Philosophiegeschichte und logische Analyse Logical Analysis and History of Philosophy

Similar documents
Logical Analysis and History of Philosophy Philosophiegeschichte und logische Analyse

Logical Analysis and History of Philosophy Philosophiegeschichte und logische Analyse

Logical Analysis and History of Philosophy Philosophiegeschichte und logische Analyse

Fabrice Correia and Sven Rosenkranz. As Time Goes By. Eternal Facts in an Ageing Universe. mentis PADERBORN

Semantic Foundations for Deductive Methods

Reply to Robert Koons

Logical Analysis and History of Philosophy Philosophiegeschichte und logische Analyse

Validity of Inferences *

Haberdashers Aske s Boys School

Informalizing Formal Logic

Selections from Aristotle s Prior Analytics 41a21 41b5

Lecture 3. I argued in the previous lecture for a relationist solution to Frege's puzzle, one which

Intuitive evidence and formal evidence in proof-formation

Remarks on a Foundationalist Theory of Truth. Anil Gupta University of Pittsburgh

Predicate logic. Miguel Palomino Dpto. Sistemas Informáticos y Computación (UCM) Madrid Spain

Moral Argumentation from a Rhetorical Point of View

The Ontological Argument for the existence of God. Pedro M. Guimarães Ferreira S.J. PUC-Rio Boston College, July 13th. 2011

Logical Mistakes, Logical Aliens, and the Laws of Kant's Pure General Logic Chicago February 21 st 2018 Tyke Nunez

Zimmerman, Michael J. Subsidiary Obligation, Philosophical Studies, 50 (1986):

What is Formal in Husserl s Logical Investigations?

CHAPTER 1 A PROPOSITIONAL THEORY OF ASSERTIVE ILLOCUTIONARY ARGUMENTS OCTOBER 2017

The Appeal to Reason. Introductory Logic pt. 1

(1) A phrase may be denoting, and yet not denote anything; e.g., 'the present King of France'.

Natujwa Umbertina Mvungi. Challenges in the Implementation of the East African Community Common Market Protocol

UC Berkeley, Philosophy 142, Spring 2016

Evaluating Classical Identity and Its Alternatives by Tamoghna Sarkar

2.3. Failed proofs and counterexamples

CHAPTER 2 THE LARGER LOGICAL LANDSCAPE NOVEMBER 2017

Bertrand Russell Proper Names, Adjectives and Verbs 1

From Necessary Truth to Necessary Existence

Truth At a World for Modal Propositions

Todays programme. Background of the TLP. Some problems in TLP. Frege Russell. Saying and showing. Sense and nonsense Logic The limits of language

A Model of Decidable Introspective Reasoning with Quantifying-In

Mikhael Dua. Tacit Knowing. Michael Polanyi s Exposition of Scientific Knowledge. Herbert Utz Verlag Wissenschaft München

Supplementary Section 6S.7

Quine on the analytic/synthetic distinction

Oxford Scholarship Online Abstracts and Keywords

Ayer and Quine on the a priori

Broad on Theological Arguments. I. The Ontological Argument

Logical Constants as Punctuation Marks

Mathematics in and behind Russell s logicism, and its

Göran Sundholm MACCOLL ON JUDGEMENT AND INFERENCE

The Development of Laws of Formal Logic of Aristotle

TRUTH-MAKERS AND CONVENTION T

IS THE SYLLOGISTIC A LOGIC? it is not a theory or formal ontology, a system concerned with general features of the

KANT, MORAL DUTY AND THE DEMANDS OF PURE PRACTICAL REASON. The law is reason unaffected by desire.

Pictures, Proofs, and Mathematical Practice : Reply to James Robert Brown

Scott Soames: Understanding Truth

Pastor-teacher Don Hargrove Faith Bible Church September 8, 2011

What is the Nature of Logic? Judy Pelham Philosophy, York University, Canada July 16, 2013 Pan-Hellenic Logic Symposium Athens, Greece

Potentialism about set theory

The Relationship between the Truth Value of Premises and the Truth Value of Conclusions in Deductive Arguments

What would count as Ibn Sīnā (11th century Persia) having first order logic?

Understanding Truth Scott Soames Précis Philosophy and Phenomenological Research Volume LXV, No. 2, 2002

prohibition, moral commitment and other normative matters. Although often described as a branch

SAVING RELATIVISM FROM ITS SAVIOUR

Overview of Today s Lecture

1/7. The Postulates of Empirical Thought

Ethical Consistency and the Logic of Ought

Received: 30 August 2007 / Accepted: 16 November 2007 / Published online: 28 December 2007 # Springer Science + Business Media B.V.

Chadwick Prize Winner: Christian Michel THE LIAR PARADOX OUTSIDE-IN

Prior, Berkeley, and the Barcan Formula. James Levine Trinity College, Dublin

Argumentative Analogy versus Figurative Analogy

SMITH ON TRUTHMAKERS 1. Dominic Gregory. I. Introduction

ON DENOTING BERTRAND RUSSELL ORIGINALLY PUBLISHED IN MIND 14.4 (1905): THIS COPY FROM PHILOSOPHY-INDEX.COM.

Philosophy 1100: Introduction to Ethics. Critical Thinking Lecture 1. Background Material for the Exercise on Validity

Bayesian Probability

Stang (p. 34) deliberately treats non-actuality and nonexistence as equivalent.

Class #14: October 13 Gödel s Platonism

Revista del Instituto de Filosofía, Universidad de Valparaíso, Año 1, N 1. Junio Pags Resumen

The Boundaries of Hegel s Criticism of Kant s Concept of the Noumenal

Russell and the Universalist Conception of Logic. Russell is often said to have shared with Frege a distinctively universalist conception

Woods, John (2001). Aristotle s Earlier Logic. Oxford: Hermes Science, xiv pp. ISBN

Carnap s notion of analyticity and the two wings of analytic philosophy. Christian Damböck Institute Vienna Circle

ROBERT STALNAKER PRESUPPOSITIONS

International Phenomenological Society

Conventionalism and the linguistic doctrine of logical truth

A-LEVEL Religious Studies

ILLOCUTIONARY ORIGINS OF FAMILIAR LOGICAL OPERATORS

But we may go further: not only Jones, but no actual man, enters into my statement. This becomes obvious when the statement is false, since then

Theories of propositions

A Defense of Contingent Logical Truths

Basic Concepts and Skills!

Leibniz, Principles, and Truth 1

Language, Meaning, and Information: A Case Study on the Path from Philosophy to Science Scott Soames

Al-Sijistani s and Maimonides s Double Negation Theology Explained by Constructive Logic

Quantificational logic and empty names

Philosophy of Mathematics Kant

Boghossian & Harman on the analytic theory of the a priori

1/12. The A Paralogisms

The Greatest Mistake: A Case for the Failure of Hegel s Idealism

Resemblance Nominalism and counterparts

Timothy Williamson: Modal Logic as Metaphysics Oxford University Press 2013, 464 pages

Russell on Denoting. G. J. Mattey. Fall, 2005 / Philosophy 156. The concept any finite number is not odd, nor is it even.

Interpretation: Keeping in Touch with Reality. Gilead Bar-Elli. 1. In a narrow sense a theory of meaning (for a language) is basically a Tarski-like

Introduction. I. Proof of the Minor Premise ( All reality is completely intelligible )

Russell: On Denoting

VAGUENESS. Francis Jeffry Pelletier and István Berkeley Department of Philosophy University of Alberta Edmonton, Alberta, Canada

A BRIEF INTRODUCTION TO LOGIC FOR METAPHYSICIANS

In Search of the Ontological Argument. Richard Oxenberg

Transcription:

Uwe Meixner Albert Newen (Hrsg.) Philosophiegeschichte und logische Analyse Logical Analysis and History of Philosophy 2 Antike Philosophie Mit einem Schwerpunkt zum Meisterargument Ancient Philosophy With a focus on the Master Argument mentis Paderborn

Die Deutsche Bibliothek CIP-Einheitsaufnahme Antike Philosophie: Mit einem Schwerpunkt zum Meisterargument = Ancient philosophy. Paderborn: mentis, 1999 (Philosophiegeschichte und logische Analyse; 2) ISBN 3-89785-151-2 Erscheint jährl. Aufnahme nach 1 (1998) kart.: DM 68.00 (Einzelbd.), DM 58.00 (Einzelbd., für Abonnenten), ös 496.00 (Einzelbd.), ös 423.00 (Einzelbd., für Abonnenten), sfr 62.00 (Einzelbd.), sfr 51.80 (Einzelbd., für Abonnenten) 2 (1999) Umschlaggestaltung: Anna Braungart, Regensburg Gedruckt auf umweltfreundlichem, chlorfrei gebleichtem und alterungsbeständigem Papier ISO 9706 1999 mentis, Paderborn (mentis Verlag GmbH, Schulze-Delitzsch-Straße 19, D-33100 Paderborn) Alle Rechte vorbehalten. Dieses Werk sowie einzelne Teile desselben sind urheberrechtlich geschützt. Jede Verwertung in anderen als den gesetzlich zulässigen Fällen ist ohne vorherige Zustimmung des Verlages nicht zulässig. PrintedinGermany Herstellung: Rhema Tim Doherty, Münster ISBN 3-89785-151-2

Buchbesprechungen Book Reviews

Mark Siebel: Der Begriff der Ableitbarkeit bei Bolzano Sankt Augustin: Academia Verlag 1997 (Beiträge zur Bolzano-Forschung Bd. 7) It is generally agreed that Bolzano was the first to give a viable definition of logical consequence. But he deemed this concept too obvious and important to have escaped entirely the attention of logicians. Yet it seemed to him that the nature of this relation has not always been correctly grasped, or, if comprehended, discussed with insufficient generality, or without a precise definition (WL (Wissenschaftslehre) 155, II p. 128). Bolzano s comments on his predecessor s theories are generally (except for Hegel) most kind. He amends them and attributes insight and understanding where less generous observers may see only confusion. No doubt, earlier Bolzano scholars I am thinking of H. Scholz and Y. Bar- Hillel thought of themselves as similarly gracious when they took Bolzano to have anticipated a fair bit of classical logic even if eight of 22 theorems in Bar-Hillel s reconstruction are not provable in Bolzano, while three of Bar- Hillel s are anti-theorems in WL (Bar-Hillel, Bolzano s Propositional Logic; cf. also Scholz s review of Bar-Hillel and his Die Wissenschaftslehre Bolzano s). When they wrote, the language and logic of Principia Mathematica was widely touted as the ideal language, the one true logic and form of expression alone suited to overcome metaphysical confusion and even political friction. In this view, if an earlier logic did not anticipate the precepts of the classical, it was of merely historical significance. Whatever their merit as enthusiastic revivers of interest in Bolzano, Scholz and Bar-Hillel savaged his logic, which, in later terminology, falls in the class of deviant logics. A far more sensitive reconstruction was later given by Berg (Bolzano s Logic). The book before us is a sympathetic treatment of Bolzano s concept of consequence and much of his logic. It is historically sensitive and reflects the more relaxed approach to alternative logic systems of the last few decades. Siebel begins by exploring Bolzano s well-known claim that logical relations hold between abstract entities, i.e. propositions and representations in themselves (p. 15 45). The resolute anti-psychologism implied here has long been recognized and acclaimed: according to Bolzano, pure logic is not concerned with judgments, mental manifestations, but with their contents. Less appreciated is the equally important point that the objects of logical inquiry, the relata of logical relations, are not linguistic entities. For example, synonymous expressions, like male goose and gander, stand for the same abstract representation. In a logic so conceived, problems of synonymy cannot be addressed. As Siebel

266 Buchbesprechungen Book Reviews points out, in Bolzano s logic of variation (of which more presently) abstract representations are varied, not their linguistic expressions (p. 86). He then patiently explores various difficulties in Bolzano s approach. Since propositions are defined as either true or false, and since they and their parts are the only entities in the abstract logical realm, the common distinction between ill- and well-formed formulas, between sense and nonsense, does not come under scrutiny. Bolzano does indeed hold that all propositions have a standard form, viz. A has (or lacks) property b. But this is not a rule of well-formation, since it is never violated: the abstract realm contains no nonsensical strings of representations. Siebel points out that a strict and a liberal characterization of propositions is supported by the text. At one point, Bolzano says that the predicate must be the representation of a property [Beschaffenheitsvorstellung] (WL 81, I p. 393), but elsewhere he suggests that it might be any representation whatever, or even a proposition (WL 127, II p. 17). This would allow God has Kant is a bachelor to be a proposition which, since nonsense is not allowed, must be presumed false. Rightly, Siebel is puzzled (p. 33ff.). Further difficulties arise from Bolzano s claim that a proposition is false if its subject representation is empty [gegenstandlos], does not have a referent. This does not imply the falsehood of Round squares do not exist. Rather, Bolzano holds, that the canonical form of this claim is The representation round square is empty, which is true. Another problem is not addressed, however. If B is a universal term, and A non-empty, then A s are B s is true, but its contrapositive non-b s are non-a s is false not a desirable consequence. After the basics, Siebel discusses Bolzano s method of variation (p. 59 80). From a given proposition other propositions can be generated by replacing certain components. For example, let The man Caius is mortal be given. There is then a set of propositions which differ from this only in the element Caius, among them The man Titus is mortal, The man Sempronius is mortal, and so on. By attending to these sets, certain properties of propositions can be determined. In this case, the replacements resulting in non-empty subject terms generate a set of only true elements (WL 147, II p. 78). In Bolzano s terms, the proposition is universally valid, or analytic, with respect to Caius. Several authors have claimed that the replacements must be of the same category as the original. Siebel takes exception. In our example, every substitution either generates a true proposition or else, if we substitute triangle or other terms from a different category, a proposition with empty subject term. Bolzano, at least in this example, seems to prefer a proviso to categorial adequacy: a proposition is analytic with respect to m if every substitution on m is true, provided Gegenständlichkeit is preserved (WL 148, II p. 83). It would seem, however, that Caius is mortal in contrast to The man Caius is mortal is not analytic with respect to Caius unless, indeed, some sort of categorial restriction is placed on the substitutions. Siebel now turns to Bolzano s famous definition of logical consequence: Propositions M,N,O, follow [sind ableitbar] from propositions A,B,C,D, with

Siebel: Der Begriff der Ableitbarkeit bei Bolzano 267 respect to the variable parts i,j, if every set [Inbegriff ] of representations whose substitution for i,j, makes all of A,B,C,D, true also makes all of M,N,O, true (WL 155, II p. 114). He makes several important observations about this, noting that it is not meant to define a semiotic relation, but one that holds among propositions an sich. Attempts to recast Bolzano s definition for formulas, linguistic entities, lead to different results: problems of synonymy would have to be addressed, which, as noted, do not arise in the realm of the an sich. More important is the observation that Bolzano has defined a triadic relation (p. 87ff.), a point missed by some earlier commentators. Further, since the variable elements are specifically noted, Bolzano can describe partly material consequences, like All men are mortal, therefore Caius is mortal, which is valid if with respect to mortal. Bolzano s precise delineation of arguments has the inestimable merit that the so-called asymmetry thesis does not hold. In classical logic, arguments that instantiate some valid schema are valid, but it does not hold that arguments that instantiate an invalid schema are invalid, since all arguments have (some) invalid form. For example, A B, B A { A A instantiates 28 schemata, four of them classically valid, the rest invalid. Bolzano s logic of variation (if amended to apply to classical sentence logic) can discern only eight forms. The main point, though, is that we do not know what argument is meant, until it is disambiguated by stating, for example, that it is valid with respect to A, B, C and is thus identified as a hypothetical syllogism. The general result of these disambiguations is that in Bolzano s dispensation it holds that arguments that have valid form are valid, invalid form invalid (p. 121ff.). Siebel goes on to make a rather puzzling point. He claims that arguments are unambiguously described by the listing of variable elements, but that this listing does not determine whether an argument is formally or merely materially valid. For example, he thinks that A, therefore possibly A will be considered a material consequence if possibly is a material element, and formal if it is part of the formal repertoire. My thought is that in Bolzano s view the status of modal operators must be an objective matter, even if difficult to determine, subject to controversy, and perhaps unknown until Aristotle discussed it in the Prior Analytics. But even if it were not, it would still be the case that the asymmetry thesis fails, whether the arguments are formal or material. Material or enthymemic consequence is an interesting subject. Bolzano notes that for the assessment of such arguments information other than logical knowledge is often required (WL 223, II p. 392). Kambartel (Bolzanos Grundlegung, p. XVIIf., cited p. 139) thinks that this knowledge will consist of physical laws, definitions of general concepts, ethical maxims and other universal forms of validity (Geltungsformen). Indeed, Bolzano seems to imply as much. But often the validity of a material consequence will ride on plain contingent facts. Consider The Independence was commissioned in 1803. Therefore the Independence was not a ship of the line. This, as it turns out, is valid with respect to Independence, not because of some universal form, but because no ship of the line was commissioned in that year.

268 Buchbesprechungen Book Reviews A thorny issue is Bolzano s contention that the premisses of an argument must be consistent with each other with respect to the variables of the deduction. Buhl (Ableitbarkeit, p. 20ff.) and others have noted that this has several unpleasant consequences: (a) not every sentence follows from itself; (b) Bolzano s logic is not monotonic one cannot add arbitrary further premisses to a valid argument and preserve validity; (c) it is not the case that if B follows from A, then the denial of A follows from the denial of B; (d) reductio arguments are not valid. The last, as Siebel points out, is a condition often violated by Bolzano himself (p. 109). I shall come back to some of this later. In a chapter on the properties of the consequence relation (pp. 143 152), Siebel corrects earlier commentators, noting that consequence, being a triadic relation, cannot simply be described as asymmetrical, transitive, etc. Bolzano himself had seen (though he did not have the technical vocabulary) that interesting properties obtain under certain circumstances. For example, if C follows from B, and B from A with respect to the same set of variable terms, thenc follows from A with respect to that set. The relation is transitive in the first two positions if the third element is identical. Now follows a perceptive comparison between Bolzano s notion of an argument form and Russell s propositional functions (p. 153 183). It had been claimed by several commentators, among them Buhl, Bar-Hillel and Scholz, that Bolzano anticipated Russell s notions, or had a crude equivalent of it in his method of variation. In criticizing this, Siebel makes the correct observation that Bolzano does not countenance variables in the modern sense, and that the an sich realm contains only propositions and their parts, not items with variables (p. 164). He further notes that in Bolzano s system the evaluation of an argument must take into account not only the functions that are instantiated, but also the truth value of the propositions of the argument itself perhaps another untoward consequence of the consistency requirement (p. 168). Siebel does not note a formal point of considerable interest. A proposition f aa can be an instance of two functions, viz. f xy and f xx. By variation of a in f aa, however, we can obtain only a set of propositions with identical arguments, corresponding to f xx, but not the set corresponding to f xy. This is analogous to the hypothetical syllogism considered above, which instantiates 28 classical schemata, but is one of only eight forms in Bolzano s scheme. In relation to a given sentence or argument there are always more propositional functions than therearebolzano typeforms. Bolzano did in fact think that the form of propositions and arguments (relative to a set of variable terms) is a species or set (Gattung, WL 12, I p. 48). He supports this with a whimsical reference to Cicero (WL 81, I p. 391), who said that forma and species mean the same thing: utroque verbo idem significatur (Topica 30). I said in an earlier piece that such a set must be generated from a given argument, and incautiously added that it is not a pre-existing thing in which the argument participates, but must be operationally developed from it (Bolzano s Consequence, p. 306). Siebel points out that propositions are abstract objects that cannot be generated. In response, I hereby withdraw the second incautious claim. This does not mean, however, that the vocabulary of

Siebel: Der Begriff der Ableitbarkeit bei Bolzano 269 generation can easily be removed from the discussion of abstract objects. In the Pure Theory of Numbers, Bolzano says in the very first paragraph that he will call a member of a certain sequence a number, if it is represented by a term that indicates its method of generation [ihre Entstehungsart] (Reine Zahlenlehre p. 15). In a letter to Exner (Briefwechsel p. 83) he reflects on a formula that generates all prime numbers. Now if we take Siebel seriously, there can be no such formula, because no formula can generate abstract objects such as numbers (or anything else, for that matter). I prefer to continue to use this figure of speech, which cannot easily be replaced in mathematical discourse. In this case, we must insist on the distinction between generating a proposition or argument from a schema, and generating a form or species of propositions or arguments from a given proposition or argument. There follows an important chapter comparing Bolzano s concept of consequence with that of Tarski (p. 185 223). The difference between the definitions concerning the objects in question (propositions vs. formulas), the model theoretical vs. substitutional approach, Bolzano s restriction to consistent premisses etc. are duly noted. It is a fine critical chapter that does not simply repeat earlier claims that Bolzano, with the limited means he had in hand, roughly anticipated Tarski s definitive account. Finally, Siebel discusses the issue of relevance (p. 225 256). Anderson and Belnap, and others have claimed that it is a necessary condition for the relevance of a premiss set to the conclusion of an argument that they share some element. In this sense the premiss A & A is not relevant to the arbitrary conclusion B, which it classically entails. Bolzano did indeed state that in a valid argument, premisses and conclusion share a variable element (WL 155, II p. 120), but he does not give a good argument for this claim. I do not think that we can satisfactorily resolve this issue if we seek a proof in the text of WL. There is too much uncertainty, for example, whether we should take the consequence relation to be contrapositive. If we do, and if we also stipulate that the conclusion not be analytic with respect to the variables of the deduction, then a plausible argument for relevance can be mounted. But this means that we approach Bolzano s theory in a spirit of correcting, amending and enlarging, in the spirit in which, for instance, Euclid s Elements have been treated over the centuries. The Elements suffer from various deficiencies, lacking, for instance, a satisfactory definition of similarity, which is defined only ad hoc for triangles, regular polygons and polyhedra, but not for other figures and bodies. In general, if a formal system has enough structure and content, its deficiencies can with good conscience be corrected in appropriate ways. We can, and I think should, do this with Bolzano, for instance by extending his triadic conception of the consequence relation to formulas with well defined grammars, such as propositional formulas with classical connectives. The systems that result may, in various ways, contravene Bolzano s explicit stipulation. For example, we may wish to insist on the validity of A & A { A, despite Bolzano s explicit denial (WL 155, II p. 115). This is because the payoff, in propositional logic, of construing consequence as triadic, depends

270 Buchbesprechungen Book Reviews on the possibility of varying compound expressions independently of their constituents. If we don t do this, then a Bolzano version of propositional logic collapses into an uninteresting fragment of the classical. On the other hand, if, in this case, we vary A independently of A, the premisses are in fact consistent with respect to the variable elements, and in this sense the argument satisfies the consistency requirement. I have argued elsewhere that this liberal form of substitution still does not allow A & A { B. If we add the condition that the conclusion not be analytic with respect to the variable elements, we also prevent A { B = B and, in fact, have described a relevant consequence relation (Bolzano s Consequence, p. 310f.). Siebel chose not to take such a radical approach. Instead, he gives a sensitive and accurate exposition of Bolzano s stated doctrine, with due attention to its various problems. More than that, his several comparisons with contemporary and recent theories Russell on propositional functions, Wittgenstein on material consequence, Tarski on logical consequence, relevance logic and various others are invaluable. They help to clarify, through comparison and contrast, many of Bolzano s tenets. This is a very important study in a most valuable series. Rolf George, University of Waterloo, Canada References Berg, J.: Bolzano s Logic, Stockholm 1962. Bar-Hillel, Y.: Bolzano s Propositional Logic. In: Archiv für mathematische Logik und Grundlagenforschung 1, 1950 52, p. 65 98. Bolzano, B.: Wissenschaftslehre, 4 vols., Sulzbach 1837. Abbreviated as WL. Bolzano, B.: Reine Zahlenlehre. Gesamtausgabe Series II, vol. 8, Stuttgart 1976. Bolzano, B.: Der Briefwechsel Bolzanos mit Exner, ed. E. Winter. In: Bernard Bolzanos Schriften, vol. 4, Prague 1935. Buhl, G.: Ableitbarkeit und Abfolge in der Wissenschaftstheorie Bolzanos. In: Kantstudien Ergänzungsheft 83, Cologne 1961. George, R.: Bolzano s Consequence, Relevance and Enthymemes. In: JournalofPhilosophical Logic 12, 1983, p. 299 318. Kambartel, F.: Bernard Bolzano s Grundlegung der Logik, Hamburg 1978. Scholz, H.: Review of Bar-Hillel. In: Zentralblatt für Mathematik und ihre Grenzgebiete 47, p. 12f. Scholz, H.: Die Wissenschaftslehre Bolzanos. Eine Jahrhundertbetrachtung. In: Mathesis Universalis, ed. H. Hermes, F. Kambartel, J. Ritter, Basel 1961, p. 219 267.