Negative Introspection Is Mysterious

Similar documents
A Model of Decidable Introspective Reasoning with Quantifying-In

All They Know: A Study in Multi-Agent Autoepistemic Reasoning

SOME PROBLEMS IN REPRESENTATION OF KNOWLEDGE IN FORMAL LANGUAGES

Semantics and the Justification of Deductive Inference

Beyond Symbolic Logic

Module 5. Knowledge Representation and Logic (Propositional Logic) Version 2 CSE IIT, Kharagpur

Gödel's incompleteness theorems

Can machines think? Machines, who think. Are we machines? If so, then machines can think too. We compute since 1651.

Masters in Logic and Metaphysics

Artificial Intelligence: Valid Arguments and Proof Systems. Prof. Deepak Khemani. Department of Computer Science and Engineering

Can Gödel s Incompleteness Theorem be a Ground for Dialetheism? *

Knowledge, Time, and the Problem of Logical Omniscience

Can A Priori Justified Belief Be Extended Through Deduction? It is often assumed that if one deduces some proposition p from some premises

Does Deduction really rest on a more secure epistemological footing than Induction?

Informalizing Formal Logic

Logic for Robotics: Defeasible Reasoning and Non-monotonicity

Semantic Foundations for Deductive Methods

Formalizing a Deductively Open Belief Space

Exercise Sets. KS Philosophical Logic: Modality, Conditionals Vagueness. Dirk Kindermann University of Graz July 2014

ON CAUSAL AND CONSTRUCTIVE MODELLING OF BELIEF CHANGE

Constructive Logic, Truth and Warranted Assertibility

Appeared in: Al-Mukhatabat. A Trilingual Journal For Logic, Epistemology and Analytical Philosophy, Issue 6: April 2013.

Comments on Truth at A World for Modal Propositions

Artificial Intelligence. Clause Form and The Resolution Rule. Prof. Deepak Khemani. Department of Computer Science and Engineering

The Gödel Paradox and Wittgenstein s Reasons. 1. The Implausible Wittgenstein. Philosophia Mathematica (2009). Francesco Berto

How Gödelian Ontological Arguments Fail

Squeezing arguments. Peter Smith. May 9, 2010

KNOWLEDGE AND THE PROBLEM OF LOGICAL OMNISCIENCE

prohibition, moral commitment and other normative matters. Although often described as a branch

JELIA Justification Logic. Sergei Artemov. The City University of New York

Wittgenstein and Gödel: An Attempt to Make Wittgenstein s Objection Reasonable

DELUSIONS OF OMNISCIENCE. Roderic A. Gide University of Auckland, Auckland, New Zealand auckland.ac.nz

Predicate logic. Miguel Palomino Dpto. Sistemas Informáticos y Computación (UCM) Madrid Spain

Moore s Paradox, Introspection and Doxastic Logic

Supplementary Section 6S.7

The Paradox of Knowability and Semantic Anti-Realism

ILLOCUTIONARY ORIGINS OF FAMILIAR LOGICAL OPERATORS

Philosophy of Logic and Artificial Intelligence

From Necessary Truth to Necessary Existence

GROUNDING AND LOGICAL BASING PERMISSIONS

A Liar Paradox. Richard G. Heck, Jr. Brown University

Logical Omniscience in the Many Agent Case

Class #14: October 13 Gödel s Platonism

UC Berkeley, Philosophy 142, Spring 2016

Potentialism about set theory

Philosophy of Mathematics Kant

Oxford Scholarship Online Abstracts and Keywords

subject are complex and somewhat conflicting. For details see Wang (1993).

Can Negation be Defined in Terms of Incompatibility?

Remarks on a Foundationalist Theory of Truth. Anil Gupta University of Pittsburgh

2 Lecture Summary Belief change concerns itself with modelling the way in which entities (or agents) maintain beliefs about their environment and how

Lecture Notes on Classical Logic

Minds, Machines, And Mathematics A Review of Shadows of the Mind by Roger Penrose

Alvin Plantinga addresses the classic ontological argument in two

Understanding Truth Scott Soames Précis Philosophy and Phenomenological Research Volume LXV, No. 2, 2002

On Priest on nonmonotonic and inductive logic

Semantic Entailment and Natural Deduction

On Infinite Size. Bruno Whittle

Rethinking Knowledge: The Heuristic View

What would count as Ibn Sīnā (11th century Persia) having first order logic?

Belief as Defeasible Knowledge

TRUTH IN MATHEMATICS. H.G. Dales and G. Oliveri (eds.) (Clarendon: Oxford. 1998, pp. xv, 376, ISBN X) Reviewed by Mark Colyvan

Other Logics: What Nonclassical Reasoning Is All About Dr. Michael A. Covington Associate Director Artificial Intelligence Center

Truth and the Unprovability of Consistency. Hartry Field

Review of Philosophical Logic: An Introduction to Advanced Topics *

1 Introduction. Cambridge University Press Epistemic Game Theory: Reasoning and Choice Andrés Perea Excerpt More information

Quantificational logic and empty names

G. H. von Wright Deontic Logic

Artificial Intelligence Prof. P. Dasgupta Department of Computer Science & Engineering Indian Institute of Technology, Kharagpur

The Ontological Argument for the existence of God. Pedro M. Guimarães Ferreira S.J. PUC-Rio Boston College, July 13th. 2011

Williams on Supervaluationism and Logical Revisionism

Paradox of Deniability

Al-Sijistani s and Maimonides s Double Negation Theology Explained by Constructive Logic

Broad on Theological Arguments. I. The Ontological Argument

Evaluating Logical Pluralism

Language, Meaning, and Information: A Case Study on the Path from Philosophy to Science Scott Soames

Review of "The Tarskian Turn: Deflationism and Axiomatic Truth"

1. Lukasiewicz s Logic

Belief, Awareness, and Two-Dimensional Logic"

First- or Second-Order Logic? Quine, Putnam and the Skolem-paradox *

QUESTIONING GÖDEL S ONTOLOGICAL PROOF: IS TRUTH POSITIVE?

Circumscribing Inconsistency

Foundations of Non-Monotonic Reasoning

Here s a very dumbed down way to understand why Gödel is no threat at all to A.I..

Logic I or Moving in on the Monkey & Bananas Problem

Turing versus Gödel on Computability and the Mind

Jaakko Hintikka IF LOGIC MEETS PARACONSISTENT LOGIC

Why and how to be a Dialetheist

The Unbearable Lightness of Theory of Knowledge:

16. Universal derivation

Chapter 6. Fate. (F) Fatalism is the belief that whatever happens is unavoidable. (55)

Intuitive evidence and formal evidence in proof-formation

Spring CAS Department of Philosophy Graduate Courses

Introduction. September 30, 2011

MISSOURI S FRAMEWORK FOR CURRICULAR DEVELOPMENT IN MATH TOPIC I: PROBLEM SOLVING

Etchemendy, Tarski, and Logical Consequence 1 Jared Bates, University of Missouri Southwest Philosophy Review 15 (1999):

Bob Hale: Necessary Beings

Truth At a World for Modal Propositions

Can Negation be Defined in Terms of Incompatibility?

The Role of Logic in Philosophy of Science

Transcription:

Negative Introspection Is Mysterious Abstract. The paper provides a short argument that negative introspection cannot be algorithmic. This result with respect to a principle of belief fits to what we know about provability principles. Autoepistemic reasoning is reasoning the inferences of which depend on representing one s own state of belief. A cognitive agent engaged in autoepistemic reasoning draws conclusion from introspective beliefs. Such epistemic beliefs express that the cognitive agent has this and that non-epistemic beliefs. If agent a has the belief The cat is on the mat the introspective belief is I believe that the cat is on the mat or without self-representation It is believed that the cat is on the mat. Formally this can be expressed using epistemic modal operators like B (for belief). One question may be now, how much access and how reliable access some cognitive agent a has to its non-epistemic beliefs (typically called first order beliefs as they do not involve epistemic operators). Let B be the set of the agent s beliefs. An agent with ideal self-access or ideal introspective capacities may fulfil both of i) positive introspection: α B Bα B ii) negative introspection: α B ybα B Further on, the ideal agent may also fulfil some version of logical omniscience or deductive closure with respect to its first order and autoepistemic beliefs: iii) Nα Bα B iv) N(α γ), Bα B Bγ B 1

The principles of positive and negative introspection can also be expressed as principles of iterating epistemic modal operators 1 : v) positive introspection: Bα BBα vi) negative introspection: ybα ByBα One can now recognize that they are epistemic variants of the modal axioms characterising the alethic modal systems S4 and S5: vii) α α viii) α α [equivalent to y α y α which looks like (vi)] These are the stronger modal systems. Especially negative introspection seems to require that we believe of all sentences of the language that we have no corresponding belief iff we do not have such a belief. For technical systems (artificial cognitive agents) in contrast to human beings this might be feasible. If we consider a database, we may say that the facts stored in the database are its first order beliefs. A query is a form of introspective access. If the queried fact is stored the positive reply exhibits positive introspection, a negative reply exhibits negative introspection. But the databases we know are only finite fact storage, anyway, so the workings of the 1 The branch of epistemic logic expressing itself in this way is the 'classical' approach that treats epistemic attitudes like operators in alethic modal logic. This approach was inaugurated by Hintikka's pioneering works (Hintikka 1962), and a first comprehensive state of the art review was provided by Lenzen (1978). This approach has been heavily criticized as its rules and axioms (like logical omniscience and deductive closure) are seen by many as epistemologically and psychologically doubtful. Epistemic logic has thus developed into several other approaches and branches which use more recent logical tools like nonmonotonic logics or descriptive logics (cf. the various approaches in Laux/Wansing 1995). Nonetheless the classical approach is still alive, as witnessed by its prominent role in the recent textbook Epistemic Logic for AI and Computer Science (Meyer/van der Hoek 2004). Within philosophical logic classic epistemic modal logic often serves as starting point in investigating epistemic attitudes and concepts, as witnessed by the survey papers on epistemic logic in two recent companions to philosophical logic (cf. Goble 2001, Jacquette 2002). Therefore the issue raised in this paper here is still relevant, even more so as it seems to have gone largely unnoticed in the criticism of classic epistemic modal logic. 2

introspection principles seem unsuspicious. In the human case, where we tend to think of the mind as unbounded or at least as a capacity to infinitely many beliefs, the introspection principle are more controversial. Negative introspection looks even worse than positive introspection, especially when combined with deductive closure. Suppose introspection and closure: by recognising that you do not believe γ, but believe α, you will immediately know that γ does not follow from α (given your other beliefs as well)! As we ordinary humans also have false beliefs this does not amount to a decision procedure, but if some cognitive agent had no contingent beliefs at all, but fulfilled both the closure principles and the introspection principles (i.e. (i) (iv) above), that agent would constitute some kind of a decision procedure for any underlying logic, which should give as a pause. The procedure would be the following: The sentences of a language L are recursively enumerable (by some Turing machine M 1 ); for good measure the theorems of some undecidable logic expressed in L are recursively enumerable (by some Turing machine M 2 ). Let M 1 provide a sentence α. Check: Bα B? Either the sentence is believed or it is not the case that it is believed. Even if belief does not obey Excluded Middle (i.e. we may neither believe a sentence nor its negation), having a belief is not vague (i.e. obeys Excluded Middle: either we have a belief or we do not). If the sentence is believed, positive introspection tells us so. As, by assumption, the system has no contingent beliefs, but only beliefs delivered by the rule of logical omniscience, we now know that the sentence in question is a theorem. If the sentence is not believed, negative introspection tells us so. Again, as the rule of logical omniscience is the only belief generating rule in the system in question, we can contrapose (the sentence is not believed) and derive that the sentence is not a theorem. Thus the nontheorems are recursively enumerable as well. Any sentence can be decided as to its theoremhood. 3

This or negative introspection alone in combination with the workings of M 2 provides us for any sentence α with an answer whether in Nα or Pα. In case the logic contains Modus Ponens the closure principles have no more import than the theorems being recursively enumerable. The blame thus rests with negative not with positive introspection. This does not provide a decision procedure in the strict sense (and thus no refutation of or contradiction to the well-known undecidability theorems) as the checking procedure certainly is not algorithmic put otherwise: it cannot be algorithmic on pains of contradicting undecidability theorems. In so far as negative introspection is the crucial ingredient in this generic decision procedure negative introspection cannot be algorithmic. This puts doubt on the mere existence of negative introspection as a cognitive capacity. Once we endorse even mild or vague versions of functionalism we suppose that our cognitive and especially our logical/linguistic capacities are program-like. As we have just seen negative introspection cannot be of that kind. A would-be logical capacity of negative introspection is highly mysterious. We should rather forsake its assumption. The argument given above shows that our intuitive complaints against negative introspection can be vindicated by a proper strong argument. This result corresponds to well-known theorems in provability theory. If one takes the operator B to express provability, then positive introspection is the claim that if α is provable (α is a theorem) then it is provable that α is provable (it is a theorem that α is provable). The provability statement is a so-called ª 1 -statement (expressing the existential claim that there is a proof of α). Any formal system extending the basic arithmetic Q is ª 1 -complete. In such a system provability is not only expressible (by the operator or predicate), but is semi-representable, which means that that if it is true that α is provable it can be proven that α is provable. Thus this system fulfils positive introspection. Modal logics 4

of provability therefore incorporate the principle of positive introspection (i.e. the modal axiom characteristic of the system S4). Negative introspection, on the other hand, is a 1 -statement (expressing in the context of provability that all proofs are such that they do not prove α). Negative introspection thereby exhibits higher complexity than positive introspection. By Gödel s Second Incompleteness Theorem negative introspection (for provability) is not only not valid, but is always false, i.e. provability is at most semi-representable. If negative introspection had a true instance (for provability) that meant that for some unprovable α it is provable that α is not provable. But proving in a formal system for some formula of the system that it is unprovable in the system means proving the system s own consistency in the system, which is the very thing excluded by Gödel s Second Incompleteness Theorem. Modal logics of provability thus exclude the modal axiom characteristic of S5. To sum up: Negative introspection is unacceptable across the board. References Goble, Lou (2001) (Ed.). The Blackwell Guide to Philosophical Logic. Oxford. Hintikka, Jaakko (1962). Knowledge and Belief. Ithaca. Jacquette, Dale (2002) (Ed.) A Companion to Philosophical Logic. Oxford. Laux, Armin/Wansing, Heinrich (1995) (Eds.) Knowledge and Belief in Philosophy and Artificial Intelligence. Berlin. Lenzen, Wolfgang (1978). Recent Work in Epistemic Logic. Special Issue of Acta Philosophica Fennica, Vol. 30 (1). 5

Meyer, J.-J. Ch./van der Hoek, W. (2004). Epistemic Logic for AI and Computer Science. Cambridge. Manuel Bremer 6