Andrea Westlund, in Selflessness and Responsibility for Self, argues

Similar documents
Kant and his Successors

A Contractualist Reply

Freedom as Morality. UWM Digital Commons. University of Wisconsin Milwaukee. Hao Liang University of Wisconsin-Milwaukee. Theses and Dissertations

BOOK REVIEW: Gideon Yaffee, Manifest Activity: Thomas Reid s Theory of Action

Moral requirements are still not rational requirements

The Kripkenstein Paradox and the Private World. In his paper, Wittgenstein on Rules and Private Languages, Kripke expands upon a conclusion

HOW TO BE (AND HOW NOT TO BE) A NORMATIVE REALIST:

Testimony and Moral Understanding Anthony T. Flood, Ph.D. Introduction

Varieties of Apriority

Summary of Kant s Groundwork of the Metaphysics of Morals

What Lurks Beneath the Integrity Objection. Bernard Williams s alienation and integrity arguments against consequentialism have

Causing People to Exist and Saving People s Lives Jeff McMahan

In Epistemic Relativism, Mark Kalderon defends a view that has become

UC Berkeley UC Berkeley Previously Published Works

DISCUSSION THE GUISE OF A REASON

THE SENSE OF FREEDOM 1. Dana K. Nelkin. I. Introduction. abandon even in the face of powerful arguments that this sense is illusory.

Reasons With Rationalism After All MICHAEL SMITH

1/8. Reid on Common Sense

I will briefly summarize each of the 11 chapters and then offer a few critical comments.

The Conflict Between Authority and Autonomy from Robert Wolff, In Defense of Anarchism (1970)

Am I free? Free will vs. determinism

PHL340 Handout 8: Evaluating Dogmatism

3. Knowledge and Justification

Pictures, Proofs, and Mathematical Practice : Reply to James Robert Brown

On the Concept of a Morally Relevant Harm

Bad Luck Once Again. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research Vol. LXXVII No. 3, November 2008 Ó 2008 International Phenomenological Society

THE MORAL ARGUMENT. Peter van Inwagen. Introduction, James Petrik

2 FREE CHOICE The heretical thesis of Hobbes is the orthodox position today. So much is this the case that most of the contemporary literature

obey the Christian tenet You Shall Love The Neighbour facilitates the individual to overcome

Speaking My Mind: Expression and Self-Knowledge by Dorit Bar-On

On the epistemological status of mathematical objects in Plato s philosophical system

Stout s teleological theory of action

BCC Papers 5/2, May

A PROBLEM WITH DEFINING TESTIMONY: INTENTION AND MANIFESTATION:

Philosophical Issues, vol. 8 (1997), pp

ALTERNATIVE SELF-DEFEAT ARGUMENTS: A REPLY TO MIZRAHI

On the alleged perversity of the evidential view of testimony

part one MACROSTRUCTURE Cambridge University Press X - A Theory of Argument Mark Vorobej Excerpt More information

From the Categorical Imperative to the Moral Law

Reply to Brooke Alan Trisel James Tartaglia *

To link to this article:

THE FREEDOM OF THE WILL By Immanuel Kant From Critique of Pure Reason (1781)

Harman s Moral Relativism

Hume's Functionalism About Mental Kinds

ON PROMOTING THE DEAD CERTAIN: A REPLY TO BEHRENDS, DIPAOLO AND SHARADIN

Deontological Perspectivism: A Reply to Lockie Hamid Vahid, Institute for Research in Fundamental Sciences, Tehran

THE CONCEPT OF OWNERSHIP by Lars Bergström

Why Is Epistemic Evaluation Prescriptive?

Do we have knowledge of the external world?

Citation for the original published paper (version of record):

BonJour Against Materialism. Just an intellectual bandwagon?

What one needs to know to prepare for'spinoza's method is to be found in the treatise, On the Improvement

DORE CLEMENT DO THEISTS NEED TO SOLVE THE PROBLEM OF EVIL?

Commitment and Temporal Mediation in Korsgaard's Self-Constitution

My project in this paper is to reconsider the Kantian conception of practical reason. Some

CONVENTIONALISM AND NORMATIVITY

SUPPORT MATERIAL FOR 'DETERMINISM AND FREE WILL ' (UNIT 2 TOPIC 5)

Happiness and Personal Growth: Dial.

On Searle on Human Rights, Again! J. Angelo Corlett, San Diego State University

This is a collection of fourteen previously unpublished papers on the fit

Kant s Fundamental Principles of the Metaphysic of Morals

Well-Being, Time, and Dementia. Jennifer Hawkins. University of Toronto

Has Nagel uncovered a form of idealism?

Belief Ownership without Authorship: Agent Reliabilism s Unlucky Gambit against Reflective Luck Benjamin Bayer September 1 st, 2014

The Problem with Complete States: Freedom, Chance and the Luck Argument

TWO APPROACHES TO INSTRUMENTAL RATIONALITY

An Alternate Possibility for the Compatibility of Divine. Foreknowledge and Free Will. Alex Cavender. Ringstad Paper Junior/Senior Division

COPLESTON: Quite so, but I regard the metaphysical argument as probative, but there we differ.

Dworkin on the Rufie of Recognition

On David Chalmers's The Conscious Mind

Sidgwick on Practical Reason

Our Union With Christ A systematic study on the Doctrines of Grace

Instrumental reasoning* John Broome

DOES STRONG COMPATIBILISM SURVIVE FRANKFURT COUNTER-EXAMPLES?

Nested Testimony, Nested Probability, and a Defense of Testimonial Reductionism Benjamin Bayer September 2, 2011

FUNDAMENTAL PRINCIPLES OF THE METAPHYSIC OF MORALS. by Immanuel Kant

What is the "Social" in "Social Coherence?" Commentary on Nelson Tebbe's Religious Freedom in an Egalitarian Age

1/8. Descartes 3: Proofs of the Existence of God

Now consider a verb - like is pretty. Does this also stand for something?

REASONS AND REFLECTIVE ENDORSMENT IN CHRISTINE KORSGAARD S THE SOURCES OF NORMATIVITY ERIC C. BROWN. (Under the direction of Melissa Seymour-Fahmy)

The view that all of our actions are done in self-interest is called psychological egoism.

Wright on response-dependence and self-knowledge

Kant On The A Priority of Space: A Critique Arjun Sawhney - The University of Toronto pp. 4-7

God s Personal Freedom: A Response to Katherin Rogers

In this paper I offer an account of Christine Korsgaard s metaethical

R. Keith Sawyer: Social Emergence. Societies as Complex Systems. Cambridge University Press

A Review on What Is This Thing Called Ethics? by Christopher Bennett * ** 1

Phil 114, Wednesday, April 11, 2012 Hegel, The Philosophy of Right 1 7, 10 12, 14 16, 22 23, 27 33, 135, 141

Reply to Gauthier and Gibbard

Today we turn to the work of one of the most important, and also most difficult, philosophers: Immanuel Kant.

A theory of adjudication is a theory primarily about what judges do when they decide cases in courts of law.

Epistemic Responsibility in Science

Contemporary Theology I: Hegel to Death of God Theologies

THE NATURE OF NORMATIVITY IN KANT S PHILOSOPHY OF LOGIC REBECCA V. MILLSOP S

Wiley is collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to Philosophy & Public Affairs.

KNOWLEDGE ON AFFECTIVE TRUST. Arnon Keren

The Need for Metanormativity: A Response to Christmas

1999 Thomas W. Polger KRIPKE AND THE ILLUSION OF CONTINGENT IDENTITY. Thomas W. Polger. Department of Philosophy, Duke University.

270 Now that we have settled these issues, we should answer the first question [n.

Divine omniscience, timelessness, and the power to do otherwise

Transcription:

Aporia vol. 28 no. 2 2018 Phenomenology of Autonomy in Westlund and Wheelis Andrea Westlund, in Selflessness and Responsibility for Self, argues that for one to be autonomous or responsible for self one must hold oneself answerable... to external critical perspectives (495). For Westlund, holding oneself answerable is connected to one s ability to critically reflect and engage in justificatory dialogue. Westlund thinks her view improves on identificationalist views of autonomy because it can handle cases of self-abnegation, while identificationalist views cannot. This certainly seems true; however, I believe that it is not an inability to engage in justificatory dialogue that is fundamental to autonomy deficiency. I will argue, inspired by the writings of psychiatrist Allen Wheelis, that autonomy deficiency fundamentally results from the lack of a sort of prior phenomenological recognition of one s options as live options. I will show that there a space for my view of autonomy, whether or not Westlund herself would endorse it, is already present in her writing. I will show how, on my view, it is rather common that people are somehow autonomy deficient. I will finish by examining how this view relates to our moral intuitions about autonomy deficiency in general. I think that my view is useful for accounting for some of our intuitions but leaves some questions unanswered. is a senior at Brigham Young University and will graduate in April 2019 with a major in philosophy and minor in computer science. He plans to attend graduate school in 2020. His philosophical interests include phenomenology, agency, and identity.

26 1. What is Fundamental to Autonomy Westlund joins the conversation by rejecting accounts of autonomy (like those presented by Frankfurt and Bratman) on the grounds that they seem to be unable to account for our intuitions about cases of self abnegating deference. Self-abnegating deference is deference wherein even one s deliberation about one s reasons for action are deferential in nature. In contrast, one might defer to a party or interest for reasons of one s own which do not seem to conflict with autonomy. In such cases of prudential deference, an agent would be able to give self-referential reasons for one s deferential action. For example, one might say, I defer to my mother always, because I think she is wise and loves me. Therefore deference is good for me. In contrast, one who is self-abnegating in one s deference would only be able to give reasons for one s actions that are themselves deferential. In this circumstance, one would be unable to reference oneself or one s own interests when accounting for why one is doing what one is doing. Westlund gives the example of Thomas Hill s deferential wife (DW). She supposes that DW is talking with a friend about moving to Minneapolis (487). The move should be a problem for DW, but she has, as is her fashion, deferred the decision to her husband and decided to go. When asked why she is going, DW is only able to give answers such as, it is important to him [her husband], it really is a great career opportunity for him... I m sure he s thought it through, and I just know this is what he really wants and I just want him to have what he wants; that s all (487). DW is unable to tie any of the reasons behind her actions to anything but the interests of the person to whom she defers. Westlund calls this being deeply deferential (488). We see a similar problem in the devotedly religious person who defers to the objects of his religious convictions in a self-abnegating way. While neither religious belief nor cooperation are inherently problematic on most accounts, someone who is unable to tie their action to self-referencing reasons seems problematic. Identificationalist accounts of autonomy seem unable to account for our intuition that these sorts of cases are problematic. Frankfurt s account, for example, states that a person has first-order desires which have the potential to cause their actions and second-order volitions which are our desires about which of our first-order desires we wish to be effective. Thus, freedom of the will results when one s effective first-order desires equate the objects of one s second-order volitions (Frankfurt). However, it seems that both DW and our devoted acolyte (DA) would have second-order volitions directed at their deferential actions. It seems that both DW and DA can identify with their actions, or, in other words, would consider their actions

Phenomenology of Autonomy 27 as speaking for their true selves (Westlund 491). At very least, it seems that neither would suppose that they were acting in spite of themselves unless, in fact, they failed in their deferential role. Westlund suggests that, rather than identification, a particular sort of critical reflectiveness is necessary for someone to be autonomous. She writes that responsibility for self [is] a matter of holding oneself answerable... to external critical perspectives (495). When someone is not held answerable for some action, they are not responsible (from an observer s perspective) for that action. If someone, therefore, does not hold themselves answerable for an act, they are not holding themselves responsible for that act. Westlund later states that autonomy is self-responsibility and, therefore, is this ability to hold oneself answerable (498). I think that Westlund is thoroughly convincing in her reasoning to this point. However, I find it strange that she finally identifies willingness to engage in justificatory dialogue to real or imagined critics as fundamental to answerability (and therefore autonomy) rather than the view of things that must be prior to that willingness. She writes, standing in this sort of relationship to oneself both changes the way in which one experiences the demands of flesh-and-blood critics and makes possible a distinctive form of independent self-criticism (497). This seems correct, but standing in this sort of relationship to oneself seems to be more fundamental to autonomy than the actual experience of demands from critics (and certainly one s response to them). I think it is this standing in a specific sort of relationship to one s self that is fundamental to autonomy, and it happens to be the case that this ability always leads to one s being able and willing (in some sense) to engage in justificatory dialogue. 2. Phenomenology of Autonomy Westlund identifies some seemingly phenomenological requirements to one s being able to hold oneself answerable. I think there is room in her view for interpretation that, to be autonomous, one must, prior to some metaphysical ability to respond to justification questions, actually perceive one s responsibility in a matter in the right sort of way: Nonetheless, merely being capable of appropriate response does not yet amount to holding oneself answerable. One might be capable of appropriate response, and yet not be inclined to exercise this capability in the absence of material incentives to do so. One might fail to see (or perhaps to be moved by the thought) that an answer is owed. One might even have the cognitive skills and social sensitivities required to understand and

28 appreciate where answers are owed by others (and so have the generic concept of answerability), without feeling the normative force of demands for answers in one s own case. (496, emphasis added) It is a noteworthy consequence of this passage that someone might even have the thought of their ownership of a particular response but, if not moved by it, they are not holding themselves answerable for that response. In Westlund s account, this person is, therefore, neither self-responsible nor autonomous about the response in question. This seems to philosophically legitimize the view of psychiatrist Allen Wheelis in How People Change, that autonomy 1 Is the awareness of alternatives and of the ability to choose in the sense that someone who is self-abnegating is not aware that their actions are up to them in the way that someone who is not self abnegating is (Wheelis 15). Now, it is surely the case that DW or DA would be able to identify some sort of theoretical ownership of their deferential actions. If we were to ask DW who it was that moved with her husband to Minneapolis, she would almost certainly say, I did it. However, it seems that she is unable to see her choice in the matter. It is precisely to questions like, why did you not do something differently? that she has no real response. She is unwilling to engage in justificatory dialogue because she does not see, as we do, that she had a choice in the matter. Wheelis suggests that this sort of lack of autonomy is rampant and a part of everyday life for everyone. He breaks necessity down into two camps: objective and arbitrary. I take objective necessity to refer to things like the necessity of one s inability to fly through the atmosphere unaided. It is, roughly, that which we metaphysically have no say over. Gravity will pull us down, and the dead will remain dead despite our deepest wishes, I will feel pain in my hand if it is cut and my nerves are uninhibited. All of these outcomes seem objectively necessary. Arbitrary necessity, on the other hand derives from forces within the personality, but construed to be outside (Wheelis 25). Thus, we can see some things which are 1 Wheelis uses freedom, but in such a way that it seems reasonable to change the term to match Westlund s.

Phenomenology of Autonomy 29 metaphysically within our control as outside of our control. 2 For example, we do not typically decide, upon greeting any person, not to attack that person. It is metaphysically true that we could attack anyone we meet, but such a randomly violent act typically does not show up for most people as an option they must respond to. Wheelis writes, A kind man does not ponder becoming a sadist, an honest man does not consider whether to become a bandit; we prefer to have such matters settled, removed from choice and hence from freedom 3 (23). If we were to question our kind man why he has done something kind, he might initially be, in DW s style, bemused at the question. For him, that sort of act is simply what is done. Wheelis writes that the issue [of autonomy] is at the boundary of the self, the limits of the I or what we see as actually within our control (25). This is in-line with Westlund s statement that when we treat another person as autonomous (as her own representative) in ordinary reciprocal relations, we presuppose that she is disposed to treat her action-guiding commitments as her own responsibility (499). When we treat another person as autonomous, we do so because we suppose that they are aware of their ownership of alternatives, that thoughts of ownership are moving the person in the right way. Now, Wheelis kind man may come around to give us (or himself) a self referential reason for his actions (that is to say, he may succeed in engaging with us in justificatory dialogue) but he will first have been confronted with the phenomenological realization that his being a sadist is really up to him. Moreover, according to Wheelis and, it seems, Westlund he must actually be moved by the thought, rather than just having it as a theoretical option that one could verbally reference (Wheelis 26, Westlund 496). It is not the case, in short, that a kind man goes about 2 Something will need to be said, at some point, about determinism. I am explicitly avoiding the topic because I do not intend my argument to be a proof for or attack against determinism. However, the issues are wrapped up tightly with one another. What I mean here by metaphysical, as opposed to phenomenological, control should follow normative lines. The assumption of determinism would seem to make everything phenomenologically out of one s control also metaphysically out of one s control, assuming, as I contend, that the phenomenology of alternatives has some causal role. I do not think this makes this argument irrelevant to discussions that assume determinism is true. In such a case, phenomenological freedom would be the division of freedom that is affected by the laws of perception and introspection. 3 Another thing I find interesting here, though I will not go into it in this paper, is how these two examples of a sort of normal lack of autonomy are talked about in terms of roles that they fill. I suspect that, in taking on roles, we induce upon ourselves arbitrary necessity. As soon as I cease merely performing kind acts and instead become a kind man, the option of committing sadistic acts becomes, in a way, closed off for me. We see this same sort of thing in the case of Mr. Stevens, below.

30 each day making the straightforward decision in each circumstance not to be a sadist, rather he does not see that there is indeed a decision to be made and is therefore not really holding himself answerable for to his non-sadism (again, unless he is made to recognize his ownership). It would not even be so strange to suppose that the kind man could not be made to see his answerability in this case. In fact, I think that many people think of morals in this way. It is not the case that I do not kill because I see it as a personally offensive option and make the straightforward decision not to. Rather, unless I get myself to think in some morally strange ways, I do not see killing another person as a decision for me at all. Furthermore, in non-philosophical circles, an inability to give justificatory dialogue about morals can be seen as a good thing as long as the moral defended by that inability is generally agreed upon. If someone were to assert that killing is wrong, most would probably not follow up with why do you think that? 3. Autonomy as a Moral Responsibility Westlund writes that we expect, encourage, and even exhort others to take responsibility for themselves-to be their own persons, to think for themselves, to take charge of their own lives in a range of contexts that extend far beyond the narrowly moral in nature (497). However, it is actually strange to hold someone responsible for their own autonomy (or, in Westlund s terms, it is strange to hold someone responsible for their own responsibility). To conclude this paper, I will examine not whether we are autonomous in typically moral questions, but the moral obligation of autonomy itself. DW seems problematic because that which is arbitrarily necessary for her deference to her husband is strange to us. When we consider the kind and the honest, or even ourselves, it is perhaps interesting to us that these people are not always acting completely intentionally, but certainly not problematic because we suppose that they could easily be made to see their ownership of their actions. Even if we should consider one of those who could not be made to see their ownership (who was deeply deferential, for example, to the principle of kindness to the point that they could not question or justify it), we are not seriously perturbed because we do not see any problem for them or others if they are kind and honest. DW and DA, however, are different because it is possible for them to perform acts that seem morally wrong without being open to any sort of correction. These examples seem to be arguments that it is better to be autonomous than

Phenomenology of Autonomy 31 not. 4 Upon further reflection, however, it seems strange for us to expect, encourage, and even exhort others to take responsibility for themselves where this responsibility does not already exist. If one of the results of self abnegating deference is an inability to reflect and engage in justificatory dialogue critically, then it seems unlikely that somebody so afflicted would be able to ever change. If deep deference is a matter of [not] holding oneself answerable... to external critical perspectives one s own and those of others it does not really seem correctable (Westlund 495). If this is a sort of phenomenological lack, it does not seem that someone within the problem would be able to recognize as much. Our criticisms would seem analogous to exhortations to imagine a color one has never seen. Which leads us, finally, to the case of Kazuo Ishiguro s Mr. Stevens. In the novel, The Remains of the Day, Mr. Stevens is a butler reflecting on his service to Lord Darlington, a British nobleman and Nazi sympathizer during the period following the first world war. Mr. Stevens is extraordinarily deferential to Lord Darlington and, influenced by this deference, commits several socially reprehensible acts (including firing all of the Jewish staff at his employer s request) as well as some personally strange acts (such as missing his father s final moments in order to fulfill his role as a butler and likewise denying a genuine and significant romantic interest to fill similar duties) (Ishiguro 104 106, 147 150, 218 219). What is interesting about reading through Mr. Stevens story is the sense in which one feels both sorry for him and a little bit disappointed in him. In one sense, he seems less responsible for his actions because of the way he apparently perceives the world. On the other hand, one also feels that he ought to perceive the world differently. When, for example, he dismisses the Jewish servants, I tend to excuse Stevens from full responsibility (though not fully from responsibility) for this act. It seems that, as a profoundly deferential character, Stevens does not see the world in the same way as someone less deferential. Because of this, he is not making the same reprehensible decision that a less deferential character would have to make in order to perform the same actions, and therefore does not seem to be responsible in the same way (really, he is just committing a different action than someone without his deference would have to commit in order to bring about the same consequences). On the other hand, inasmuch as Stevens is responsible for his deference, he seems to have made a moral mistake. Yielding oneself up to the possibility 4 There are, however, arguments to the contrary. Wheelis, for example, suggests that we subject ourselves to arbitrary necessity in some cases so that we do not have to deal with the turmoil of making too many decisions, or internally feeling responsible for too much (28).

32 of being accessory to such (and perhaps more) moral wrongness seems to be a failure of moral judgment. 4. Conclusion I share Westlund s intuition that self-abnegating deference is a case of a lack of autonomy. Because identificationalist accounts cannot account for this lack of autonomy, there is something deficient, either in their account or our intuition about deference. Westlund does a marvelous job of describing why someone who is deeply deferential is unfree. However, I think that her assertion that one s willingness to engage in justificatory dialogue about an action constitutes their autonomy, while correlatively true, does not identify that which is absolutely fundamental to autonomy. I have proposed the view that phenomenological perception of one s ownership (or, in other words, of alternatives that are actually live options) is that which constitutes one s ability to engage in justificatory dialogue and, therefore, that which actually constitutes autonomy. About her view, Westlund writes, One might even suggest that there are simply two different senses of autonomy in play here self governance of choice and action, on the one hand, which may be captured by the structural accounts offered by identificationalists, and self-representation in justificatory dialogue, on the other, which may be captured instead by an account centered on the attitude of responsibility for self. My own view is that these two forms of autonomy are deeply linked or, more precisely, that one s autonomy as a chooser and actor is partly constituted by one s readiness to engage in justificatory dialogue about the commitments that guide one s choices and actions. (500) I suggest (although I cannot now say for sure) that by going deeper than justificatory dialogue into its phenomenological basis, we may find a bridge between these two senses of autonomy. I also discussed the mystery of one s responsibility for self-autonomy. I mainly identified some intuitions about deference and drew no definitive conclusions. I think that more work needs to be done before we can say how morally reprehensible DW, DA, and Mr. Stevens are for the way in which they are submissive. What needs to be identified is if an agent can be responsible for their own lack of self-responsibility, how self-abnegating deference comes about, and what the historical difference is between a self abnegatingly deferential agent and one who is deferential in another way.

Works Cited Frankfurt, Harry G. Freedom of the Will and the Concept of a Person. The Journal of Philosophy, vol. 68, no. 1, 1971, pp. 5 20. Ishiguro, Kazuo. The Remains of the Day. Vintage International, 1993. Westlund, Andrea C. Selflessness and Responsibility for Self: Is Deference Compatible with Autonomy? The Philosophical Review, vol. 112, no. 4, 2003, pp. 483 523. Wheelis, Allen. How People Change. Harper Colophon, 1975.