THESES SIS/LIBRARY TELEPHONE:

Similar documents
THESES SIS/LIBRARY TELEPHONE:

THESES SIS/LIBRARY TELEPHONE:

THESES SIS/LIBRARY TELEPHONE:

THESES SIS/LIBRARY TELEPHONE:

WITTGENSTEIN, AUSTIN, AND THE ORIGINS OF SPEECH-ACT THEORY

J. L. Austin ( )

THESES SIS/LIBRARY TELEPHONE:

USE OF THESES. Australian National University

THE SEMANTIC REALISM OF STROUD S RESPONSE TO AUSTIN S ARGUMENT AGAINST SCEPTICISM

Kierkegaard, Indirect Communication and Performativity. Hunter Alan Bragg. Thesis. Submitted to the Faculty of the

THESES SIS/LIBRARY TELEPHONE:

USE OF THESES. «1 s a. ٢ ٦ ٠ ٦ Australian

Philosophy A465: Introduction to Analytic Philosophy Loyola University of New Orleans Ben Bayer Spring 2011

USE OF THESES. Australian National University

THESES SIS/LIBRARY TELEPHONE:

Moral Objectivism. RUSSELL CORNETT University of Calgary

Oxford Dictionary of National Biography

Templates for Writing about Ideas and Research

Each copy of any part of a JSTOR transmission must contain the same copyright notice that appears on the screen or printed page of such transmission.

COURSE BI-192 (B) 1 TIMOTHY

Legal Positivism: the Separation and Identification theses are true.

THESES SIS/LIBRARY TELEPHONE:

THESES SIS/LIBRARY TELEPHONE:

Vol. II, No. 5, Reason, Truth and History, 127. LARS BERGSTRÖM

THE NATURE OF NORMATIVITY IN KANT S PHILOSOPHY OF LOGIC REBECCA V. MILLSOP S

A HUNDRED YEARS OF ENGLISH PHILOSOPHY

Ryle on Systematically Misleading Expresssions

DIRECTIVE SPEECH ACT REALIZATION IN THE TEACHING AND LEARNING AT MAGISTER OF LANGUAGE STUDIES MUHAMMADIYAH UNIVERSITY OF SURAKARTA 2014

Davidson and Wittgenstein a Homeric Struggle? Åsa Wikforss Stockholm University

Wittgenstein and Austin on What is in Common : A Neglected Perspective?

Issue 4, Special Conference Proceedings Published by the Durham University Undergraduate Philosophy Society

New Critical Reasoning What Wittgenstein Offered

Denis Seron. Review of: K. Mulligan, Wittgenstein et la philosophie austro-allemande (Paris: Vrin, 2012). Dialectica

This form of plagiarism also includes getting somebody else to write your work for you (ghost-writing).

Unit VI: Davidson and the interpretational approach to thought and language

Wittgenstein and Heidegger: on Use

RECONSTRUCTING THE DOCTRINE OF THE SUFFICIENCY OF SCRIPTURE 1

Molnar on Truthmakers for Negative Truths

THESES SIS/LIBRARY TELEPHONE:

On happiness in Locke s decision-ma Title being )

Wittgenstein on the Fallacy of the Argument from Pretence. Abstract

SYLLABUS for COURSE TH-464 (B) THE HOLY SPIRIT

MIND, LANGUAGE, AND METAPHILOSOPHY

KANT S CRITIQUE OF PURE REASON

CLASSICAL SOCIOLOGICAL THEORY Sociology 475

Primary and Secondary Qualities. John Locke s distinction between primary and secondary qualities of bodies has

Topics in Philosophy of Mind Other Minds Spring 2003/handout 2

Two Kinds of Ends in Themselves in Kant s Moral Theory

THE CHICAGO STATEMENT ON BIBLICAL INERRANCY A Summarization written by Dr. Murray Baker

POSITIVISM AND CHRISTIANITY A STUDY OF THEISM AND VERIFIABILITY

Kant and the Problem of Metaphysics 1. By Tom Cumming

Week 8 Biblical Inerrancy

The Chicago Statement on Biblical Inerrancy

Rule-Following and the Ontology of the Mind Abstract The problem of rule-following

THESES SIS/LIBRARY TELEPHONE:

Wittgenstein s Influence on Austin s Philosophy of Language

THESES SIS/LIBRARY TELEPHONE:

BASIC SENTENCE PATTERNS

COURSE OUTLINE. Philosophy 116 (C-ID Number: PHIL 120) Ethics for Modern Life (Title: Introduction to Ethics)

The Life Myth, Short Lives and Dealing with Live Subjects in Political Biography

A problem for expressivism

From Necessary Truth to Necessary Existence

If we can t assert this, we undermine the truth of the scientific arguments too. So, Kanterian says: A full

Introduction to Political Thought: POL-103 REVISED 1/8/18 Spring 2018 MWF, 9:30 am - 10:20 pm Johns Hall, 212

Scriptural Promise The grass withers, the flower fades, but the word of our God stands forever, Isaiah 40:8

The challenge for evangelical hermeneutics is the struggle to make the old, old

Speech-Act Theory and the Formal Essay.

SYLLABUS for COURSE TH-464 (A) THE HOLY SPIRIT

Introduction: Paradigms, Theism, and the Parity Thesis

INTRODUCTION TO THE Holman Christian Standard Bible

Class 2 - The Ontological Argument

Strawson On Referring. By: Jake McDougall and Siri Cosper

Did Marc Hauser's Moral Minds Plagiarize John Mikhail's Earlier Work?

CHAPTER 2 THE LARGER LOGICAL LANDSCAPE NOVEMBER 2017

part one MACROSTRUCTURE Cambridge University Press X - A Theory of Argument Mark Vorobej Excerpt More information

There might be nothing: the subtraction argument improved

2004 by Dr. William D. Ramey InTheBeginning.org

Reply to Lorne Falkenstein RAE LANGTON. Edinburgh University

WITTGENSTEIN S TRACTATUS

THEOLOGY IN THE FLESH

Supplementary Section 6S.7

Russell, Propositional Unity, and the Correspondence Intuition By Anssi Korhonen

This is a longer version of the review that appeared in Philosophical Quarterly Vol. 47 (1997)

Philosophical Review.

Faith and Reason Thomas Aquinas

Etchemendy, Tarski, and Logical Consequence 1 Jared Bates, University of Missouri Southwest Philosophy Review 15 (1999):

Cognitivism about imperatives

THE MORAL ARGUMENT. Peter van Inwagen. Introduction, James Petrik

acting on principle onora o neill has written extensively on ethics and political philosophy

The Myth of Factive Verbs

EMBEDDING QUOTATIONS

The excitement of seminars, and I have been teaching them for many (many)

Judging Coherence in the Argumentative Situation. Things are coherent if they stick together, are connected in a specific way, and are consistent in

Is THERE A DOCTRINAL DIFFERENCE?

CONTENTS. INTRODUCTORY Chapter I ETHICAL NEUTRALITY AND PRAGMATISM

Paper #1: Maria tegui & The Problem of the Indian

Lesson 2 The Existence of God Cause & Effect Apologetics Press Introductory Christian Evidences Correspondence Course

LOCKE STUDIES Vol ISSN: X

ACADEMIC SKILLS PROGRAM STUDENT SERVICES AND DEVELOPMENT

Russell on Plurality

Transcription:

THESES SIS/LIBRARY TELEPHONE: +61 2 6125 4631 R.G. MENZIES LIBRARY BUILDING NO:2 FACSIMILE: +61 2 6125 4063 THE AUSTRALIAN NATIONAL UNIVERSITY EMAIL: library.theses@anu.edu.au CANBERRA ACT 0200 AUSTRALIA USE OF THESES This copy is supplied for purposes of private study and research only. Passages from the thesis may not be copied or closely paraphrased without the written consent of the author.

STUDIES IN J. L. AUSTIN'S PHILOSOPHY OF LANGUAGE by Maxwell Wright A thesis submitted for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy in the Australian National University, June 1965

C l*"; j i'v.ip rl J,ff'l>.. -'t"~....,..;...t,.,_'} / Of course comments on comments, criticisms of criticisms, are subject to the law of diminishing fleas.. Unfair to facts

This thesis is my own work, written while I was a research scholar in the Research School of Social Sciences in the Australian National University. '- :' ~-t \ l I ~~{ I.A.) '

CONTENTS Abbreviations used Preface Synopsis iii iv viii PART I Meaning and Statement CHAPTER 1 The Meaning of Language CHAPTER 2 Statements and Associated Speech Acts CHAPTER 3 Statements and Facts 1 20 58 PART II Speech Acts and the Uses of Language CHAPTER 4 The Use of Language 96 CHAPTER 5 Locutionary, Illocutionary and Perlocutionary Acts 153 i

ii PART III Grammatical Investigations CHAPTER 6 'I Know' and Performative Utterances 187 C~PTER7 C~PTER 8 Performative Utterances, Illocutionary Forces and Parenthetical Verbs Ability and Choice 212 249 Publications Cited 279

iii ABBREVIATIONS The following abbreviations are used in citations. Papers HTDTWW ss A AJP p PAS PASS PR,!g ECA Austin's Philosophical Papers How to do Things with Words Sense and Sensibilia Analysis Australasian Journal of Philosophy Philosophy Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society do., Supplementary Volume Philosophical Review Philosophical Quarterly Essays in Conceptual Analysis

iv PREFACE What follows is a series of loosely related studies of some aspects of J.L. Austin's philosophy of language and of what I have called his 'grammatical investigations' into the usage of such verbs as 'I know' and 'I can'. Perhaps I had better say: Some aspects of philosophy of language as they arise out of Austin's work. For, while the starting point is always Austin, and the subjects discussed - meaning, use, force, statements, facts, speech-acts and so on- figure prominently in Austin's work, I have, in discussing them, drawn, not only on Austin's work, but also on related contemporary writings; for example, work by P.F. Strawson on statements, by Gilbert Ryle on the use of language, by J.O. Urmson on non-descriptive, force-showing verbs. I am hesitant to advance any large thesis about Austin, preferring rather that this work be thought of as constituting a small part of that 'patient accumulation of many small truths' with which Austin, according to G.J. Warnock, 1 may have hoped to pave 'the road to large truths'. However, before turning to the minutiae, I should like to say two quite general things about Austin, one of them completely untendentious. 1 John Lan~shaw Austin, Proceedings of the British Academy. XLIX (1963), p.354.

v follows: The concluding words of Austin's Philosophical Papers are as life and truth and things do tend to be a bit complicated. It's not things, it's philosophers that are simple. You will have heard it said, I expect, that over-simplification is the occupational disease of philosopher, and in a way one might agree with that. But for a sneaking suspicion that it's their occupation. I should claim that Austin's occupation was, at least very often, philosophy, that is, over-simplification, even though, elsewhere (HTDTWW 38), he remarked that over-simplification must at all costs be avoided. It is of some interest to compare the following two quotations, the first from Philosophical Investigations (1:23) the second from Austin's Performative Utterances (Papers 221) But how many kinds of sentence are there? Say assertion, question, and command? There are countless kinds: countless different kinds of use of what we call 'symbols', 'words', 'sentences' (Wittgenstein's italics). I think we should not despair too easily and talk, as people are apt to do, about the infinite uses of language. Philosophers will do this when they have listed as many, let us say, as seventeen; but even if there were something like ten thousand uses of language, surely we could list them all in time. (Austin's italics). Now if Wittgenstein is right any attempted schematization of ordinary language will be either incomplete or an 'over-simplification'. And Wittgenstein may well be right. Nevertheless I believe that we ought to follow Austin in attempting the schematization even if it means

vi engaging in a bit of over-simplification or philosophy. For, notice that Austin's ten thousand uses of language would be almost as dull as Wittgenstein's countless uses if it were impossible to categorize these uses, subsuming them under the simplest possible schema. And, in fact, when Austin does list a great variety of speech-acts (HTDTWW chap.l2) he classifies some as, for example, expositive uses of language, as opposed to verdictive, exercitive, commissive and behabitive uses of language. Furthermore, all verdictive, exercitive, commissive, behabitive and expositive uses of language are alike in being illocutionary uses of language as opposed to, for example, perlocutionary uses of language. The attempted schematization may be an over-simplification, but the fun is in the trying. Secondly, I want to say that I have found in the close study of Austin's philosophical writing what Austin claimed to find in the study of excuses, namely, 'what philosophy is so often thought, and made, barren of- the fun of discovery, the pleasures of co-operation, and the satisfaction of reaching agreement' Disagreement too, of course, as I shall try to make clear. For I am acknowledging, gratefully, that it is always possible, even when Austin's argument is most complex and difficult, to be clear what the argument is. So that, agreeing or disagreeing, we can know what we are agreeing or disagreeing with. Who will say that it is always so in philosophy?

vii My thanks go to the Australian National University whose generous research scholarship made this work possible: And to Professor John Passmore and Dr Robert Brown for a great deal of patient, sympathetic criticism. Canberra, June 1965.

viii SYNOPSIS Chapter 1 I examine Austin's paper How to Talk from the point of view of the theory of meaning (sense and reference) there adumbrated. Chapter 2 I describe the operation of 'fitting' and 'matching' by means of which Austin, in How to Talk, claims to generate four distinct speechacts from a given speech-situation. I then argue, against J.W. Roxbee Cox, that it is neither vacuous to speak of fitting an item to a given name while matching the 'item-type' to the 'sense' of the name, nor impossible to speak of fitting an item to a name while matching the 'sense' of the name to the 'item-type'. I go on, however, to claim that 'statements', 'descriptions', etc., the speech-acts schematized by Austin, are not distinguished in ordinary language in the way that Austin suggests they are. Chapter 3 I consider the role played by statements in the controversy between Austin and Strawson about Truth; I argue that some of the confusion about facts which that debate engendered rests on a prior confusion about statements.

vix Chapter 4 Contemporary philosophers often speak of the use of (units of) language for (units of) speech. I examine some recent 'use-talk' as it is found in the writing of Austin, Ryle and Strawson, and try to show that it is neither particularly consistent nor particularly sensible. I except, with some reservations, the later use-talk of Austin; the use of language, not for the 1 bare 1 locutionary act of saying something, but for further illocutionary and perlocutionary acts. I then argue in favour of Ryle's recommendation that use-talk be construed as talk about how language is used rather than as talk about what language is used for. However, I go on to claim, against Ryle, that use-talk, thus construed, becomes 'usage-talk'. Finally, I argue that Ryle, in his important papers on this topic, is led into error just because he writes in terms of the use of language rather than in terms of linguistic usage. Chapter 5 I try to examine, in some detail, the distinctions drawn by Austin, in How to do Things with Words, between (l) the phonetic act, the phatic act and the rhetic act - the speech-acts which together comprise a complete locutionary act; (2) the locutionary act and the illocutionary act; (3) the illocutionary act and the perlocutionary act.

X Chapter 6 I begin by claiming that J.O. Urmson's argument to the effect that Austin did not, in Other Minds, read 'I know' as performative, is unsuccessful. I go on to argue that Austin, while affecting to draw a parallel between knowing and promising, succeeds only in drawing a parallel between saying 'I know' and saying 'I promise'; and that the latter parallel does not support the former just because 'I promise' is a performative utterance while 'I know' is not. The breakdown of the parallelism suggests the sort of grammatical criterion for performative or practical utterances which has been proposed by W.H.F. Barnes. I proceed to test Barnes' criterion, first against some paradigmatically performative utterances, 'I promise', 'I guarantee' and so on, then against utterances which are less clearly performative, 'I hold', 'I agree' and so on. I find that while the criterion will do very well for the paradigms, verbs like 'I agree' may be read either as conforming or as not conforming to Barnes' rule. I then suggest that 'I agree' conforms or fails to conform to Barnes' rule (is performative or descriptive) according to whether we think of agreement as an action to be performed or a 'state of mind' to be described. I conclude by arguing that 'I know' is never performative just because knowing is not an action we perform. Chapter 7 Austin's later doctrine of illocutionary forces will not, I argue, accommodate 'I know' and 'I believe' as illocutionary verbs, any more

xi than the performative thesis before it would accommodate 'I know' as a performative utterance. a theory of speech-acts. For the later theory is, like the earlier, Because knowing and believing are not things that we do they are not things that we do with words. I go on to make a critical examination of Urmson's related thesis that 'I know' and 'I believe' are non-descriptive because force-showing or degreeindicating or parenthetical. Finally, I compare Urmson's attempt to 'reduce' some important 'psychological-descriptives' to the class of parenthetical or force-showing verbs with Austin's attempt to'reduce' the class of performative utterances to the class of illocutionary or force-showing verbs, in order to bring out what I take to be a weakness common to both enterprises. Chapter 8 I examine Austin's more successful investigations into the 'grammar' of 'I can', in the light of later criticism by D.J. O'Connor and P.H. Nowell-Smith.