of his account of desire. In bringing him into conversation with the Western canon, Dalton successfully establishes that, though Levinas comes close to others in their accounts of longing, it is a closeness that is in proximity only. KRIS SEALEY (Ph.D., University of Memphis) is an Assistant Professor of Philosophy at Fairfield University. Specializing in the philosophy of Emmanuel Levinas and Jean-Paul Sartre, she has published essays in Levinas Studies, Research in Phenomenology, and The Journal of the British Society for Phenomenology. Kris Sealey. Sealey, Kris. Desire as Disruption, in Journal for Cultural and Religious Theory vol. 11 no. 3 (Winter 2011): 30-36.