Comparing Kant and Sartre. Ed. by Sorin Baiasu. London/New York: Palgrave Macmillan, 2016, 262 pp. ISBN

Similar documents
FIRST STUDY. The Existential Dialectical Basic Assumption of Kierkegaard s Analysis of Despair

Freedom as Morality. UWM Digital Commons. University of Wisconsin Milwaukee. Hao Liang University of Wisconsin-Milwaukee. Theses and Dissertations

Kant and the Problem of Metaphysics 1. By Tom Cumming

Christian Lotz, Commentary, SPEP 2009 Formal Indication and the Problem of Radical Philosophy in Heidegger

Moral Argumentation from a Rhetorical Point of View

1 Hans Jonas, The Imperative of Responsibility: In Search of an Ethics for the Technological Age (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1984), 1-10.

Important dates. PSY 3360 / CGS 3325 Historical Perspectives on Psychology Minds and Machines since David Hume ( )

Canadian Society for Continental Philosophy

From Transcendental Logic to Transcendental Deduction

A HOLISTIC VIEW ON KNOWLEDGE AND VALUES

Rationalism. A. He, like others at the time, was obsessed with questions of truth and doubt

The Paradox of the stone and two concepts of omnipotence

Response to Gregory Floyd s Where Does Hermeneutics Lead? Brad Elliott Stone, Loyola Marymount University ACPA 2017

FREEDOM AND THE SOURCE OF VALUE: KORSGAARD AND WOOD ON KANT S FORMULA OF HUMANITY CHRISTOPHER ARROYO

The Middle Path: A Case for the Philosophical Theologian. Leo Strauss roots the vitality of Western civilization in the ongoing conflict between

Aspects of Western Philosophy Dr. Sreekumar Nellickappilly Department of Humanities and Social Sciences Indian Institute of Technology, Madras

From the Categorical Imperative to the Moral Law

Happiness and Personal Growth: Dial.

2 FREE CHOICE The heretical thesis of Hobbes is the orthodox position today. So much is this the case that most of the contemporary literature

Making Sense of the Postulate of Freedom. and God, play in Kant s system is akin to walking a tightrope. First and foremost, the reader must

Resolutio of Idealism into Atheism in Fichte

THE STUDY OF UNKNOWN AND UNKNOWABILITY IN KANT S PHILOSOPHY

Kant and his Successors

Phenomenal Knowledge, Dualism, and Dreams Jesse Butler, University of Central Arkansas

Purple Haze: The Puzzle of Consciousness

Rationalist-Irrationalist Dialectic in Buddhism:

Rule-Following and the Ontology of the Mind Abstract The problem of rule-following

1/10. The Fourth Paralogism and the Refutation of Idealism

KANT ON THE UNITY OF THEORETICAL AND PRACTICAL REASON.

Mikhael Dua. Tacit Knowing. Michael Polanyi s Exposition of Scientific Knowledge. Herbert Utz Verlag Wissenschaft München

Was Berkeley a Rational Empiricist? In this short essay I will argue for the conclusion that, although Berkeley ought to be

Thursday, November 30, 17. Hegel s Idealism

A Review on What Is This Thing Called Ethics? by Christopher Bennett * ** 1

The Rightness Error: An Evaluation of Normative Ethics in the Absence of Moral Realism

Plato s Concept of Soul

Korsgaard and Non-Sentient Life ABSTRACT

Response to The Problem of the Question About Animal Ethics by Michal Piekarski

To appear in The Journal of Philosophy.

Are There Reasons to Be Rational?

Right-Making, Reference, and Reduction

GOD'S SILENCE IN THE DIALOGUE ACCORDING TO MARTIN BUBER

Heidegger Introduction

Tuesday, November 11, Hegel s Idealism

Chapter 25. Hegel s Absolute Idealism and the Phenomenology of Spirit

Some Notes Toward a Genealogy of Existential Philosophy Robert Burch

Religious Studies. Name: Institution: Course: Date:

The Groundwork, the Second Critique, Pure Practical Reason and Motivation

Testimony and Moral Understanding Anthony T. Flood, Ph.D. Introduction

Tuesday, September 2, Idealism

what makes reasons sufficient?

Denis Seron. Review of: K. Mulligan, Wittgenstein et la philosophie austro-allemande (Paris: Vrin, 2012). Dialectica

An Article for Encyclopedia of American Philosophy on: Robert Cummings Neville. Wesley J. Wildman Boston University December 1, 2005

The Qualiafications (or Lack Thereof) of Epiphenomenal Qualia

The Impossibility of Evil Qua Evil: Kantian Limitations on Human Immorality

FUNDAMENTAL PRINCIPLES OF THE METAPHYSIC OF MORALS. by Immanuel Kant

Philosophical Review.

Review of Constructive Empiricism: Epistemology and the Philosophy of Science

GS SCORE ETHICS - A - Z. Notes

-- The search text of this PDF is generated from uncorrected OCR text.

Craig on the Experience of Tense

A CONTRACTUALIST READING OF KANT S PROOF OF THE FORMULA OF HUMANITY. Adam Cureton

What Lurks Beneath the Integrity Objection. Bernard Williams s alienation and integrity arguments against consequentialism have

Kant and the Problem of Personal Identity Jacqueline Mariña

REVIEW THE DOOR TO SELLARS

Two Kinds of Ends in Themselves in Kant s Moral Theory

Process Thought and Bridge Building: A Response to Stephen K. White. Kevin Schilbrack

Jacob Martin Rump, PhD Symposium: Contemporary Work in Phenomenology Boston Phenomenology Circle Boston University, 1 April 2016

Gestures in the Making

The title of this collection of essays is a question that I expect many professional philosophers have

The Human Science Debate: Positivist, Anti-Positivist, and Postpositivist Inquiry. By Rebecca Joy Norlander. November 20, 2007

Contemporary Theology I: Hegel to Death of God Theologies

Communicative Rationality and Deliberative Democracy of Jlirgen Habermas: Toward Consolidation of Democracy in Africa

The Greatest Mistake: A Case for the Failure of Hegel s Idealism

Review Tutorial (A Whirlwind Tour of Metaphysics, Epistemology and Philosophy of Religion)

PHILOSOPHY DEPARTMENT FALL SEMESTER 2009 COURSE OFFERINGS

Critical Discussion of A. W. Moore s Critique of Kant

Inner Sense, Self-A ection, & Temporal Consciousness .,. ( )

THE RELATIONSHIP BETWEEN SCIENCE, RELIGION AND ARISTOTELIAN THEOLOGY TODAY

RECENT WORK THE MINIMAL DEFINITION AND METHODOLOGY OF COMPARATIVE PHILOSOPHY: A REPORT FROM A CONFERENCE STEPHEN C. ANGLE

Varieties of Apriority

1/6. The Second Analogy (2)

Anselmian Theism and Created Freedom: Response to Grant and Staley

Dave Elder-Vass Of Babies and Bathwater. A Review of Tuukka Kaidesoja Naturalizing Critical Realist Social Ontology

Phil 114, Wednesday, April 11, 2012 Hegel, The Philosophy of Right 1 7, 10 12, 14 16, 22 23, 27 33, 135, 141

Is Kant's Account of Free Will Coherent?

1/12. The A Paralogisms

What God Could Have Made

Epistemology and sensation

PROSPECTS FOR A JAMESIAN EXPRESSIVISM 1 JEFF KASSER

1/8. Introduction to Kant: The Project of Critique

Introduction. Bernard Williams

1/8. The Schematism. schema of empirical concepts, the schema of sensible concepts and the

ABSTRACT of the Habilitation Thesis

The Boundaries of Hegel s Criticism of Kant s Concept of the Noumenal

DISCUSSION PRACTICAL POLITICS AND PHILOSOPHICAL INQUIRY: A NOTE

Philosophy of Ethics Philosophy of Aesthetics. Ross Arnold, Summer 2014 Lakeside institute of Theology

Kant s Critical Thoughts on Freedom from a Contemporary Perspective -

On Searle on Human Rights, Again! J. Angelo Corlett, San Diego State University

Anthony P. Andres. The Place of Conversion in Aristotelian Logic. Anthony P. Andres

Transcription:

Buchbesprechungen 487 Lebens. Das Buch vermag die gegenseitige Durchdringung der moralischen und der emotional-psychologischen Dimension im Denken Kants plastisch vor Augen zu führen. Zugleich betrachtet sie die Gefühlstheorie Kants als sehr hilfreich, sowohl für die moralische Integration der Gefühle als auch für die Abwehr von reduktionistischen psychologischen oder naturwissenschaftlichen Theorien der Emotionen. Die deontologische Ethik Kants wird oft im Gegensatz zur eudaimonistischen Ethik des Aristoteles gesehen. Eines der sekundären Ziele des Buches von Williamson ist es zu zeigen, dass die Differenz auf den zweiten Blick wesentlich geringer ist, als es auf den ersten Blick den Anschein hat. Das Resultat: Das moralische Leben ist immer auch emotional geladen, und unsere Gefühle sollen stets in eine moralische Perspektive eingebunden werden, aus der sie beurteilt und richtig eingeordnet werden können. Es gibt laut Williamson keine Moral ohne Gefühle und unsere Affektivität muss stets moralisch evaluiert werden. Dass uns dies die kantische Philosophie lehren kann, das hat die Autorin in ihrem sehr differenzierten und detailliert ausgearbeiten Buch brillant gezeigt. Comparing Kant and Sartre. Ed. by Sorin Baiasu. London/New York: Palgrave Macmillan, 2016, 262 pp. ISBN 978-1-137-45452-2. Besprochen von Dr. Ana Falcato: Instituto de Filosofia da Nova, Universidade Nova de Lisboa, IFILNOVA, Philosophy, Av. de Berna, 26 4º Piso 1069 061 Lisboa, Portugal; aniusca@hotmail.com https://doi.org/10.1515/kant-2017-0031 Despite the many references to Kant in his posthumously published Notebooks for an Ethics, and despite the fact that he called his last major work Critique of Dialectical Reason, the young Sartre did not generally situate Kant as a prominent interlocutor. Indeed, his attitude toward Kant in Being and Nothingness is, if anything, one of discrete dismissal. Why then choose rapprochement between Kant s and Sartre s philosophical systems as an organizing topic for a volume of essays? It is as important to consider Kant s impact on philosophical systems from the eighteenth century onwards as it is to trace the historical development of his ideas. Phenomenology, and Sartre s work in particular, are fruitful areas in this regard. Three core characteristics of Kant s practical and theoretical thinking played a significant role in Sartre s project, and each of these are thoroughly developed in the essays included in this volume. To begin with, what in Kant was a crucial inheritance from the Protestant worldview the ascription of great moral significance to everyday experience, as against heroic, supermeritorious

488 Buchbesprechungen deeds would, in a desacralized vein, later impact Sartre s phenomenological descriptions of the daily lives of individuals. Sartre also borrowed from Kant s philosophy the notion that our fundamental ethical dispositions are formed by an original act of voluntary choice one that is located outside of time, detached from the agent s environment, and that renders intelligible all individual choices and personal character. Finally and crucially it is from Kant that Sartre acquired the critical notion that any attempt at self-knowledge is obliterated by the continuous withdrawal of an I with the capacity to reflect. Building on these organizing insights from critical philosophy, Comparing Kant and Sartre proceeds by addressing thematically the affinities between the two thinkers. Following an extensive introduction, the volume is divided into three thematic sections on metaphysics, metaethics and metaphilosophy, respectively. In the opening chapter of the first section, Baiasu further develops claims he had previously established in his comparison of the Kantian transcendental unity of apperception and Sartre s pre-reflective consciousness of self (Baiasu, S., 2011: Kant and Sartre: Re-discovering Critical Ethics. New York: Palgrave Macmillan). He defends them against two objections. According to the first, both of the formal conditions of subjective world-apprehension are too thin to have any moral relevance. Baiasu claims that they are fundamental epistemological conditions even for experiences as primitive as having the sensation of red. Furthermore, and against the objection that he construes Kant as arguing that such basic sensorial inputs are pre-objective elements of experience, Baiasu defends the transcendentally critical claim that the experience of red presupposes a certain synthesis, which renders that fragmentary element of experience a partial effect of the object upon sensibility. Were this not so, Kant could be accused of offering a traditional form of idealism. And this brings us to the core of the second objection, which stresses the possibility of a problematic overlap between epistemological and ontological concerns in Baiasu s argument. By starting with both thinkers conceptions of the subjective conditions that determine the apprehension of phenomena and then isolating the ontological status of sensation, Baiasu seems to want the best of both worlds, or so the objection goes. Moreover, by concentrating on the ontology of sensation as conceived by Kant (whose main concerns in the first Critique seem to have been purely epistemological) while still comparing this with Sartre s primary framework for self-apprehension, the author might be read as imposing an epistemic bias on Sartrean ontology. Baiasu defends himself by insisting on the crucial point that, because Kantian metaphysics does not rely on things in themselves, there is no contradiction in pursuing the ontological conditions of empirically real phenomena. The second essay, by Daniel Herbert, analyses Kant s and Sartre s views on temporality. Herbert begins by reminding us of both philosophers forceful rejec-

Buchbesprechungen 489 tions of the view that time is an objective event. Despite this common point of departure, however, Herbert goes on to show how the differences between the two philosophical systems outweigh their similarities. Because of their radically different methodological starting points laying the subjective foundation of mathematical sciences, grounding the spontaneity of human agency Kant and Sartre reach equally divergent conclusions regarding temporality. Three such differences stand out. First, Kant roots temporality in the cognitive workings of the transcendental subject, and Sartre thinks that this precludes reasonable disclosure of the internal processing of temporal phenomena. Second, and because of this initial separation between the transcendental and the empirical subject, Kant attempts to explain alteration over time as a set of changes undergone by a persistent substance; this, according to Sartre, erases the radical ontological difference between temporality and substantiality, or, in his own terms, between being-for-itself and being-in-itself. Finally, Sartre believes that Kant s insistence on dichotomies pushed him to a contradictory notion of free will. To the extent that Kant viewed determinism about natural phenomena as compatible with noumenal freedom, he posited a non-temporal source of spontaneity as the ultimate ground of practical agency, thus undermining subjectivity itself which is only possible, for Sartre, as a temporal non-self-identity. In Kant and Sartre: Psychology and Metaphysics: The Quiet Power of the Imaginary, Thomas Flynn considers the intertwinement of distinctive features of Sartre s moral psychology and the broader metaphysical structures from which it stems, the main connecting thread being his notion of the imaginary. From his earliest writings onward even in the 1927 Diplôme d études supérieures Sartre intuits the potential for radical freedom associated with a consciousness capable of imagining, and thus of negating its present moment. Flynn shows how, in his more marginal works (where Sartre gathers material for bigger, more systematic pieces), two elements from Kantian philosophy continually re-emerge, reshaped in existentialist terms: the function of the ego and the categorical imperative. The most significant outcome of this dialogue with Kantian philosophy and his phenomenological predecessors is, for Sartre, the undermining of any sharp distinction between the purely normative and the purely descriptive. Flynn s argument reveals the impact that Sartre s early defence of an egoless conscience had on his later selective agreement with Kantian universal decision-making: choosing for all men with each individual decision makes no sense, for Sartre, unless that choice is accompanied by a strong element of risk on the part of the protagonist. In the last chapter in this section, Drawing on Sartre s Ontology to Interpret Kant s Notion of Freedom, Christian Onof analyses Kant s and Sartre s treatments of freedom. One initial difficulty with this comparison consists in reconciling Kantian compatibilism i. e. the critical claim that transcendental freedom

490 Buchbesprechungen is compatible with determinism in the natural realm with the Sartrean view of radical, non-negotiable freedom as the very being of the for-itself. Onof s proposal for solving this apparently irreconcilable clash is original and challenges current interpretations. After examining several notions and developments that led up to Kant s forceful defence of transcendental freedom via the fact of reason, Onof argues that both the solution to the conundrum of the human moral situation (human agency s being ascribable neither to the realm of appearances nor to the realm of the in-itself) and the Kantian and Sartrean models of freedom can be traced to Willkür qua negative transcendental freedom or spontaneous consciousness of choice. Significantly, it is Sartre s view on freedom as the essential vocation of the for-itself that inspires a more harmonious, less dichotomous model for interpreting transcendental freedom. At the close of the essay, the author stresses the importance of negativity in both Sartre s account of human consciousness and Kant s views on conscious spontaneity, which grounds practical self-determination in possibility rather than actuality. Leslie Stevenson s Self-knowledge in Kant and Sartre opens the second thematic section of the volume, the focus of which is metaethics. Here, Stevenson stresses not the cognitively pure structure that enables objective knowledge but the ontological grounds of self-knowledge, which both philosophers take to have practical and emotional consequences. Stevenson begins by drawing attention to the contrast between animal and human mental structures, where the latter but not the former allow the subject both to become positionally aware of herself, her relationship to the environment, and her mental landscape as whole and to linguistically articulate this awareness. Stevenson proceeds by briefly considering the Sartrean opposition between pure and impure reflection and finishes with a longer section on the relationship between self-knowledge and freedom in both systems of thought. The perhaps overly broad scope of issues raised in this text prevents Stevenson from examining in more detail what I think is a crucial point of convergence between Kant s and Sartre s views at a practical level: the refinement of this pure reflection, which can make the subject aware of the precariousness of the reasons grounding her actions and conscious choices. The daunting dilemma when comparing both philosophers views on self-knowledge is not primarily one of aligning two apparently irreconcilable standpoints on the self Kant s epistemic angle versus Sartre s preoccupation with radical self-choice. If only in radically sceptical terms, their views meet; the impossibility of apprehending our own motives, which for Kant lies in the threat of self-love as a veiled incentive, is for Sartre characterized by the very scissiparity at work in the cogito: the self s non-coincidence with itself is the only mode of consciousness. Peter Poellner s Action, Value and Autonomy: A Quasi-Sartrean View attempts to extract Sartrean lessons for contemporary debates on practical ration-

Buchbesprechungen 491 ality. Poellner begins by making explicit the Sartrean account of autonomy as a feature of consciousness, in which both self-determination and reason-sensitivity play a central role. He further summarizes the most significant aspects of Sartre s view of freedom, insisting that, far from imposing a metaphysical model, it is all about the practical reality of action and that therein lies the parallel with Kant. The next and more complex step in Poellner s argument deals with what he terms the Sartrean completion thesis, i. e. the constant lack which defines consciousness and its pointless attempts at self-coincidence. Poellner rightly sees that a link can be drawn between this ontological feature of self-consciousness and a similar desire for completion that is characteristic of practical deliberation. Affinities with Kantian ethical theory emerge at the level of what has sometimes been called the latter s constitutive perfectionism : just as consciousness bears intrinsic value insofar as it aims at unqualifiedly valuable ends, potentially encompassing all conscious beings, so Kant s morality is crafted as a continuous quest for the summum bonum. The essay is not as successful as it could be because of its highly analytic, systematic approach to Sartre s views on the conditions for action (drawn from Parts One and Two of Being and Nothingness and elsewhere), because of which it cannot adequately deal with the phenomenological texture of Sartre s analysis. The result of this methodological reversal wouldn t be so unfortunate if the author didn t also object after what he terms rational reconstruction that a contentful account of consciousness s attempts at completion would require a level of phenomenological thickness that Sartre fails to provide. In Kantian Radical Evil and Sartrean Bad Faith, Justin Alam brings together two of the most puzzling accounts of acting against oneself in the history of philosophy, suggesting that Sartre s views on bad faith might help to solve some of the paradoxes associated with the Kantian account of evil. When dealing with the intractable problem at the centre of the Religion how to make sense of someone s choosing an evil supreme maxim Alam draws on nuanced Sartrean views of the kind of self-deception at work in cases of bad faith. Sartre s distinction between lying to others and lying to oneself makes it possible to avoid both the Belief Paradox and the Deceiver Paradox, both of which are said to threaten the Kantian account of radical evil. The subject in cases of bad faith does not simultaneously believe P and not-p, since the interpretation of poor evidence for not-p allows him to voluntarily treat it as its opposite. Because he manipulates the bare epistemic evidence, the subject is not split into deceiver and deceived in one and the same experience. On the contrary, and because bad faith is a form of faith, what is necessary is that the subject be able to take evidence supporting a given view of himself as evidence for an alternative picture that better suits him. Alam suggests that a formally similar process happens when it comes to the Kantian agent s choice of an evil maxim: insufficient evidential resources lead the agent

492 Buchbesprechungen to use a false notion of freedom (compared to genuine freedom as autonomy) as a license for self-indulgence. What remains unexplored in this paper, however, is the interesting parallel between evil as a Denkungsart or conscious mode of thinking and bad faith as an individual project. Concluding the section on metaethics, Michelle R. Darnell s The Pursuit of Happiness considers both thinkers views on the purposiveness of action. Existentialists commonly criticise Kantian ethics with regards to its formalism, its lack of concern for the concrete features of human facticity, its rootedness in a kind of noumenal freedom that prevents positive normativity, and, as a consequence of these features, its inability to provide a true model of practical reason. Darnell reminds us of two features of Kant s account of morality that jointly answer these charges: the role of happiness as an indirect duty supporting moral ends and the account s teleological form. Once we rightly understand these positive aspects of Kant s ethics, we can see how Sartre s attack can begin to be refuted. In response to existentialist critiques, it is important to stress the communitarian role played by the highest good as a final goal of moral action and to maintain its balance with the distinctly Kantian norm of autonomy. Finally, Darnell draws a positive view of happiness from Sartre s sparse ethical remarks one purified of the most salient traces of bad faith. She argues that its connection to authenticity, in which the subject s actions become building blocks in the constitution of a meaningful world, allows us to conceive of Sartrean happiness as playing a positive role. Comparative questions remain, however, the most obvious one bearing on the contrast between this quasi-revolutionary view of happiness and the Kantian teleological framework sketched above. The opening essay of the book s third part is Katherine Morris s Sartre s Method: Philosophical Therapy or Transcendental Argument? Although brief, the paper sets itself the ambitious aim of making sense, in terms of philosophical method, of Sartre s descriptions of everyday experience in BN :). Two approaches are examined one transcendental, the other therapeutic and the first is rebutted in part via Morris s deployment of the conceptual resources made available by Sartre s analysis of bad faith, which are here expanded to include a form of intellectual prejudice. The transcendental reading of Sartre s examples e. g. the approach taken by Mark Sacks and Sebastian Gardner grounds the kind of daily situations described by Sartre in undisputed premises about subjectivity, whereas the therapeutic reading, which Morris proposes, views Sartre as disputing the incontestability of these premises. The latter view construes both well-known Sartrean descriptions of figures living in bad faith the coquette, the homosexual, etc. and the daily situations that shed light on the role of negativity in human experience in terms of a phenomenological problematization of certain shared paradigms used to describe experience. In a further twist,

Buchbesprechungen 493 Morris charges defenders of the transcendental model with succumbing to bad faith themselves to the extent that their intellectual approach to Sartrean bad faith results in dogmatic views of experience. At this level, a therapeutic reading of Sartre could perhaps connect his view on the sharp contrast between appearances and reality in the descriptions of human experience with contemporary renderings such as Heidegger s of what Kant saw as the scandal of philosophy : our failure to have secured a solid argument against scepticism. Although the suggestion is historically plausible, it would involve reading Kant through a Heideggerian lens, a proposal many would shy away from. The book closes with a rich essay by Richard E. Aquila, The Transcendental Idealisms of Kant and Sartre, which again construes both philosophies as transcendental projects. Aquila s starting point is a detailed examination of the opening section of Being and Nothingness, The Pursuit of Being. Situating his inquiry in the tradition of Kant-inspired phenomenology, Sartre considered detailed examination of the ontological status of appearances themselves an absolute priority. Aquila takes this goal seriously and construes the main thematic affinity between Kant and Sartre as a form of transcendental idealism, which he calls transcendental phenomenalism. The key idea here is that, given the multivocal ontological nature of appearances, any judgment about the reality of an appearance can, without contradiction, affirm its objectivity as a phenomenon from one point of view while affirming its inscription in an infinite series of appearances that makes up the very phenomenon in question from another. As Sartre convincingly shows in BN, the ontologically open status of appearances as consciously available objects in no way amounts to a denial of their importance to the world as subjectively disclosed. Thus, any empirical judgment will involve an appeal both to the infinite series of appearances of the phenomenon in question and to the being-in-itself of its object. In the experience under assessment, however, objects are considered not as things-in-themselves but from a transcendental point of view; hence the affinity between Sartre s phenomenological ontology and the Kantian framework for describing experience. As my synopsis of the book s various essays makes clear, Sartre s metaphysical system inherits from Kant what we might call the problem of the subject, in both its epistemological and practical varieties. Comparing Kant and Sartre s most relevant contribution to Kant scholarship is therefore its compelling demonstration of how Kant s commitment to the primacy of practical reason in self-constitution and objections levelled by critical philosophy against reifying and substantializing takes on subjectivity found new life in the work of Jean-Paul Sartre, whose existentialism pushed these Kantian themes in ever more concrete directions.