Reviewing Nolen Gertz s Nihilism and Technology. Frank Scalambrino, Duquesne University

Similar documents
Political Science 206 Modern Political Philosophy Spring Semester 2011 Clark University

How to Live a More Authentic Life in Both Markets and Morals

Man Alone with Himself

Nietzsche, Vol. 1: The Will To Power As Art, Vol. 2: The Eternal Recurrance Of The Same By Martin Heidegger, David Farrrell Krell READ ONLINE

Kant and the Problem of Metaphysics 1. By Tom Cumming

POSC 256/350: NIETZSCHE AND POLITICAL PHILOSOPHY. Professor Laurence Cooper Winter 2015 Willis 416 Office hours: F 10-12, 1-3

A Philosophically Appealing Nietzschean Theory of Value

Nietzsche s Philosophy as Background to an Examination of Tolkien s The Lord of the Rings

E L O G O S ELECTRONIC JOURNAL FOR PHILOSOPHY/2008 ISSN Tracks in the Woods. F.A. Hayek s Philosophy of History.

The Anarchist Aspects of Nietzsche s Philosophy- Presentation

BOOK REVIEW. Thomas R. Schreiner, Interpreting the Pauline Epistles (Grand Rapids: Baker Academic, 2nd edn, 2011). xv pp. Pbk. US$13.78.

J. Aaron Simmons and Bruce Ellis Benson, The New Phenomenology: A Philosophical Introduction (New York: Bloomsbury, 2013)

Phil 2303 Intro to Worldviews Philosophy Department Dallas Baptist University Dr. David Naugle

Undergraduate Calendar Content

Rationalist-Irrationalist Dialectic in Buddhism:

Friedrich Nietzsche ( ) On Beyond Good and Evil 1

Translating, Repeating, Naming: Foucault, Derrida and The Genealogy of Morals

DISCUSSION PRACTICAL POLITICS AND PHILOSOPHICAL INQUIRY: A NOTE

On Some Alleged Consequences Of The Hartle-Hawking Cosmology. In [3], Quentin Smith claims that the Hartle-Hawking cosmology is inconsistent with

ntroduction to Socialist Humanism: An International Symposium by Eri...

In Defense of Radical Empiricism. Joseph Benjamin Riegel. Chapel Hill 2006

Review of The use of bodies by Giorgio Agamben, translated by Adam Kotsko

Who is a person? Whoever you want it to be Commentary on Rowlands on Animal Personhood

Going beyond good and evil

Who is Able to Tell the Truth? A Review of Fearless Speech by Michel Foucault. Los Angeles, CA: Semiotext(e), 2001.

STILL NO REDUNDANT PROPERTIES: REPLY TO WIELENBERG

Response to The Problem of the Question About Animal Ethics by Michal Piekarski

- We might, now, wonder whether the resulting concept of justification is sufficiently strong. According to BonJour, apparent rational insight is

Honours Programme in Philosophy

Ethical Theory for Catholic Professionals

A Review of Norm Geisler's Prolegomena

PHILOSOPHY IM 25 SYLLABUS IM SYLLABUS (2019)

What did Nietzsche think that it was possible to learn from the past?


PHIL101: Assessment 8

1 Hans Jonas, The Imperative of Responsibility: In Search of an Ethics for the Technological Age (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1984), 1-10.

Logical Puzzles and the Concept of God

In order to make some sense of this paradoxical figure s situation, which is marked by their material connection to labor and symbolic alliance with

Take Home Exam #1. PHI 1500: Major Issues in Philosophy Prof. Lauren R. Alpert

This paper serves as an enquiry into whether or not a theory of metaphysics can grow

4/30/2010 cforum :: Moderator Control Panel

Oneing. Most of us were given the impression that Christ was. introduction

Haberdashers Aske s Boys School

Emptiness Appraised: A Critical Study of Nagarjuna's Philosophy (review)

A Multitude of Selves: Contrasting the Cartesian and Nietzschean views of selfhood

New people and a new type of communication Lyudmila A. Markova, Russian Academy of Sciences

Class 23 - April 20 Plato, What is Right Conduct?

Kant and the 19 th Century ***Syllabus***

WHY IS GOD GOOD? EUTYPHRO, TIMAEUS AND THE DIVINE COMMAND THEORY

WHAT FACTORS LED THE APOLOGISTS TO EXPOUND AND DEFEND THEIR CHRISTIAN FAITH AND HOW IS THIS EVIDENT IN WHAT THEY WRITE?

A Review on What Is This Thing Called Ethics? by Christopher Bennett * ** 1

Friedrich Nietzsche and European Nihilism Paul van Tongeren

FUNDAMENTAL PRINCIPLES OF THE METAPHYSIC OF MORALS. by Immanuel Kant

Literature, Philosophy, Nihilism

John Scottus Eriugena: Analysing the Philosophical Contribution of an Forgotten Thinker

2003 Marc Helfer. Marc Helfer. June 10, 2002 PHIL 320. Professor Mills

PHILOSOPHY th Century Philosophy: Nietzsche in Context

Post Pluralism Through the Lens of Post Modernity By Aimee Upjohn Light

Hegel and History. Jay D. Feist

Violence as a philosophical theme

Consciousness might be defined as the perceiver of mental phenomena. We might say that there are no differences between one perceiver and another, as

1/8. Introduction to Kant: The Project of Critique

POL320 Y1Y/L0101: MODERN POLITICAL THOUGHT Summer 2015

Process Thought and Bridge Building: A Response to Stephen K. White. Kevin Schilbrack

KINGSBOROUGH COMMUNITY COLLEGE of The City University of New York. Common COURSE SYLLABUS

BENEDIKT PAUL GÖCKE. Ruhr-Universität Bochum

Existentialism Philosophy 303 (CRN 12245) Fall 2013

Tu Quoque, Archbishop

Ethical values in Nietzsche s thinking

Chapter 15. Elements of Argument: Claims and Exceptions

Wittgenstein on The Realm of Ineffable

5 A Modal Version of the

On Searle on Human Rights, Again! J. Angelo Corlett, San Diego State University

Philosophy Courses Fall 2011

Tara Smith s Ayn Rand s Normative Ethics: A Positive Contribution to the Literature on Objectivism?

Humanizing the Future

By the end of this course, students will be able to:

VIEWING PERSPECTIVES

Phil 341: Kierkegaard and Nietzsche. CSUN Spring, 2016 Prof. Robin M. Muller. Office: Sierra Tower 506

Perspectival Methods in Metaphysics

A RESPONSE TO "THE MEANING AND CHARACTERISTICS OF AN AMERICAN THEOLOGY"

The Unveiling of Illusion in Nietzschean Aesthetics

Received: 30 August 2007 / Accepted: 16 November 2007 / Published online: 28 December 2007 # Springer Science + Business Media B.V.

Care of the Soul: Service-Learning and the Value of the Humanities

OSSA Conference Archive OSSA 3

JUSTYNA MORUŚ WARRIOR CODES AS AN ELEMENT OF THE ETHICS OF STRUGGLE

The Will to Power. Benjamin C. Sax 1

12 Bible Course Map--2013

The Greatest Mistake: A Case for the Failure of Hegel s Idealism

1/10. Descartes Laws of Nature

The Vocation Movement in Lutheran Higher Education

A copy can be downloaded for personal non-commercial research or study, without prior permission or charge

A Studying of Limitation of Epistemology as Basis of Toleration with Special Reference to John Locke

[JGRChJ 9 (2013) R28-R32] BOOK REVIEW

Prompt: Explain van Inwagen s consequence argument. Describe what you think is the best response

SIMONE DE BEAUVOIR: ARE WOMEN COMPLICIT IN THEIR OWN SUBJUGATION, IF SO HOW?

FIRST STUDY. The Existential Dialectical Basic Assumption of Kierkegaard s Analysis of Despair

Ludwig Feuerbach The Essence of Christianity (excerpts) 1 PHIL101 Prof. Oakes updated: 10/23/13 9:10 AM. Section III: How do I know? Reading III.

Evaluating Heidegger s Fundamental Mood of Dread: Intentionality and Revealing

From a Statement of Its Vision Toward Thinking into the Desire of a Corporate Daimon Frank Scalambrino, University of Dallas

Transcription:

http://social-epistemology.com ISSN: 2471-9560 Reviewing Nolen Gertz s Nihilism and Technology Frank Scalambrino, Duquesne University Scalambrino, Frank. Reviewing Nolen Gertz s Nihilism and Technology. Social Epistemology Review and Reply Collective 7, no. 12 (2018): 22-28. Short url: https://wp.me/p1bfg0-44b (provided by WordPress)

Vol. 7, no. 12 (2018): 22-28. https://wp.me/p1bfg0-44b There are three (3) parts to this review, each of which brings a philosophical, and/or structural, issue regarding Dr. Gertz s book into critical focus. 1) His characterization of nihilism. a) This is specifically about Nietzsche. 2) His (lack of) characterization of the anti- and post-humanist positions in philosophy of technology. a) Importantly, this should also change what he says about Marx. 3) In light of the above two changes, going forward, he should (re)consider the way he frames his human-nihilism relations 1) Consider that: If his characterization of nihilism in Nietzsche as Who cares? were correct, then Nietzsche would not have been able to say that Christianity is nihilistic (cf. The Anti-Christ 6-7; cf. The Will to Power 247). The following organizes a range of ways he could correct this, from the most to least pervasive. 1a) He could completely drop the term nihilism. Ultimately, I think the term that fits best with his project, as it stands, is decadence. (More on this below.) In 43 of The Will to Power, Nietzsche explained that Nihilism is not a cause, but only the rationale of decadence. 1b) He could keep the term nihilism on the cover, but re-work the text to reflect technology as decadence, and then frame decadence as indicating a kind of nihilism (to justify keeping nihilism on the cover). 1c) He could keep everything as is; however, as will be clear below, his conception of nihilism and human-nihilism relations leaves him open to two counter-arguments which as I see it are devastating to his project. The first suggests that from the point of view of Nietzsche s actual definition of nihilism, his theory itself is nihilistic. The second suggests that (from a post-human point of view) the ethical suggestions he makes (based on his revelation of human-nihilism relations) are empty threats in that the de-humanization of which he warns refers to a non-entity. Lastly, I strongly suggest anyone interested in nihilism in Nietzsche consult both Heidegger (1987) and Deleuze (2006). 1. Gertz s Characterization of Nihilism Nietzsche s writings are notoriously difficult to interpret. Of course, this is not the place to provide a How to Read Nietzsche. However, Dr. Gertz s approach to reading Nietzsche is peculiar enough to warrant the following remarks about the difficulties involved. When approaching Nietzsche you should ask three questions: (1) Do you believe Nietzsche s writings are wholly coherent, partially coherent, or not coherent at all? (2) Do you believe Nietzsche s writings are wholly consistent, partially consistent, or not consistent at all? (3) Does Nietzsche s being consistent make a system out of his philosophy? 22

F. Scalambrino The first question is important because you may believe that Nietzsche was a madman. And, the fallacy of ad hominem aside, you may believe his madness somehow invalidates what he said either partially or totally. Further, it is clear that Nietzsche does not endorse a philosophy which considers rationality the most important aspect of being human. Thus, it may be possible to consider Nietzsche s writings as purposeful or inspired incoherence. For example, this latter point of view may find support in Nietzsche s letters, and is exemplified by Blanchot s comment: The fundamental characteristic of Nietzsche s truth is that it can only be misunderstood, can only be the object of an endless misunderstanding. (1995: 299). The second question is important because across Nietzsche s writings he seemingly contradicts himself or changes his philosophical position. There are two main issues, then, regarding consistency. On the one hand, distinct periods of philosophy have been associated with various groupings of Nietzsche s writings, and establishing these periods along with affirming position changes can be supported by Nietzsche s own words (so long as one considers those statements coherent). Thus, according to the standard division, we have the Early Writings from 1872-1876, the Middle Writings from 1878-1882, the Later Writings from 1883-1887, and the Final Writings of 1888. By examining Dr. Gertz s Bibliography it is clear that he privileges the Later and Unpublished of Nietzsche s writings. On the other hand, as William H. Schaberg convincingly argued in his The Nietzsche Canon: A Publication History and Bibliography, despite all of the inconsistencies, from beginning to end, Nietzsche s writings represent the development of what he called the Dionysian Worldview. Importantly, Dr. Gertz neither addresses these exegetical issues nor does he even mention Dionysus. The third question is important because throughout the last century of Nietzsche scholarship there have been various trends regarding the above, first two, questions, and often the consistency and anti-system issues have been conflated. Thus, scholars in the past have argued that Nietzsche must be inconsistent if not incoherent because he is purposefully an anti-systematic thinker. However, as Schaberg s work, among others, makes clear: To have a consistent theme does not necessitate that one s work is systematic. For example, it is not the case that all philosophers are systematic philosophers merely because they consistently write about philosophy. That the Dionysian Worldview is ultimately Nietzsche s consistent theme is not negated by any inconsistencies regarding how to best characterize that worldview. Thus, I would be interested to know the process through which Dr. Gertz decided on the title of this book. On the one hand, it is clear that he considers this a book that combines Nietzsche and philosophy of technology. On the other hand, Dr. Gertz s allegiance to (the unfortunately titled) postphenomenology and the way he takes up Nietzsche s ideas make the title of his book problematic. For instance, the title of the first section of Chapter 2 is: What is Nihilism? 23

Vol. 7, no. 12 (2018): 22-28. https://wp.me/p1bfg0-44b What About the Meaning of Nihilism? Dr. Gertz notes that because the meaning of nihilism in the writings of Nietzsche is controversial, he will not even attempt to define nihilism in terms of Nietzsche s writings (p. 13). He then, without referencing any philosopher at all, defines nihilism stating: in everyday usage it is taken to mean something roughly equivalent to the expression Who cares? (p. 13). Lastly, in the next section he uses Jean-Paul Sartre to characterize nihilism as bad faith. All this is problematic. First, is this book about nihilism or bad faith? It seems to be about the latter, which (more on this to come) leads one to wonder whether the title and the supposed (at times forced) use of Nietzsche were not a (nihilistic?) marketing-ploy. Second, though Dr. Gertz doesn t think it necessary to articulate and defend the meaning of nihilism in Nietzsche, just a casual glance at the same section of the Unpublished Writings (The Will to Power) that Gertz invokes can be used to argue against his characterization of nihilism as Who cares? For example, Nietzsche is far more hardcore than Who cares? as evidenced by: Nihilism does not only contemplate the in vain! nor is it merely the belief that everything deserves to perish: one helps to destroy [emphasis added] (1968b: 18). Nihilism pertains to moral value. It is in this context that Nietzsche is a so-called immoralist. Nietzsche came to see the will as, pun intended, beyond good and evil. It is moralizing that leads to nihilism. Consider the following from Nietzsche: Schopenhauer interpreted high intellectuality as liberation from the will; he did not want to see the freedom from moral prejudice which is part of the emancipation of the great spirit Fundamental instinctive principle of all philosophers and historians and psychologists: everything of value in man, art, history, science, religion, technology [emphasis added], must be proved to be of moral value, morally conditioned, in aim, means and outcome Does man become better through it? (1968b: pp. 205-6). The will is free, beyond all moral values, and so the desire to domesticate it is nihilistic if for no reason other than in domesticating it one has lowered the sovereignty of the will into conformity with some set of rules designed for the preservation of the herd (or academiccartel). Incidentally, I invoked this Nietzschean point in my chapter: What Control? Life at the limits of power expression in our book Social Epistemology and Technology. Moreover, none of us philosophers of the future have yet expressed this point in a way that surpasses the excellence and eloquence of Baudrillard (cf. The Perfect Crime and The Agony of Power). In other words, what is in play are power differentials. Thus, oddly, as soon as Dr. Gertz begins moralizing by denouncing technology as nihilistic, he reveals himself not technology to be nihilistic. For all these reasons, and more, it is not clear why Dr. Gertz insists on the term nihilism or precisely how he sees this as Nietzsche s position. 24

F. Scalambrino To be sure, the most recent data from the CDC indicate that chlamydia, gonorrhea, and syphilis are presently at an all-time high; do you think this has nothing to do with the technological mediation of our social relations? Yet, the problem of bringing in Nietzsche s conception of nihilism is that Nietzsche might not see this as a problem at all. On the one hand, we have all heard the story that Nietzsche knew he had syphilis; yet, he supposedly refused to seek treatment, and subsequently died from it. On the other hand, at times it seems as though the Nietzschean term Dr. Gertz could have used would have been decadence. Thus, the problem with technology is that it is motivated by decadence and breeds decadence. Ultimately, the problem is that despite the nowadays obligatory affirmation of the non-binary nature of whatever we happen to be talking about Dr. Gertz frames his conception in terms of the bifurcation: technophile v. technophobe. Yet, Nietzsche is, of course, a transcendental philosopher, so there are three (not 2) positions. The third position is Amor Fati. The predominance of suffering over pleasure or the opposite (hedonism): these two doctrines are already signposts to nihilism that is how a kind of man speaks who no longer dares to posit a will, a purpose, a meaning: for any healthier kind of man the value of life is certainly not measured by the standard of these trifles [pleasure and pain]. And suffering might predominate, and in spite of that a powerful will might exist, a Yes to life, a need for this predominance. (Nietzsche, 1968b: p. 23). In terms of philosophy of technology, if it is our fate to exist in a world torn asunder by technological mediation, well, then, love it (in this wise, even the Death of God can be celebrated). And, here would be the place to mention postmodern irony, which Dr. Gertz does not consider. In sum, Dr. Gertz s use of the term nihilism is, to say the least, problematic. Technology s Disconnect From Nietzsche Himself Nietzsche infamously never used a typewriter. It was invented during his lifetime, and, as the story goes, he supposedly tried to use the technology but couldn t get the hang of it, so he went back to writing by hand. This story points to an insight that it seems Dr. Gertz s book doesn t consider. For Nietzsche human existence is the point of departure, not technology. So, the very idea that technological mediation will lead to a better existence (even if better only means more efficient, as it could in the case of the typewriter), should, according to Nietzsche s actual logic of nihilism, see the desire to use a typewriter as either a symptom of decadence or an expression of strength; however, these options do not manifest in the logic of Gertz s Nietzsche analysis. Rather, Dr. Gertz moralizes the use of technology: Working out which of these perspectives is correct is thus vital for ensuring that technologies are providing us leisure as a form of liberation rather than providing us leisure as a form of dehumanization. (p. 4). Does the Who cares? logic of Gertz s nihilism necessarily lead to an interpretation of Nietzsche as a kind of Luddite? 25

Vol. 7, no. 12 (2018): 22-28. https://wp.me/p1bfg0-44b Before moving on to the next part of this review, a few last remarks about how Dr. Gertz uses Nietzsche s writings are called for. There are nine (9) chapters in Nihilism and Technology. Dr. Gertz primarily uses the first two chapters to speak to the terminology he will use throughout the book. He uses the third chapter to align himself with the academic-cartel, and the remaining chapters are supposed to illustrate his explication of what he calls Nietzsche s five human-nihilism relations. All of these so-called human-nihilism relations revolve around discussions which take place only in the Third Essay of Nietzsche s On the Genealogy of Morals except one foray into The Gay Science. Two points should be made here. First, Dr. Gertz calls these nihilism relations, but they are really just examples of Slave Mentality. This should come as no surprise to those familiar with Nietzsche because of where in his writings Dr. Gertz is focused. Moreover, there is not enough space here to fully explain why, but it is problematic to simply replace the term Slave Mentality with nihilism relation. Second, among these nihilism relations there are two glaring misappropriations of Nietzsche s writings regarding pity and divinity. That is, when Dr. Gertz equates pity sex (i.e. having sexual intercourse, of one kind or another, with someone ostensibly because you pity them) with Nietzsche s famous discussion of pity in On the Genealogy of Morals, it both overlooks Nietzsche s comments regarding Master pity and trivializes the notion of pity in Nietzsche. For, as already noted above, if in your day to day practice of life you remain oriented to the belief that you need an excuse for whatever you do, then you are moralizing. (Remember when we used to think that Nietzsche was dangerous?) If you are moralizing, then you re a nihilist. You re a nihilist because you believe there is a world that is better than the one that exists. You believe in a world that is nothing. Conclusion: The faith in the categories of reason is the cause of nihilism. We have measured the value of the world according to categories that refer to a purely fictitious world. (Nietzsche, 1968b: p. 13). Lastly, Dr. Gertz notes: Google stands as proof that humans do not need gods, that humans are capable of fulfilling the role once reserved for the gods. (p. 199). However, in making that statement he neither accurately speaks of the gods, in general, nor of Nietzsche s understanding of for example Dionysus. 2) The Anti- and Post-Humanist Positions in Philosophy of Technology In a footnote Dr. Gertz thanks an anonymous reviewer for telling him to clarify his position regarding humanism, transhumanism, and posthumanism; however, despite what sounds like his acknowledgement, he does not provide such a clarification. The idea is supposed to be that transhumanism is a kind of humanism, and anti- and post-humanism are philosophies which deny that human refers to a natural category. It is for this reason that many scholars talk of two Marxisms. That is to say, there is the earlier Marxism which takes human as a natural category and aims at liberation, and there is the later Marxism which takes human to be category constructed by Capital. 26

F. Scalambrino It is from this latter idea that the care for the self is criticized as something to be sold to the worker and to eventually transform the worker s work into the work of consumption this secures perpetual demand, as the worker is transformed into the consumer. Moreover, this is absolutely of central importance in the philosophy of technology. For, from a point of view that is truly post-human, Dr. Gertz s moralizing-warning that technology may lead to a form of dehumanization. (p. 4) is an empty threat. On the one hand, this fidelity to human as a natural category comes from Don Ihde s postphenomenology. For Gertz s idea of human-nihilism relations was developed from Idhe s human-technology relations. (p. 45). Gertz notes, Ihde turns Heidegger s analysis of hammering into an exemplar of how to carry out analyses of human-technology relations, analyses which lead Ihde to expand the field of human-technology relations beyond Heidegger s examples (p. 49). However, there are two significant problems here, both of which point back, again, to the lack of clarification regarding post-humanism. First, Heidegger speaks of Dasein and of Being, not of human. Similarly, Nietzsche could say, The will to overcome an affect is ultimately only the will of another affect, or of several other affects. (Nietzsche, 1989a: 117), or There is no being behind doing the doer is merely a fiction added to the deed the deed is everything. (Nietzsche, 1989b: p. 45). Second, the section of Being & Time from which postphenomenology develops its relations of co-constitution is The Worldhood of the World, not Being-in-the-World. In other words, Dasein is not an aspect of ready-to-hand hammering, the ready-to-hand is an aspect of Dasein. Thus, human may be seen as a worldly present-at-hand projection of an in order to. Again, this is also why Gertz doesn t characterize Marxism (p. 5) as two Marxisms, namely he does not consider the anti- or post-humanist readings of Marx. Hence, the importance of clarifying the incommensurability between humanism and posthumanism: Gertz s characterization of technology as nihilistic due to its de-humanizing may turn out to be itself nihilistic in terms of its moralizing (noted in Part I, above) and in terms of its taking the fictional-rational category human as more primordial than the (according to Nietzsche) non-discursive sovereign will. 3) His human-nihilism relations Students of the philosophy of technology will find the Chapter 3 discussion of Ihde s work helpful; going forward, we should inquire regarding Ihde s four categories in the context of post-humanism and cybernetics if they are exhaustive. Moreover, how might each of these categories look from a point of view which takes the fundamental alteration of (human) being by technology to be desirable? This is a difficult question to navigate because it shifts the context for understanding Gertz s philic/phobic dichotomy away from care for the self and toward a context of evolutionary selection. Might public self-awareness, in such a context, influence the evolutionary selection? 27

Vol. 7, no. 12 (2018): 22-28. https://wp.me/p1bfg0-44b So long as one is explicitly taking a stand for humanism, then one could argue that the matrix of human-technology relations are symptoms of decadence. Interestingly, such a stance may make Nihilism and Technology, first and foremost, an ethics book and not a philosophy of technology book. Yet, especially, though perhaps not exclusively, presenting only the humanistic point of view leaves one open to the counter-argument that the intellectual and philosophical relations to technology that allow for such an analysis into these various discursive identities betrays a kind of decadence. It would not be much of a stretch to come to the conclusion that Nietzsche would consider academics decadent. Further, it would also be helpful for philosophy of technology students to consider from a humanistic point of view the use of technology to extend human life in light of humandecadence relations. Of course, whether or not these relations, in general, lead to nihilism is a separate question. However, the people who profit from the decadence on which these technologies stand will rhetorically-bulwark the implementation of their technological procedures in terms of saving lives. Here, Nietzsche was again prophetic, as he explicitly considered a philosophy of survive at all costs to be a sign of degeneracy and decay. Contact details: franklscalambrino@gmail.com References Blanchot, Maurice. (1995). The Work of Fire. C. Mandell (Trans.). Stanford, CA: Stanford University Press. Deleuze, Gilles. (2006). Nietzsche and Philosophy. H. Tomlinson (Trans.). New York: Columbia University. Heidegger, Martin. (1987). D.F. Krell (Ed.). Nietzsche, Vol. IV: Nihilism. F.A. Capuzzi (Trans.). New York: Harper & Row. Nietzsche, Friedrich. (1989a). Beyond Good and Evil: Prelude to a Philosophy of the Future. W. Kaufmann (Trans.). New York: Vintage.. (1989b). On the Genealogy of Morals /Ecce Homo. W. Kaufmann (Trans.). New York: Vintage Books.. (1968a). Twilight of the Idols/The Anti-Christ. R.J. Hollingdale (Trans.). Middlesex, England: Penguin Books.. (1968b). The Will to Power. W. Kaufmann and R.J. Hollingdale (Trans.). New York: Vintage Books. Schaberg, William H. (1995). The Nietzsche Canon: A Publication History and Bibliography. Chicago: University of Chicago Press. 28