philippine studies Ateneo de Manila University Loyola Heights, Quezon City 1108 Philippines

Similar documents
Selections from Aristotle s Prior Analytics 41a21 41b5

SYLLOGISTIC LOGIC CATEGORICAL PROPOSITIONS

MCQ IN TRADITIONAL LOGIC. 1. Logic is the science of A) Thought. B) Beauty. C) Mind. D) Goodness

7. Some recent rulings of the Supreme Court were politically motivated decisions that flouted the entire history of U.S. legal practice.

Chapter 9- Sentential Proofs

Based on the translation by E. M. Edghill, with minor emendations by Daniel Kolak.

Ayer on the criterion of verifiability

Semantic Entailment and Natural Deduction

Logic: Deductive and Inductive by Carveth Read M.A. CHAPTER IX CHAPTER IX FORMAL CONDITIONS OF MEDIATE INFERENCE

Verificationism. PHIL September 27, 2011

John Buridan. Summulae de Dialectica IX Sophismata

Posterior Analytics. By Aristotle. Based on the translation by G. R. G. Mure, with minor emendations by Daniel Kolak. BOOK I.

On Interpretation. Section 1. Aristotle Translated by E. M. Edghill. Part 1

THE FORM OF REDUCTIO AD ABSURDUM J. M. LEE. A recent discussion of this topic by Donald Scherer in [6], pp , begins thus:

Semantic Foundations for Deductive Methods

Anthony P. Andres. The Place of Conversion in Aristotelian Logic. Anthony P. Andres

Fr. Copleston vs. Bertrand Russell: The Famous 1948 BBC Radio Debate on the Existence of God

Logic: Deductive and Inductive by Carveth Read M.A. CHAPTER VI CONDITIONS OF IMMEDIATE INFERENCE

5: Preliminaries to the Argument

Informalizing Formal Logic

c Peter King, 1987; all rights reserved. WILLIAM OF OCKHAM: ORDINATIO 1 d. 2 q. 6

The Development of Laws of Formal Logic of Aristotle

Artificial Intelligence: Valid Arguments and Proof Systems. Prof. Deepak Khemani. Department of Computer Science and Engineering

Aristotle on the Principle of Contradiction :

How Do We Know Anything about Mathematics? - A Defence of Platonism

The Ontological Argument for the existence of God. Pedro M. Guimarães Ferreira S.J. PUC-Rio Boston College, July 13th. 2011

The Appeal to Reason. Introductory Logic pt. 1

First Principles. Principles of Reality. Undeniability.

Study Guides. Chapter 1 - Basic Training

2. Refutations can be stronger or weaker.

1/5. The Critique of Theology

Bertrand Russell Proper Names, Adjectives and Verbs 1

Vol 2 Bk 7 Outline p 486 BOOK VII. Substance, Essence and Definition CONTENTS. Book VII

Rationalist-Irrationalist Dialectic in Buddhism:

IS THE SYLLOGISTIC A LOGIC? it is not a theory or formal ontology, a system concerned with general features of the

Introduction. I. Proof of the Minor Premise ( All reality is completely intelligible )

Revisiting the Socrates Example

2.1 Review. 2.2 Inference and justifications

The Problem of Major Premise in Buddhist Logic

Aspects of Western Philosophy Dr. Sreekumar Nellickappilly Department of Humanities and Social Sciences Indian Institute of Technology, Madras

Alvin Plantinga addresses the classic ontological argument in two

McCLOSKEY ON RATIONAL ENDS: The Dilemma of Intuitionism

What would count as Ibn Sīnā (11th century Persia) having first order logic?

On The Logical Status of Dialectic (*) -Historical Development of the Argument in Japan- Shigeo Nagai Naoki Takato

Logic clearly dictates that the needs of the many outweigh the needs of the few or the needs of the one (Spock and Captain Kirk).

Does the Third Man Argument refute the theory of forms?

1 Clarion Logic Notes Chapter 4

Who or what is God?, asks John Hick (Hick 2009). A theist might answer: God is an infinite person, or at least an

1/6. The Resolution of the Antinomies

16. Universal derivation

Tutorial A03: Patterns of Valid Arguments By: Jonathan Chan

5.3 The Four Kinds of Categorical Propositions

Remarks on a Foundationalist Theory of Truth. Anil Gupta University of Pittsburgh

Broad on Theological Arguments. I. The Ontological Argument

Aquinas' Third Way Modalized

3.3. Negations as premises Overview

Can logical consequence be deflated?

William Ockham on Universals

(1) A phrase may be denoting, and yet not denote anything; e.g., 'the present King of France'.

Plato's Parmenides and the Dilemma of Participation

CHAPTER III. Of Opposition.

THREE LOGICIANS: ARISTOTLE, SACCHERI, FREGE

Spinoza, Ethics 1 of 85 THE ETHICS. by Benedict de Spinoza (Ethica Ordine Geometrico Demonstrata) Translated from the Latin by R. H. M.

Logic: Deductive and Inductive by Carveth Read M.A. Questions

Illustrating Deduction. A Didactic Sequence for Secondary School

Ramsey s belief > action > truth theory.

Concerning God Baruch Spinoza

Lecture Notes on Classical Logic

KANT'S PROLEGOMENA TO ANY FUTURE METAPHYSICS CHICAGO DR. PAUL CARUS THE OPEN COURT PUBLISHING COMPANY

ILLOCUTIONARY ORIGINS OF FAMILIAR LOGICAL OPERATORS

Dr. Carlo Alvaro Reasoning and Argumentation Distribution & Opposition DISTRIBUTION

KANT, MORAL DUTY AND THE DEMANDS OF PURE PRACTICAL REASON. The law is reason unaffected by desire.

Chapter 5: Freedom and Determinism

Reductio ad Absurdum, Modulation, and Logical Forms. Miguel López-Astorga 1

MITOCW Lec 2 MIT 6.042J Mathematics for Computer Science, Fall 2010

Quaerens Deum: The Liberty Undergraduate Journal for Philosophy of Religion

Chapter 3: More Deductive Reasoning (Symbolic Logic)

C. Exam #1 comments on difficult spots; if you have questions about this, please let me know. D. Discussion of extra credit opportunities

Am I free? Freedom vs. Fate

The Sea-Fight Tomorrow by Aristotle

But we may go further: not only Jones, but no actual man, enters into my statement. This becomes obvious when the statement is false, since then

1/12. The A Paralogisms

Exercise Sets. KS Philosophical Logic: Modality, Conditionals Vagueness. Dirk Kindermann University of Graz July 2014

On Some Themes in Parmenides

The Ethics. Part I and II. Benedictus de Spinoza ************* Introduction

Is the Existence of the Best Possible World Logically Impossible?

Philosophy of Mathematics Nominalism

LOGIC ANTHONY KAPOLKA FYF 101-9/3/2010

Introduction to Philosophy

Day 3. Wednesday May 23, Learn the basic building blocks of proofs (specifically, direct proofs)

Logic Appendix: More detailed instruction in deductive logic

Can Negation be Defined in Terms of Incompatibility?

10.3 Universal and Existential Quantifiers

Durham Research Online

philippine studies Ateneo de Manila University Loyola Heights, Quezon City 1108 Philippines Philippine Studies vol. 22, no. 3-4 (1974)

On the Aristotelian Square of Opposition

What is the Nature of Logic? Judy Pelham Philosophy, York University, Canada July 16, 2013 Pan-Hellenic Logic Symposium Athens, Greece

CRITICAL THINKING (CT) MODEL PART 1 GENERAL CONCEPTS

CHAPTER 2 THE LARGER LOGICAL LANDSCAPE NOVEMBER 2017

Baruch Spinoza. Demonstrated in Geometric Order AND. III. Of the Origin and Nature of the Affects. IV. Of Human Bondage, or the Power of the Affects.

Transcription:

philippine studies Ateneo de Manila University Loyola Heights, Quezon City 1108 Philippines Some Historical Applications of the Method of Indirect Proof Thomas J. O Shaugnessy, S.J. Philippine Studies vol. 19, no. 4 (1971): 593 603 Copyright Ateneo de Manila University Philippine Studies is published by the Ateneo de Manila University. Contents may not be copied or sent via email or other means to multiple sites and posted to a listserv without the copyright holder s written permission. Users may download and print articles for individual, noncommercial use only. However, unless prior permission has been obtained, you may not download an entire issue of a journal, or download multiple copies of articles. Please contact the publisher for any further use of this work at philstudies@admu.edu.ph. http://www.philippinestudies.net Fri June 30 13:30:20 2008

philippine studies Ateneo de Manila University Loyola Heights, Quezon City 1108 Philippines Some Historical Applications of the Method of Indirect Proof Thomas J. O Shaugnessy, S.J. Philippine Studies vol. 19, no. 4 (1971): 593 603 Copyright Ateneo de Manila University Philippine Studies is published by the Ateneo de Manila University. Contents may not be copied or sent via email or other means to multiple sites and posted to a listserv without the copyright holder s written permission. Users may download and print articles for individual, noncommercial use only. However, unless prior permission has been obtained, you may not download an entire issue of a journal, or download multiple copies of articles. Please contact the publisher for any further use of this work at philstudies@admu.edu.ph. http://www.philippinestudies.net Fri June 30 13:30:20 2008

Some Historical Applications of the Method of Indirect Proof THOMAS J. O'SHAUGHNESSY, S.J. FTER proposing the categorical imperative, "Act as if the maxim of thine action were to become by thy will a Universal Law of Nature," Kant tests the formula by four cases. In these he verifies his criterion indirectly, that is, by pointing out the unacceptable situations that would result from neglecting it. For example, if it were a universal law that a man in need could promise to pay back a loan even when he knows he will not be able to, then "the promise itself would become impossible, as well as the end that one might have in view in it, since no one would consider that anything was promised to him, but would ridicule all such statements as vain pretences."l Such an untenable consequence makes the supposition equally untenable. Therefore, Kent concludes, no such universal law is possible, but he who promises is morally bound to be sincere. People are often more inclined to argue negatively than positively. An inept proposal is rejected more because of the difficulties it raises than because of the advantages the contrary course promises. Being a natural and easy form of argumentation, this indirect procedure has a long history in dialectics. Socrates favored it as a means of combating the self-assertiveness of the Sophists and of getting to the universal definitions 1 I. Kant, Fundamental Principles of the Metaphysic of Morals (Great Books Foundation, Chicago 1949), sect. 2, pp. 43-45.

PHILIPPINE STUDIES he was looking for. In fact, he uses it to such an extreme in the Protagoras that he sea4 more sophistical there than the opponent after whom Plato named the dialogue. But the indirect proof--or disproof as it might better be called2-when rightly used is a cogent form of argument because of the obviousness of the principle underlying its most common form, the reductw ake absurdurn: If a proposition implies its own denial, it is false. In Kant's example he whose promise is a self-negating pretence is simply not promising. Sometimes the indirect method is the only kind the matter lends itself to, as for example when the terms of the judgment to be proved are related, not by a medium drawn from either by analysis, but of themselves, thus forming what Aristutle calls an immediate tr~th.~ 'I'he procedure then follows the following pattern: to prove judgment p assume that its contradictory - p or non-p is true and draw out the implications of the assumption. If they are absurd, - p is excluded. No hypothesis whose implications are impossible can be true. But if - p is false, then p must be true, since of two contradictories one is true and the other is false. In this form the argument appears on almost every page of the history of science, because each new development is tested by its implications. If these can be shown to be absurd, the hypothesis is unsound. The Phoenician inscriptions of Paraiba, Brazil are genuine, argues the archeologist, Cyrus H. Gordon, in his recent analysis, because, if they are not, the supposed nineteenth century forger would have to have known linguistic peculiarities and shadings of meaning proper to the period of Phoenician in question but discovered only in the last few years-a gratuitous and untenable implication. The same procedure is used in metaphysics to show that being is not a genus capable of contraction. If the notion were zthe common name for the argument is the "indirect proof" or the "indirect method of proof," but the term "indirect disproof" indicates its negative function: to disprove a proposition by showing that its affirmation would involve one in aburdities 3 Post. Anal., I, 3, 72b22.

O'SHAUGHNESSY: INDIRECT PROOF 595 contracted to its inferiors by determinative differences these latter would be being or non-being. But they cannot be being because a true difference cannot be identical with the notion it contracts; nor can they be non-being, because the logical inferiors of being must be differentiated by something. Hence the hypothesis that the notion of being is capable of contraction by true differences is false and its contradictory is true.' Self-evident principles too, since their denial assumes their own truth-a principle that complements the redrcct&allow only indirect dem~nstration.~ The most obvious example is the principle of contradiction: to be and not to be in the same way at the same time is impossible. It is likewise immediately evident that if anything acts (p), it acts for some determined effect (q). If not [-(p a q)], it acts from the supposition but at the same time does not produce this effect rather than that, that is, does not act." The method of indirect proof, therefore,.depends on the principle that a false conclusion of a correct process implies falsity in the antecedent. But if the premises are held to be true, the false conclusion proves the falsity of the hypothesis that has been inserted into the sequence, which hypothesis contradicts what is to be proved. Parmenides' apparent proof that becoming is an illusion provides a further illustration of the form the argument often cakes. Let it be supposed, he argues, that something becomes. If so, it does not come out of being, because what already exists does not come to be. Yet if it really becomes, it must "That which the mind first conceives, as most known, and to which it reduces all other conceptions is being, as Avicenna says at the beginning of his Metaphysics. Hence all other concepts of the mind are fonned by adding to being....some modality not explicit in the term itself." De Ver., I, 1. 5 Whitehead and Russell state the reductio ad nbsurdun as follows: *2.01 : p 3 - p. 3 - - p. That is, if p implies its own falsehood, then p is false. The complement of this principle is *2.18. @ : - p 3 p. 3. p. That is, if by denying p one implies p, then p is true. A. Whitehead aand B. Russell, Principia Mathematica, 2nd ed. (Cambridge, 1963), I, 100 and 103-104. asurn. Cont. Gent., 111, 2.

596 PHILIPPINE STUDIES have come out of being, because out of nothing comes nothing. Therefore nothing becomes. In the seemingly complete disjunction reasons are given for the truth of both alternatives. Hence, if an absurdity follows-the simultaneous truth of the proposition, "Whatever becomes comes out of being," and its contradictory-it is only because a supposedly false hypothesis, "Something becomes," has been posited. The argument can be set down as follows, if p is taken to represent "X becomes" and q "X comes out of being." (1) P hypothesis (2) p 3 - q premise (3) P 2 q premise (4) - q. q (1) (2) (3) (5) - P (2) (3) Per Zmpussibile Briefly, if it is assumed that something becomes il), contradictories (4) follow, and hence the assumption (1) is alleged to be false. Zeno of Elea, Parmenides' disciple, "composed forty proofs to demonstrate that being is one, thinking it a good thing to come to the help of his master."' The master's denial of phenomena seemingly so evident as becoming and multiplicity had brought him into disrepute. But both, Zeno claimed, really do involve gross absurdities if one assumes them to be verified in fact. Consequently the assumption cannot be admitted and, by opposition, Parmenides' denial must be true. Two samples of Zeno's use of the method of indirect proof will suffice to illustrate his procedure. I. Let the hypothesis be: Realitv is composed of many units which either have or do not have magnitude. If each unit has magnitude it is infinitely divisible, because, no matter how much one divides, magnitude that is further 7 F. Copleston, A History oi Philosophy (London, 1951), I, 55. citing Proclus, In Parmcn. 694, 23 id 20 A 15)

O'SHAUGHNESSY: INDIRECT PROOF 597 divisible will remain. Consequently each unit is itself made up of an infinite number of divisible units, each with rnagnitude, and is therefore infinitely great. If each unit has no magnitude, nothing will have magnitude, since an aggregate of units without magnitude is itself without magnitude. Therefore reality is not infinitely great. Since under either supposition, i.e., each unit has magnitude or each unit has no magnitude, the hypothesis that reality is composed of many units leads to contradictions, it is absurd and its contradictory, Parmenides' denial of multiplicity, is true. 11. Let the hypothesis be: There is a many, which is finite or is not finite in.number. The many must be finite in number, because there are as many things as there are, neither more nor less. Yet the many cannot be finite in number, because for units to be separate the intervention of a third thing is necessary, and so on indefinitely. Since the hypothesis, "There is a many," apparently leads to a contradiction, its contradictory is proved indirectly. * * * Perhaps the most celebrated use of the method of indirect proof was that by which the Pythagorean school is said to have demonstrated that the 2 is incommensurable with unity or, geometrically, that the side of a given squaewhich side is chosen as the unit of length-and the diagonal with the length x have no common measure. Since therefore by the Pythagorean theorem x2 = l2 + l2 = 2, x or V' 2 cannot be a rational number. The form of demonstration that the Pythagoreans seem actually to have used in this case is described by Aristotle as an argument per im.possibile. It shows that, if the diagonal were commensurable with the side, the same number would be both even and not even. For all who effect an argument per impodbile infer syllogistically what is false, and prove the original conclusion hypothetically when eomething impossible results from the assumption of 1 1 contradictory; e.g. that the diagonal of the square is incommensurate with the side,

598 PHILIPPINE STUDIES kaum odd numbers are equal to evens if it is supposed to be commensurate. One infers syllogistically? that odd numbers wme out equal to avens, and one proves hypothetically the incommensurability of the diagonal, since a falsehood results through contradicting this. For this we found to be reasoning per impossibile, viz. proving something impossible by means of an hypothesis conceded at the beginning.* It was only late in the last century, when a rigorous theory of irrational numbers was worked out, that the Pythagorean doctrine of incommensurables came to be recognized for the masterpiece of mathematical reasoning that it The premises that follow are in part a summary of certain points in the theory applicable to a more extended form of the indirect proof.lo A. A rational number is one written p/q where q is not equal to 0 and p and q are positive or negative integers with no common factor other than plus or minus one. B. An irrational number is one that cannot be written p/q. C, The square of an even number is also even, and the square of an odd number is odd. D. A number is even if it has 2 as a factor. E. The square of an even number is divisible by 4. The Proof Per Impmsibik (taking A, B, C, D, and E as premises) : (1) 2 = p/q (2) 2 = p2/q2 (3) p2 = 2q2 (4) p2 is an even number. (5) p is an even number. (6) p% divisible by 4. (7) 2qGs divisible by 4. (8) qz is an even number. (9) q is an even number. hypothesis (1) (2) (Dl (3) (C) (4) (El (5) (3) (6) (D) (7) (C) (8) 8 Prwr Anal., I,23, 41a23-32 (transl. A. Jenkinson). 9R. Courant and H. Robbins. What Is Mathematics? (London, 1951), pp. 59-60. J. Newman, The World of Mathematics (New York, 1956), 1, 525-27, summing up the work of Richard Dedekind.

O'SHAUGHNESSY: INDIRECT PROOF 599 (10) p and q have 2 as a common factor. (5) (9) (11) -(d 2 = ~ /q) (A) Per Zmpmsibile (Q.E.D.) (12) 2 is an irrational number. (B) (11) Hence the hypothesis that the 2 is a rational number, since it implies (A) that p/q is in lowest terms with no common factor between p and q but concludes (10) that both have 2 as a common factor, is necessarily false (11) and its contradictory (12) follows by opposition.ll The "syllogistic inference" mentioned by Aristotle is abbreviated in the above sequence by the notations after each step indicating the two premises from which it is derived. For example, in step (4) the complete syllogism would be: A number having 2 as a factor is an even number (D). But pz is a number having 2 as a factor (3). Therefore, p2 is an even number. Y * * The indirect reduction of syllogisms of the second and third figures to those of the first is an interesting variant of the method of indirect proof or the reductw ad absurdum. Aristotle called it the reductw ad impossibile12 and proposed it in summary form as a means of validating all syllogistic moods,1s even those that admit direct reduction. Using Aristotle's demonstration as a starting point, Peter the Spaniard (later Pope John XXI--died 1277) worked out a detailed scheme for applying this type of validation in his SummuZue Logicales. This was the first medieval work proposing to cover the whole of Aristotle's logic systematically. It remained the standard introduction to the subject for more than three hundred years. Forty-eight editions of it came out in the one century that followed the invention of printing. In it are found, for the first time it seems, nearly all the memonic devices later used in teaching logic. Perhaps the best known 11 Another way of expressing the contradiction is: p/q is in lowest terms (A); it is not the case that p/q is in lowest terms (10). 12 Prior Anal., 1, 5, 27a15; I, 7, 29a35-39. 13 See Prior Anal., XI, 14, 63a.

PHILIPPINE STUDIES are the lines Barbara, Celarent, etc. which contain in abbreviated form a detailed method of directly reducing the other figures to the first by conversion and interchange of premises. In the fourth chapter of his Summulae Peter-and after him the classical logicians-applied the technique of reducing per impossibile to validate Bamo and Bocardo, the two moods of the second and third figures that do not admit direct reduction. The pertinent texts are as follows: (4.04) Syllogisms must have a mood and a figure. The figure is determined by the arrangement of the three terms as subject and predicate.... The second figure is that in which the same term is predicate in both premises.... The third figure has the same subject in both premises.... The mood is the arranging of the two premises according to quality and quantity in a way suitable [for drawing a conclusion]. (4.11) The second figure has four moods.... The fourth consists of one universal affirmative [premise] and one particular negative and a particular negative conclusion; for example, Every man is an animal. Some stone is not an animal. Therefore, some stone is not a man. This is reducible to the first [figure] per impossibile. (4.12) To reduce per impossihile is to infer the contradictory of the second premise from the contradictory of the conclusion together with the first premise. For example, let the above conclusion be contradicted, 'Every stone is a man,' and [then] taken together with the major of the fourth mood as follows: Every man is an animal. Every stane is a man. Therefore, every stone is an animal This conclusion contradicts the minor of the fourth [mood] and a reduction per impossibile is effected. (4.14) The third figure has six moods.... (4.15) The fifth i~ made up ~>f me particular negative premise and one universal affirmative with a particular negative conclusion, as, Some man is not a stone. Every man is an animal. Therefore, some animal is not a stone. It is reducible to the first [figure] per impossibile by taking the contradictory of the conclusion together with the second premise, thus obtaining the contradictory of the remaining [i.e., the first] premise; for example: Every animal is a stone. Every man is an animal. Therefore, every man is a stone." This conclusion, drawn 14A correction for the conclusion, "Therefore, every stone is a man." in the Summulae.

O'SHAUGHNESSY: INDIRECT PROOF 601 fmm the first mood of the first figure, contradicts the major [premise] of the fifth mood of the third figure.ls The "impossibility" for which this kind of reduction is named would consist, as in the forms of indirect proof already examined, in admitting the simultaneous truth of two contradictories. For example, to deny the validity of the fourth mood of the second figure (Baroco) is the same as admitting the truth of the premises but denying the conclusion because of the assumption that the reasoning of this mood is illegitimate. But if the conclusion is false, then its contradidory must be true. This contradidory is then taken with the major premise of the mood in question, which major has already been admitted as true, and a syllogism in the first figure-whose validity is conceded-is formed. The conclusion of this must be admitted as true, because of the admission that the premises are true and the process is valid. But this admittedly true conclusion contradicts the minor, already admitted as true, of the syllogism originally in question. If, then, one denies the validity of Baroco, one is led to affirm contradictories. Therefore the validity of this mood must be admitted. For Baroco the conclusion which is to be proved as validly drawn from the premises is (Ex) (Sx -- Mx). The predicate variables M, A, and S in the scope of the following premises are abbreviations of the terms used in Peter's illustrations. The proof explained above is then written: 15 Petri Hispani SummuIae Logicnles, ed. I. Bochenski (Torino, 1947), pp. 37-41.

602 PHILIPPINE STUDIES Similarly, if Bocardo is a valid mood, it will have the conclusion, (Ex) (Ax. - Sx). Contradicting this in the third step of the proof as written above, quantifying it universally as (x) (Ax 5 Sx), and taking this universal statement with the minor of Bocardo will give the indirect proof for this mood. If the propositions in Peter's examples are rearranged according to the principles of exportation, transposition, and partial duality, the process he describes16 in 4.12 of the above citation is shown in step (5) of the following argument and that of 4.15 in step (9). ~rom the I ~M (~ocardo) to the Second i~wcd),~ (1) [( 3x)(Fk - Sx)*(x)(~Lx 3 Ax)lD ( 3x)(Ax - Sx) (111: Booarbo) (2) c(x)(mx 3 Ax)*( 3f)(lrk - S X ) 3 ~ ( 3x)(k.- SX) (1) 0) (x)(ih 3 Ax) 3 [( 3x)(~k*-Sx) 3 ( ZX)(~ - sd-7 (2) (4) -[- ( 3x)(Ax.-sx) 3 -( 3x)(~m*-sx)] Z) -(x)(m 3 a) (3) (5) [<x)(ax 3 Sx)*( SX)(?~*-SX)] 3 ( 3x)(13x - Ax) (4)(II: &-om the Second Fiyre (~aroco) to the Mrst (~arbara): (5) f (x)(ax 3 Sx)*( 3x)(llx -sx)] 3 ( 3x)(l.k - Ax) (11: Bsroco) (6) [( 3x)(l.k -Sx)*(x)(Ax 3 SX)] 3 (3x)(Fk - Ax) (5) (7) ( 3x)(l* 4) 5 [(x)(ax 3 (8x)(pk -k)j (6) (el - [(x)(lllr 3 SX) 3 ( 3x)().br - ( ~x)(~x*-sx) (7) -&)ID (9) [(XI(& 3 Ww(~)(fi 3 h1-7 3 (XI(& 3 *) (e)(z:~.r-) Thus all three moods imply one another and denying the validity of any one of them requires a like denial of that of the other two. Indirect demonstration concludes only to the fact that a thing is so or not so and cannot be otherwise, but without giving the intrinsic reason why. Where one must be content with negative grounds for judging, the method is a valuable means of arriving at knowledge. But in some of its more celebrated applications in the history of thought the contradiction 16 The process is here represented but not tlle distribution of terms.

O'SHAVGHNESSY: INDIRECT PROOF 603 to which the unwanted assumption leads is only apparent. Aristotle destroyed the dilemma of Parmenides by the postulate of potentiality, and Zeno's riddles were solved by acknowledging magnitude to be continuous rather than discrete. At the time they were proposed, however, Zeno's arguments raised insoluble difficulties and so opened the way for the scepticism of the Sophists, who were interested in confuting their opponents rather than in getting to the truth. Socrates used the indirect method of proof to overthrow their easy assumptions and to show the existence of problems that had scarcely occurred to his predecessors. Thinkers of all times have found in the revtuctio ad abswdum and like forms of argumentation a method of clarifying their reflections on basic principles which because of their obscurity or their immediacy cannot be proved directly. In every field of investigation the indirect method will remain useful for its versatility, its apodictic character, and its effectiveness in excluding false hypotheses.