FACING JUDICIAL DISCRETION

Similar documents
Law and Philosophy Library

THE APOLOGETIC VALUE OF HUMAN HOLINESS

ART, EDUCATION, AND THE DEMOCRATIC COMMITMENT

INSTITUTIONAL LEGAL FACTS

STUDIES IN PHILOSOPHY AND RELIGION

A HUNDRED YEARS OF ENGLISH PHILOSOPHY

PHENOMENOLOGICAL ASPECTS OF WITTGENSTEIN'S PHILOSOPHY

WHOLES. SUMS AND UNITIES

The Challenge of Religious Discrimination at the. Dawn of the New Millennium

PHILOSOPHICAL LOGIC AND LOGICAL PHILOSOPHY

KNOWLEDGE AND DEMONSTRATION

THE CONCEPT OF GOD, THE ORIGIN OF THE WORLD, AND THE IMAGE OF THE HUMAN IN THE WORLD RELIGIONS

Managing Editor: Editors:

Positivism A Model Of For System Of Rules

Legal positivism represents a view about the nature of law. It states that

Constructive Logic, Truth and Warranted Assertibility

Faith, Philosophy and the Reflective Muslim

Ethics in Cyberspace

Is Klein an infinitist about doxastic justification?

SYNTHESE HISTORICAL LIBRARY

BETWEEN HISTORY AND METHOD

IMAGINATION AND REFLECTION: INTERSUBJECTIVITY FICHTE'S: GRUNDLAGE OF 1794

* Dalhousie Law School, LL.B. anticipated Interpretation and Legal Theory. Andrei Marmor Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1992, 193 pp.

INQUIRY AS INQUIRY: A LOGIC OF SCIENTIFIC DISCOVERY

5AANA009 Epistemology II 2014 to 2015

EPISTEME. Editor: MARIO BUNGE Foundations and Philosophy of Science Unit, McGill University. Advisory Editorial Board:

Received: 30 August 2007 / Accepted: 16 November 2007 / Published online: 28 December 2007 # Springer Science + Business Media B.V.

The Philosophical Review, Vol. 100, No. 3. (Jul., 1991), pp

PROFILES EDITORS EDITORIAL BOARD. RADU J. BOGDAN, Tulane University ILKKA NIINILUOTO, University of Helsinki VOLUME 4

Right-Making, Reference, and Reduction

THE LOGIC OF INVARIABLE CONCOMITANCE IN THE TATTVACINTĀMANI

HENRY E. KYBURG, JR. & ISAAC LEVI

TYPES, TABLEAUS, AND GODEL' S GOD

Speaking My Mind: Expression and Self-Knowledge by Dorit Bar-On

xiv Truth Without Objectivity

Muhammad Haniff Hassan CIVIL DISOBEDIENCE IN ISLAM. A Contemporary Debate

-- The search text of this PDF is generated from uncorrected OCR text.

Brian Leiter (ed), Objectivity in Law and Morals, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2001, xi pp, hb

Studies in Brain and Mind

International Institute of Philosophy Institut International de Philo sophie

Boston Studies in Philosophy, Religion and Public Life

Reason and Explanation: A Defense of Explanatory Coherentism. BY TED POSTON (Basingstoke,

COHERENTISM AS A FOUNDATION FOR ETHICAL DIALOG AND EVALUATION. Coherentism as a Foundation for Ethical Dialog and Evaluation in School

AN INSTITUTIONAL THEORY OF LAW

THESES SIS/LIBRARY TELEPHONE:

Could There Have Been Nothing?

Naturalized Epistemology. 1. What is naturalized Epistemology? Quine PY4613

CBT and Christianity

Gary Ebbs, Carnap, Quine, and Putnam on Methods of Inquiry, Cambridge. University Press, 2017, 278pp., $99.99 (hbk), ISBN

Unit VI: Davidson and the interpretational approach to thought and language

Education, Democracy, and the Moral Life

Heidegger s Interpretation of Kant

Also by Nafsika Athanassoulis. Also by Samantha Vice

In Defense of Pure Reason: A Rationalist Account of A Priori Justification, by Laurence BonJour. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press,

NEW PERSPECTIVES IN SOCIOLOGY

Faults and Mathematical Disagreement

Münster Lectures in Philosophy

EMPIRICISM AND DARWIN'S SCIENCE

ON CAUSAL AND CONSTRUCTIVE MODELLING OF BELIEF CHANGE

Juan Alberto del Real Alcalá*

Mindfulness and Acceptance in Couple and Family Therapy

Oxford Scholarship Online Abstracts and Keywords

THE EVENT OF DEATH: A PHENOMENOLOGICAL ENQUIRY

Jeu-Jenq Yuann Professor of Philosophy Department of Philosophy, National Taiwan University,

1. The basic idea is to look at "what the courts do in fact" (Holmes, 1897). What does this mean?

The Oxford Handbook of Epistemology

Marxism and Criminological Theory

Literature, Philosophy, Nihilism

The Afterlife of Idealism

CONVENTIONALISM AND NORMATIVITY

THE ENLIGHTENMENT PROJECT IN THE ANALYTIC CONVERSATION

PHENOMENOLOGICAL METHOD: THEORY AND PRACTICE

Early Muslim Polemic against Christianity Abu Isa al-warraq s Against the Incarnation

THE RIGHTS OF WOMEN IN ISLAM

Developing Christian Servant Leadership

Legal Positivism: the Separation and Identification theses are true.

A Critical Study of Hans Küng s Ecclesiology

Kant s Practical Philosophy

ADAM SMITH'S THEORY OF VALUE AND DISTRIBUTION

PHILOSOPHY OF RELIGION A-Z

EDUCATION AND CIVILIZATION

Freedom's Law: The Moral Reading of the American Constitution.

LAW, ORDER AND FREEDOM

Jan Narveson, Pacifism: A. Philosophical Examination 1

Relativism and Indeterminacy of Meaning (Quine) Indeterminacy of Translation

THE PHILOSOPHY OF RIGHT AND LEFT

Experience and Foundationalism in Audi s The Architecture of Reason

NATURALIZING EPISTEMIC VIRTUE

DISPUTED QUESTIONS IN THEOLOGY AND THE PHILOSOPHY OF RELIGION

Critical Scientific Realism

LOGIC, EPISTEMOLOGY, AND THE UNITY OF SCIENCE

THESES SIS/LIBRARY TELEPHONE:

IDEOLOGY AND SOCIAL SCIENCE

Protestant Catholic Conflict from the Reformation to the Twenty-first Century

foundationalism and coherentism are responses to it. I will then prove that, although

Why Legal Positivism?

Précis of Democracy and Moral Conflict

Moral Twin Earth: The Intuitive Argument. Terence Horgan and Mark Timmons have recently published a series of articles where they

Library of Exact Philosophy. Editor: Mario Bunge, Montreal

Are There Reasons to Be Rational?

Transcription:

FACING JUDICIAL DISCRETION

Law and Philosophy Library VOLUME 49 Managing Editors FRANCISCO J. LAPORTA, Department of Law, Autonomous University of Madrid, Spain ALEKSANDER PECZENIK, Department of Law, University of Lund, Sweden FREDERICK SCHAUER, John F. Kennedy School of Government, Harvard University, Cambridge, Mass., U.S.A. Former Managing Editors AULIS AARNIO, MICHAEL D. BAYLESt, CONRAD D. JOHNSONt, ALANMABE Editorial Advisory Board AULIS AARNIO, Research Institute for Social Sciences, University oftampere, Finland ZENON BANKOWSKY, Centre for Criminology and the Social and Philosophical Study of Law, University of Edinburgh PAOLO COMANDUCCI, University of Genua, Italy ERNESTO GARZ6N VALDES, Institutfiir Politikwissenschaft, Johannes Gutenberg Universitiit Mainz JOHN KLEINIG, Department of Law, Police Science and Criminal Justice Administration, John Jay College of Criminal Justice, City University of New York NEIL MacCORMICK, European Parliament, Brussels, Belgium WOJCIECH SADURSKI, European University Institute, Department of Law, Florence, Italy ROBERT S. SUMMERS, School of Law, Cornell University CARL WELLMAN, Department of Philosophy, Washington University The titles published in this series are listed at the end a/this volume.

FACING JUDICIAL DISCRETION Legal Knowledge and Right Answers Revisited by MARISA IGLESIAS VILA Professor of Legal Theory, Department of Legal, Moral and Political Philosophy, Pompeu Fabra University, Barcelona, Spain, SPRINGER-SCIENCE+BUSINESS MEDIA, B.V.

A c.r.p. Catalogue record for this book is available from the Library of Congress. ISBN 978-90-481-5637-5 ISBN 978-94-015-9684-8 (ebook) DOI 10.1007/978-94-015-9684-8 English translation of EI problema de la discreci6n judicial. Una aproximaci6n al conocimiento juridico, Centro de Estudios Politicos y Constitucionales, Madrid, 1999, translated by S.C. Mendlewicz. Printed an acid-free paper AII Rights Reserved 2001 Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht Originally published by Kluwer Academic Publishers in 2001 Softcover reprint ofthe hardcover Ist edition 2001 No part of the material protected by this copyright notice may be reproduced or utilized in any form or by any means, electronic or mechanical, inciuding photocopying, recording or by any information storage and retrieval system, without written permission from the copyright owner.

For Nuri Vila, the noblest dreamer

TABLE OF CONTENTS ACKNOWLEDGEMENTS xi INTRODUCTION Xlll CHAPTER 1: THE CONCEPT OF rudicial DISCRETION 1.1 Introduction 1.2 Uses of 'discretion' 1.2.1 Senses of judicial discretion 1.3 Strong discretion 1.3.1 The context of strong discretion 1.3.2 Discretion as choice 1.3.3 Open alternatives Semantic problems Legal gaps Normative contradiction 1.3.4 The zone of reasonableness 1.3.5 The demand for justification 1.3.6 Having discretion and exercising discretion 1.4 Weak discretion 1.4.1 An approach to weak discretion 1.4.2 A further approach to weak discretion 3 4 8 8 9 12 14 21 23 24 26 29 32 32 34 CHAPTER 2: THE STRONG DISCRETION MODEL 2.1 Introduction 2.2 A first look at the strong discretion model 2.3 Simple and sophisticated positivism 2.4 Judicial discretion and hartian positivism 2.4.1 The law-communication thesis 2.4.2 Hartian semantics Meaning as settled use: easy cases 37 39 40 43 43 45 46

viii TABLE OF CONTENTS Particular and social contexts of u~e Indexicality and social conventions Rule-following 2.4.3 No right answer: hard cases Hard cases and legal interpretation Antirealism and semantic indeterminacy 2.5 Final remarks 47 50 56 66 69 70 74 CHAPTER 3: THE WEAK DISCRETION MODEL 3.1 Introduction 3.2 Legal theory and normative adjudication 3.3 Law as interpretation 3.3.1 The semantic sting 3.3.2 Constructive interpretation Concept and conception The interpretive concept Conceptions of the concept Stages of constructive interpretation 3.3.3 The chain novel 3.4 Law as integrity 3.4.1 Integrity as a legal virtue 3.5 Final remarks 77 78 81 81 85 88 88 92 93 96 98 100 103 CHAPTER 4: INTERPRETATION VERSUS INVENTION 4.1 Introduction 108 4.2 Notions of interpretation 109 4.3 Are we interpreting or inventing? 113 4.3.1 The controversy Dworkin - Fish 115 4.3.2 Internal objectivity 119 4.3.3 Constraints to interpretation: the structure ofa conceptual scheme 125 4.4 Quine's episternic holism 127 4.5 Davidson's episternic coherentism 130 4.6 Final remarks 136

TABLE OF CONTENTS ix CHAPTER 5: COHERENCE IN LEGAL INTERPRETA non 5.1 Introduction 5.2 Truth, assertability and coherence 5.2.1 Coherentism as an epistemic theory, and as a theory of truth Constitutive coherence and epistemic coherence Back to the point 5.3 The theory of truth as coherence 5.3.1 Coherence and complexity Coherence in the justification of beliefs From justification to truth-assertability 5.4 Coherence in legal interpretation 5.4.1 Interpretive adjudication of norms 5.4.2 Authority and coherence 5.4.3 Coherence and the normative'dimension oflaw 5.5 Right legal answers and strong discretion 5.5.1 Incommensurability 5.5.2 Tie between interpretations 138 139 142 142 145 147 148 148 153 160 160 162 166 170 171 174 CHAPTER 6: HARD CASES AND LEGAL DETERMINACY 6.1 Introduction 6.2 The sceptical challenge 6.3 Justifiying semantic indeterminacy 6.4 Rule-following and the internal relationship 6.5 Agreement, disagreement, and right answers 6.6 Final remarks 178 181 186 191 199 204 BIBLIOGRAPHY INDEX 206 221

ACKNOWLEDGEMENTS This book began life as a doctoral thesis, submitted at the Universitat Pompeu Fabra, Barcelona, in 1997, which I completed thanks to the financial support of the Generalitat de Catalunya. It is the result of several years of study, reflection, and persistency with ideas that only hesitantly assent to leave darkness. Special thanks are due to all those who made its publication possible both in its Spanish as well as in its English version, in particular, to the managing editors of Centro de Estudios Politicos y Constitucionales and Kluwer Academic Publishers. I am grateful to the translator, S. C. Mendlewicz, for her work and for the long hours of detailed discussion. Her observations have helped me clarify a number of points. Intellectual activity is not the product of mere individual effort. Philosophy benefits markedly from hard questions, criticism and discussion. I have greatly benefited from the intellectual atmosphere I was privileged to enjoy at the Department of Legal Philosphy of the Universitat Pompeu Fabra. I wish to express my gratitude to its director and my supervisor, Albert Calsamiglia, who provided not only the support, which means so much, but constant guidance and invaluable criticism from the beginning to the end. His striking ability to create a fruitful environment for philosophical exchange afforded me a unique opportunity to meet and learn from thinkers such as Ernesto Garz6n Valdes, Carlos Santiago Nino, and Eugenio Bulygin. I am deeply indebted to Jose Juan Moreso, Ricardo Caracciolo, Cristina Redondo and Maribel Narvaez for the many stimulating and fruitful discussions on the issues addressed in this book, and for reading and commenting upon large portions of earlier drafts. Their incisive criticism and fine observations have led to many improvements. Many thanks must go to Jordi Ferrer, Josep Maria Vilajosana, Teresa Pascual, Jose Luis Perez Trivifio, Jorge Malem, Pablo Navarro, Daniel Mendonca, Roberto Gargarella, and Victor Ferreres for their patience and encouragement. I have been the grateful recipient of their suggestions in developing the ideas in this book. Most importantly, I have had the pleasure of sharing with them my passion for philosophical inquiry. I wish to thank Neus Torbisco, and all my friends for their unfailing support. They have been wise to remind me the other strands in my life during the difficult moments in the writing of this book. And, of course, I shall not forget to mention Africa. Finally, and most of all, my everlasting gratitude goes to my parents and sisters, Cristina and Elisabeth, without whose affection, warmth and generosity this book would never have seen the light of day.

INTRODUCTION In response to ETA's 1997 kidnappings and murders thousands of Spaniards attended mass demonstrations to express their contempt for violence as a means of political pressure. The demand that public authorities prosecute and condemn those who directly or indirectly support ETA and its terrorist attacks was one of the most prevalent slogans in the marches. Indeed, the social response was aimed not only against the terrorist group, but also against Herri Batasuna (HB), the political party that openly endorse ETA's armed actions in the Basque Country. From the legal point of view, it is interesting to examine what it is citizens are requesting from the government in the above-mentioned case. How do these collective claims translate into legal language? One may think it fit to answer that Spanish citizens want violence to be met with the institutional punishment prescribed by the legal order. Nonetheless, it could also be argued that citizens in fact demand that certain kinds of behaviour be regulated by the law in their country. While from the latter viewpoint citizens wish for the creation of new legal norms, from the former they are just calling for the application of the law. What reasons may render us inclined to sympathise with one of these two views rather than the other? Which one of these two options is most appropriate? At first sight, this may appear to be a simple question. Answering it requires no more than consulting the normative texts and determining what is prescribed by the Spanish law with regard to this point. If it is the case that support to terrorism falls into a delictive category, citizens just claim an effective application of the law. Otherwise, they are demanding that a new criminal figure be created. However, there is more to it than that. Let us inquire about what would make support to terrorism a legally regulated action. The literal meaning of normative texts is usually malleable. How would otherwise members of HB have eluded convictions of an offence of conniving at terrorist acts by expressing approval of them, or co-operating with armed terrorist organisations? Precisely the legal qualification of the conduct of HB's members has been widely debated in connection to the limits of free speech, and the room for political action as a sign of democratic pluralism. Thus, the answer to which alternative better describes citizens claims against the support of violence is not obvious at all - it very much depends on the conception of law we choose to embrace;

xiv INTRODUCTION but law is a dynamical social practice that involves argument and discussion, and in which interaction is driven by some specific purpose. We know what law is when we are able to account for this complex social practice. This book is an attempt to address this issue from an epistemic point of view. I will explore some of the assumptions that account for particular conclusions of certain legal theories about which behaviours are legally regulated. My discussion will develop in the context of legal adjudication. Over the last few decades, legal philosophy has paid much attention to the analysis of judicial reasoning. This has proven an interesting starting point to explore questions of a wider scope such as what is law, how do we come to know it, and what are its limits. For this reason, investigating judicial discretion and legal interpretation will ultimately enable us to identify some of the elements that a view of law should incorporate to warrant its viability. The main question I will attempt to answer to is how to ensure the existence of objectively right legal answers. With a view to doing so, I will investigate some of the difficulties encountered by a theory of the truth conditions of legal propositions that assumes, at least, partial legal determinacy. I will suggest an answer along the lines of Dworkin's theory, the thesis of internal objectivity, as to how to justify the existence of right legal answers, and yet avoid falling into semantic realism. Moreover, I will hint at reasons that prevent the determinacy of law in all cases. The first chapter outlines the different meanings ascribed to the expression 'judicial discretion' in the context of legal theory. The features of each one of these uses are described and particular attention is paid to weak and strong discretion. Each of these two uses of discretion yields a separate model about what is law and how it is identified. In the second chapter, the 'strong discretion model', mainly endorsed by Hartian positivism, is introduced. The distinguishing features of this model can be summarised in the four postulates: I) the thesis of the social sources of law; II) law as communication; III) meaning as settled use; and IV) the partial indeterminacy of law. The purpose of an analysis of these theses is to show the difficulties met by Hartian positivism and its conventionalist semantics to overcome the sceptical challenge of rulefollowing without falling into semantic realism. Additionally, I point to certain deficiencies in the justification of the positivist claim that semantic disagreement necessarily leads to legal indeterminacy. The third chapter is devoted to an analysis of what I shall call 'the weak discretion model', whose chief exponent is Ronald Dworkin. I develop three aspects of this theory of law: I) the relationship between legal theory and normative adjudication; II) the interpretive view of law; and III) law as integrity or narrative coherence. The purpose of

INTRODUCTION xv this chapter is to illuminate the epistemic assumptions of Dworkin's theory and to point to the main objection that can be pressed against his model, namely how to justify optimism about the possibility of eliminating the need for strong discretion in adjudication. The starting point of the fourth chapter is the idea that every theory supportive of the existence of right legal answers ought to account for the distinction between interpretation and invention. The ultimate goal of this chapter is to provide an answer as to how to draw this distinction objectively and simultaneously avoid externalism or semantic realism. To this end, I set forth the epistemic grounds of the interpretive theory of law and evince the advantages of such an approach over Quine's holism and Davidson's epistemic coherentism. This leads to the conclusion that the best way to distinguish between invention and interpretation is by adopting a theory of truth as assertability for legal statements in line with Putnam's internal realism. The purpose of the fifth chapter is to advocate a theory of truth as assertability that adopts coherence as the criterion to determine what it is we are entitled to assert. I consider coherence as a property and as a relationship. Moreover, as far as coherence as a relationship is concerned, I distinguish between vertical and horizontal coherence. My claim here is that for a coherentist theory to avoid both foundationalism and a too strict form of holism it should take into account vertical and horizontal coherence, as suggested by the idea of reflective equilibrium. I argue that coherence within a complex interpretive scheme can warrant legal determinacy, albeit only partially. Thus, although judges always require a weak form of discretion when they adjudicate norms, there is evidence to support the need for strong discretion in the resolution of certain cases. Finally, Chapter 6 relates the postulates of Hartian positivism to those of Dworkin's theory, and shows their differences and similarities. I favour Dworkin's view on the grounds of its epistemic accessibility and its higher explanatory output. I specifically stress that Dworkin's position permits a viable strategy to overcome the problem of rulefollowing, and distinguish interpretation from invention. This leads to the conclusion that legal indeterminacy does not necessarily follow from semantic disagreement.