ON GOD, SUFFERING, AND THEODICAL INDIVIDUALISM

Similar documents
On the Separateness of Individuals, Compensation, and Aggregation Within Lives

Agnosticism, the Moral Skepticism Objection, and Commonsense Morality

Is#God s#benevolence#impartial?#!! Robert#K.#Garcia# Texas&A&M&University&!!

SATISFICING CONSEQUENTIALISM AND SCALAR CONSEQUENTIALISM

What God Could Have Made

Ordinary morality does not imply atheism

THEODICAL INDIVIDUALISM

KANTIAN ETHICS (Dan Gaskill)

UTILITARIANISM AND CONSEQUENTIALISM: THE BASICS

Phil 108, August 10, 2010 Punishment

Zimmerman, Michael J. Prima Facie Obligation and Doing the Best One Can, Philosophical Studies, 78 (1995):

BELIEF POLICIES, by Paul Helm. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, Pp. xiii and 226. $54.95 (Cloth).

The Harm of Coming into Existence

In Defense of The Wide-Scope Instrumental Principle. Simon Rippon

DEFEASIBLE A PRIORI JUSTIFICATION: A REPLY TO THUROW

If Natural Entities Have Intrinsic Value, Should We Then Abstain from Helping Animals Who Are Victims of Natural Processes? 1

IS GOD "SIGNIFICANTLY FREE?''

Moral Philosophy : Utilitarianism

W.D. Ross ( )

Responsibility and Normative Moral Theories

REASONS AND ENTAILMENT

Choosing Rationally and Choosing Correctly *

Philosophy 1100: Ethics

Direct Realism and the Brain-in-a-Vat Argument by Michael Huemer (2000)

Practical Rationality and Ethics. Basic Terms and Positions

A Contractualist Reply

Suppose... Kant. The Good Will. Kant Three Propositions

TWO NO, THREE DOGMAS OF PHILOSOPHICAL THEOLOGY

Q2) The test of an ethical argument lies in the fact that others need to be able to follow it and come to the same result.

Chapter 3 PHILOSOPHICAL ETHICS AND BUSINESS CHAPTER OBJECTIVES. After exploring this chapter, you will be able to:

The Pleasure Imperative

In-Class Kant Review Dialogue 1

THE ROAD TO HELL by Alastair Norcross 1. Introduction: The Doctrine of the Double Effect.

Kant, Deontology, & Respect for Persons

Evaluating actions The principle of utility Strengths Criticisms Act vs. rule

DOES ETHICS NEED GOD?

Short Answers: Answer the following questions in one paragraph (each is worth 4 points).

Living High and Letting Die

Utilitarianism: For and Against (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1973), pp Reprinted in Moral Luck (CUP, 1981).

THE CONCEPT OF OWNERSHIP by Lars Bergström

Scanlon on Double Effect

Review of What We Owe To Each Other

God and Gratuitous Evil

Reasoning with Moral Conflicts

The fact that some action, A, is part of a valuable and eligible pattern of action, P, is a reason to perform A. 1

Act Consequentialism s Compelling Idea and Deontology s Paradoxical Idea

B. C. Johnson. General Problem

Those of us who oppose torture, and who are acutely conscious of the grave

IN DEFENCE OF CLOSURE

Philosophy 1100: Introduction to Ethics. Critical Thinking Lecture 2. Background Material for the Exercise on Inference Indicators

CLIMBING THE MOUNTAIN SUMMARY CHAPTER 1 REASONS. 1 Practical Reasons

Action in Special Contexts

James Rachels. Ethical Egoism

Lesson 26 Romans DIFFERING OPINIONS (ROMANS 14:1-12) Imagine. The Servant of Another (Romans 14:1-4) Background. Study Notes

Introduction to Philosophy Philosophy 110W Fall 2014 Russell Marcus

Normative Objections to Theism

SUPPOSITIONAL REASONING AND PERCEPTUAL JUSTIFICATION

Let s Bite the Bullet on Deontological Epistemic Justification: A Response to Robert Lockie 1 Rik Peels, Vrije Universiteit Amsterdam.

A number of epistemologists have defended

Does God exist? The argument from evil

Practical reason: rationality or normativity but not both. John Broome

A FORMAL MODEL OF LEGAL PROOF STANDARDS AND BURDENS

PHIL 202: IV:

Atheism and the Basis of Morality

in Social Science Encyclopedia (Routledge, forthcoming, 2006). Consequentialism (Blackwell Publishers, forthcoming, 2006)

Philosophy of Religion 21: (1987).,, 9 Nijhoff Publishers, Dordrecht - Printed in the Nethenanas

John Hawthorne s Knowledge and Lotteries

Mind Association. Oxford University Press and Mind Association are collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to Mind.

PHL340 Handout 8: Evaluating Dogmatism

Positivism, Natural Law, and Disestablishment: Some Questions Raised by MacCormick's Moralistic Amoralism

HAVE WE REASON TO DO AS RATIONALITY REQUIRES? A COMMENT ON RAZ

Proofs of Non-existence

From the Categorical Imperative to the Moral Law

Luminosity, Reliability, and the Sorites

DOES CONSEQUENTIALISM DEMAND TOO MUCH?

Lecture 12 Deontology. Onora O Neill A Simplified Account of Kant s Ethics

CONSEQUENTIALISM AND THE SELF OTHER ASYMMETRY

Gale on a Pragmatic Argument for Religious Belief

Practical Equilibrium: A Way of Deciding What to Think about Morality

Suicide. 1. Rationality vs. Morality: Kagan begins by distinguishing between two questions:

How to approach complaint mechanisms which relate to social, economic and cultural rights either as church or individual?

A Social Practice View of Natural Rights. Word Count: 2998

RESPONSE TO ADAM KOLBER S PUNISHMENT AND MORAL RISK

Asymmetry and Self-Sacrifice

AGAINST MULTIVERSE THEODICIES

From Necessary Truth to Necessary Existence

Hume s Law Violated? Rik Peels. The Journal of Value Inquiry ISSN J Value Inquiry DOI /s

Bernard Hoose - Proportionalism

Consequentialism. The defining feature of consequentialism is that it ranks outcomes (the outcomes

Philosophical Ethics. Consequentialism Deontology (Virtue Ethics)

This leads to conflicting ideas: How can there be a right to property before there is Law?

The belief in the existence of an omniscient, omnipotent and benevolent God is inconsistent with the existence of human suffering. Discuss.

A Coherent and Comprehensible Interpretation of Saul Smilansky s Dualism

Puzzles for Divine Omnipotence & Divine Freedom

Agnosticism, Skeptical Theism, and Moral Obligation

Imprint. Excusing Mistakes of Law. Gideon Yaffe. Philosophers. University of Southern California

The Comparative Badness for Animals of Suffering and Death Jeff McMahan November 2014

All things considered duties to believe

DEONTOLOGY AND ECONOMICS. John Broome

David Ethics Bites is a series of interviews on applied ethics, produced in association with The Open University.

Transcription:

187 ON GOD, SUFFERING, AND THEODICAL INDIVIDUALISM JEROME GELLMAN Ben Gurion University of the Negev Recently, Stephen Maitzen has provided an argument for the nonexistence of God based on ordinary morality. Here is Maitzen s argument, abbreviated down to the relevant parts for my reply and slightly reformulated for ease of presentation: (1) Necessarily, God permits undeserved, involuntary, human suffering only if such suffering ultimately produces a net benefit for the sufferer. (Maitzen calls this TI ) (2) If God exists, then necessarily, all undeserved, involuntary human suffering ultimately produces a net benefit for the sufferer. (From 1) (3) If, necessarily, all undeserved, involuntary human suffering ultimately produces a net benefit for the sufferer, then we never have a moral obligation to prevent undeserved, involuntary human suffering. (4) We sometimes have a moral obligation to prevent undeserved, involuntary human suffering. (5) So, it isn t the case that, necessarily, all undeserved, involuntary human suffering ultimately produces a net benefit for the sufferer. (From 3 and 4) (6) So: God does not exist. (From 2 and 5) I will assume the truth of (1), and thus of (2) which follows from (1). My problem is with (3). Maitzen must do much more to show that (3) is true, or even very plausible. My argument is that (a) the set of propositions I am about to list is not implausible, granting God s existence and perfect goodness and a proper understanding of ordinary morality, and EUROPEAN JOURNAL FOR PHILOSOPHY OF RELIGION 1 (2010), PP. 187 191

188 JEROME GELLMAN (b) since that is so, the consequent of (3) does not plausibly follow from (3) s antecedent. Let P be any person that I allow to endure suffering, instead of preventing the suffering. And let S be the particular instance of suffering that P undergoes. And consider the following set of five propositions, the first four of which are about God and the fifth a moral principle: (G1) God has so created the world that God is able to produce for P a degree, D, of good for P that will make P s existence worthwhile. (G2) God will bring about D for P. This will not be in the form of compensation but a result produced by P s history. (G3) D is a maximal degree of good that God can produce for P. (G4) God will bring about D for P whether P suffers (this particular) S or not. If P suffers S, then God will produce a net good from S for P, to offset the evil of S in order to reach D. (G5) One can morally allow P to suffer S, if and only if the net benefit to P from allowing S will far outweigh S, and either: (a) the net benefit to P from allowing S will be far greater than the good that will be P s if one prevents S, or (b) the net benefit to P from one s allowing S will not be less than the good that will be P s if one prevents S, and allowing S will significantly increase the net good in the world. I now explain each of the members of (G1)-(G5): (G1) and (G2) are consequences of theodical individualism, according to which God must see to it that each person s life be worthwhile, and not just that the existence of the world at large be worthwhile. I include in P s existence P s life after death. I envision the degree of good that is P s in the afterlife as produced by earlier events and not as compensation. I also do not disallow a view like John Hick s wherein we continue to grow and change in the afterlife with new degrees of goodness accruing to our existence. (G3) follows from God s supreme goodness. There will be constraints upon what the maximal degree of goodness is that God can produce for P. For example, God will want the best distribution of good overall in the world and will want a world that is good overall. So, given such con-

ON GOD, SUFFERING, AND THEODICAL INDIVIDUALISM 189 straints, God will produce the best possible degree of good for P. P will have no claims against God that God did not produce a higher degree of good for her, because her existence is the best it could be without fulfilling her selfish desires to get more for herself on other peoples accounts. (G4) reflects the fact that God is so damned smart that God has been able to create the world so that whether P suffers S or not, P will receive D. And it reflects God s goodness, in that God would not allow S to occur if it were to detract from the ultimate net result, D, for P. (G5) makes a claim about our ordinary morality. It says that while consequentialist reckoning is relevant to the allowing of undeserved, involuntary, human suffering, the morality of allowing such suffering is not purely consequentialist. That is because we have a moral deontological obligation to prevent undeserved, involuntary, human suffering (when able, when appropriately situated, etc.). And while that obligation is defeasible, it is not overridden by a mere net benefit for the sufferer. What is needed to defeat the deontological obligation not to allow suffering is that either: (a) the net benefit far outweighs the suffering and far outweighs what good would accrue to the sufferer without that suffering; or (b) the net benefit that far outweighs the suffering is at least the same as what good would accrue to the sufferer without that suffering, and produces a significant net increase of good in the world. These are necessary and sufficient conditions for one being allowed not to prevent undeserved, involuntary, human suffering. On alternative (a), the benefit justifying one s not preventing the suffering is all P s. On alternative (b), however, the benefit that justifies not preventing the suffering is not P s but others. This can happen in at least two ways. The first is that one might be able to bring a very high benefit to another person by allowing P to suffer. And the second is that in adjudicating one s moral obligations to others as well as to P it turns out that one s obligations to others are stronger than, and so defeat, one s obligation to prevent P from enduring S. You might protest that (b) violates Maitzen s Kantian stricture, let s call it K. (K) Nobody (including God) can treat human beings merely as a means.

190 JEROME GELLMAN The violation appears to occur because (G5) permits us (and God) to allow P to suffer in order to benefit others. However, (G5) does not violate (K), on Maitzen s interpretation of it, which I accept. For Maitzen, (K) prohibits sacrificing an innocent person who did not ask for it (p. 116, my emphasis), and (K) prohibits, exploiting a person by visiting upon them undeserved, involuntary, human suffering (p. 117). However, (G5) licenses none of these. Remember, whenever (G5) allows the non-prevention of undeserved, involuntary, human suffering the sufferer is either better off or at least as well off as she would have been without having endured that suffering. The only thing that has happened is that the deontological moral obligation that others have not to allow P to endure undeserved, involuntary, suffering has been overridden by either a justified benefit to P or to others. This does not constitute a sacrifice or exploitation of P in any way, and should not be forbidden by (K). To put it tersely, (G5) does not excuse any instance in which a person treats P merely as a means. It is not implausible to assume that the set (G1)-(G5) is true, granting God s existence and perfect goodness and our understanding of ordinary morality. But, then the antecedent of (3): (3a) Necessarily, all undeserved, involuntary human suffering ultimately produces a net benefit for the sufferer. does not plausibly imply (3) s consequent: (3c) We never have a moral obligation to prevent undeserved, involuntary human suffering. That my allowing P s undeserved, involuntary suffering will result in a net benefit for P is, by (G5), not sufficient reason for me to not have a moral obligation to prevent P s suffering. More is necessary. So, (3) is not plausible. Even if all involuntary human suffering ultimately were to produce a net benefit for the sufferer, there would still be instances in which I had a moral obligation to prevent it. Such would be an instance, for example, where the benefit to the sufferer is only slightly more than preventing the suffering would yield. Moreover, according to (G1)-(G4), it will never be the case that we may allow an instance of undeserved, involuntary suffering on the grounds

ON GOD, SUFFERING, AND THEODICAL INDIVIDUALISM 191 that it will produce a far greater benefit for the person than would preventing the suffering. And that is because in every instance, according to (G1)-(G4), God will in any case bring about the maximum possible degree of good for the person during his existence whether he endures that particular suffering or not. So the clause (a) of (G5) will never apply to any of us when faced with the opportunity to prevent suffering. For my money, theodical individualism should entail that we always have an obligation to prevent a case of suffering in P, unless the conditions of (G5) are met. In practice, this means that in the great majority of situations, my theodical individualism will obligate preventing suffering. In any case, since (G1)-(G5) is not implausible, (3) is not yet plausible. Well, now, you ask, what justifies God allowing undeserved, involuntary suffering? After all, (G5) obligates God no less than it does mere mortals. And since God is a perfect being God will faithfully fulfill the dictate of (G5). On (G1)-(G4), it follows that the suffering God allows a person to endure is such that God allows it either: (i) so as to produce for that person a degree of good that is maximal for that person and also satisfies the conditions of (G5), or: (ii) because allowing it follows from God s juggling of God s obligations to all human persons. Since God is the creator of all persons and sustains them in life at every moment, all human beings stand before God with an equal claim on God to produce for them a maximal possible ultimate benefit in their existence. All human beings are turned to God with an equal claim to a personal maximal net benefit, everything else being equal. Thus, God s obligations to others besides P are of vastly greater dimensions than that of any human being to other persons. That is at least one reason why God might be justified in allowing suffering in the world, in vastly many cases, while humans have relatively sparse permission to do so. I have already argued that in light of (G1)-(G5) such thinking does not violate the above Kantian stricture about using people as mere means. One might be skeptical as to whether the world we live in is one where the God of (G1)-(G4) exists. One might doubt, for example, whether every person receives an ultimate benefit that makes his or her existence worthwhile. Such doubts belong to the problem of evil and must be discussed on their own. They do not relate to the present argument against God s existence from theodical individualism. That argument, I have tried to show, fails to convince.