Lecture One: The Aspiration for a Natural Science of the Social

Similar documents
Can Rationality Be Naturalistically Explained? Jeffrey Dunn. Abstract: Dan Chiappe and John Vervaeke (1997) conclude their article, Fodor,

PHI 1700: Global Ethics

Key definitions Action Ad hominem argument Analytic A priori Axiom Bayes s theorem

CLASS #17: CHALLENGES TO POSITIVISM/BEHAVIORAL APPROACH

Philosophy of Social Science: Lecture 3, Interpretative Social Science

Ayer s linguistic theory of the a priori

Philosophy 12 Study Guide #4 Ch. 2, Sections IV.iii VI

Logical behaviourism

Naturalized Epistemology. 1. What is naturalized Epistemology? Quine PY4613

! Jumping ahead 2000 years:! Consider the theory of the self.! What am I? What certain knowledge do I have?! Key figure: René Descartes.

Is Truth the Primary Epistemic Goal? Joseph Barnes

Business Research: Principles and Processes MGMT6791 Workshop 1A: The Nature of Research & Scientific Method

Philosophy 125 Day 1: Overview

How to Mistake a Trivial Fact About Probability For a. Substantive Fact About Justified Belief

Logic, Truth & Epistemology. Ross Arnold, Summer 2014 Lakeside institute of Theology

Chalmers, "Consciousness and Its Place in Nature"

The Problem of Induction and Popper s Deductivism

Philosophy and Methods of the Social Sciences

All philosophical debates not due to ignorance of base truths or our imperfect rationality are indeterminate.

Van Inwagen's modal argument for incompatibilism

THE TWO-DIMENSIONAL ARGUMENT AGAINST MATERIALISM AND ITS SEMANTIC PREMISE

PHILOSOPHY DEPARTMENT FALL SEMESTER 2009 COURSE OFFERINGS

Aboutness and Justification

Is there a good epistemological argument against platonism? DAVID LIGGINS

REVIEW: Marc Lange, Laws and Lawmakers: Science, Metaphysics, and the Laws of Nature.

Phil 1103 Review. Also: Scientific realism vs. anti-realism Can philosophers criticise science?

The Principle of Sufficient Reason and Free Will

SKEPTICISM, ABDUCTIVISM, AND THE EXPLANATORY GAP. Ram Neta University of North Carolina, Chapel Hill

Inductive Reasoning.

Ayer and Quine on the a priori

The Question of Metaphysics

Teaching Portfolio. 1 Introduction to the Philosophy of Causation. 2 Introduction to Classical Logic. Michael Baumgartner.

Moral Argumentation from a Rhetorical Point of View

Intro to Ground. 1. The idea of ground. 2. Relata. are facts): F 1. More-or-less equivalent phrases (where F 1. and F 2. depends upon F 2 F 2

Can moral facts be an explanation? naturalism and non-naturalism is whether or not there are any moral explanations

Epistemology Naturalized

Remarks on the philosophy of mathematics (1969) Paul Bernays

There are two common forms of deductively valid conditional argument: modus ponens and modus tollens.

Varieties of Apriority

In Defense of Pure Reason: A Rationalist Account of A Priori Justification, by Laurence BonJour. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press,

Intro. The need for a philosophical vocabulary

Causation as Metaphor a Catachresis

The normativity of content and the Frege point

IDHEF Chapter 2 Why Should Anyone Believe Anything At All?

PHIL / PSYC 351. Thinking and Reasoning

Jeu-Jenq Yuann Professor of Philosophy Department of Philosophy, National Taiwan University,

Realism and the success of science argument. Leplin:

Psillos s Defense of Scientific Realism

Merricks on the existence of human organisms

Stout s teleological theory of action

We aim to cover in some detail a number of issues currently debated in the philosophy of natural and social science.

Broad on Theological Arguments. I. The Ontological Argument

Right-Making, Reference, and Reduction

Are There Reasons to Be Rational?

Fundamentals of Metaphysics

Primitive Concepts. David J. Chalmers

Honors Ethics Oral Presentations: Instructions

1. What is Philosophy?

Honours Programme in Philosophy

Chapter 2 Test Bank. 1) When one systematically studies being or existence one is dealing with the branch of metaphysics called.

CHRISTIANITY AND THE NATURE OF SCIENCE J.P. MORELAND

Philosophy 5340 Epistemology Topic 4: Skepticism. Part 1: The Scope of Skepticism and Two Main Types of Skeptical Argument

Aspects of Western Philosophy Dr. Sreekumar Nellickappilly Department of Humanities and Social Sciences Indian Institute of Technology, Madras


Philosophy Courses-1

Argumentative Analogy versus Figurative Analogy

Introduction to Philosophy

Philosophy of Economics and Politics

Epistemicism, Parasites and Vague Names * vagueness is based on an untenable metaphysics of content are unsuccessful. Burgess s arguments are

III Knowledge is true belief based on argument. Plato, Theaetetus, 201 c-d Is Justified True Belief Knowledge? Edmund Gettier

Understanding Truth Scott Soames Précis Philosophy and Phenomenological Research Volume LXV, No. 2, 2002

Defending A Dogma: Between Grice, Strawson and Quine

KANT, MORAL DUTY AND THE DEMANDS OF PURE PRACTICAL REASON. The law is reason unaffected by desire.

Van Fraassen: Arguments Concerning Scientific Realism

Scientific Method and Research Ethics

24.01 Classics of Western Philosophy

Unit VI: Davidson and the interpretational approach to thought and language

THE REFUTATION OF PHENOMENALISM

SUPPORT MATERIAL FOR 'DETERMINISM AND FREE WILL ' (UNIT 2 TOPIC 5)

Think by Simon Blackburn. Chapter 7c The World

Falsification or Confirmation: From Logic to Psychology

YFIA205 Basics of Research Methodology in Social Sciences Lecture 1. Science, Knowledge and Theory. Jyväskylä 3.11.

A Priori Knowledge: Analytic? Synthetic A Priori (again) Is All A Priori Knowledge Analytic?

2. Refutations can be stronger or weaker.

Quine on the analytic/synthetic distinction

It doesn t take long in reading the Critique before we are faced with interpretive challenges. Consider the very first sentence in the A edition:

Philosophy of Science. Ross Arnold, Summer 2014 Lakeside institute of Theology

Lecture 4: Transcendental idealism and transcendental arguments

Reply to Robert Koons

PHI2391: Logical Empiricism I 8.0

Scientific Method and Research Ethics Questions, Answers, and Evidence. Dr. C. D. McCoy

DR. LEONARD PEIKOFF. Lecture 3 THE METAPHYSICS OF TWO WORLDS: ITS RESULTS IN THIS WORLD

Constructing the World

Philosophy Courses-1

IN his paper, 'Does Tense Logic Rest Upon a Mistake?' (to appear

A Brief History of Scientific Thoughts Lecture 5. Palash Sarkar

Critical Thinking 5.7 Validity in inductive, conductive, and abductive arguments

Four Arguments that the Cognitive Psychology of Religion Undermines the Justification of Religious Belief

The problems of induction in scientific inquiry: Challenges and solutions. Table of Contents 1.0 Introduction Defining induction...

Holtzman Spring Philosophy and the Integration of Knowledge

Transcription:

Lecture One: The Aspiration for a Natural Science of the Social Explanation These lectures presuppose that the primary task of science is to explain. This does not mean that the only task of science is to explain; description and classification are acknowledged to be important aspects of science, and not everyone thinks they are important only as tools for explanation. More importantly, not everyone thinks that social science in particular is geared towards explaining the phenomena it studies; some writers appear at least to think that interpreting is not explaining. I shall argue that the appearances are deceptive and that even they are committed to the view that explanation is the name of the game; I shall also try to show that it is (usually) possible to accept the substantive claims of such writers while (often) rejecting the philosophical glosses that they put on them. This involves working our way through ideas about makes explanations explanatory, then through a number of claims about the form that explanations in the social science ideally take: functionalist, causal, interpretative, ratonal choice and so on. What is the philosophy of science about? This is itself a philosophical question, and answers range from nothing to policing the rationality of the scientific enterprise. The argument for nothing rests on the perception that no physicist would be deterred by a philosopher telling him he was doing physics badly; conversely, physicists don t care whether philosophers endorse their work or not. Standards, on this view, are internal to a discipline, or more broadly to a practice so that I cannot, but a trained priest could, tell a new officiant how to celebrate the Eucharist. But, even a scientist who thinks that philosophers have nothing to contribute will think in addition that what she is doing is science and that doing science is interestingly different from all sorts of other activities. This presupposes at least that there is some form of science/non-science demarcation that is taken for granted in practice, but which can be elaborated on and justified. 1

(Otherwise, there is the danger of extreme relativism, where anyone can say what they like about anything, and there is no consensus on what is true/false or unassessable.) The consensus view is: i) philosophers cannot tell scientists how to do their job either natural scientists or social scientists any more than they can tell car mechanics or street cleaners how to do their jobs; ii) they can elaborate an account of the scientific enterprise in much the same way that they can give an account of art, poetry, religion etc; iii) they can in a loose sense of the term logic give an account of the logic of different sorts of explanation and understanding. The issues discussed this term fall into that broad category. One respect in which philosophy of social science is peculiar is physics envy or perhaps engineering envy. That is, the practical aims of social science have (largely) remained unrealised, whereas non-social technology has since the 18 th century advanced at an accelerating pace. Understanding why the very idea of social technology is a fraught topic with no ready analogue in philosophy of physical science. The task of science as the production of explanations; To pre-empt some later arguments: to say that science sets out to produce explanations is too quick; sometimes, we are grateful for predictions especially when they are warnings even when they do not come with explanations attached. Reliable ways of predicting earthquakes, hurricanes, epidemics would all be very worth having even if they left us as puzzled as ever about what causes them. (Think of populations reacting to plague by escaping contact with the affected, or more obscurely, people fleeing earthquakes because birds fall silent.) Opinion polling is useful to politicians, but we are not altogether sure what makes people vote one way rather than another. And to pre-empt another famous argument, the non-isomorphism of explanation and prediction goes both ways: explanations do not always produce predictions; we may be good at explaining post mortem why someone has died, but 2

still be unable to predict who will and won t die. In any non-deterministic system, prediction over more than a short period will be impossible; and even a deterministic system is indeterministic if it is open to other, non-deterministic systems. Different accounts of explanation, psychological and logical; The question is what is an explanation; or what makes an explanation explanatory. The basic distinction is between accounts that make explanatoriness a psychological matter and those that make it a matter of logic; logic is not a wholly satisfactory way of drawing the contrast, but given the salience of the so-called hypotheticodeductive account of explanation, it is more satisfactory than most alternatives. Psychological theories mostly focus on the effect on the person who asks for an explanation; and they range from the achievement of what is known as the aha effect familiar from Conan Doyle stories to what one might call the puzzlement reduction effect. A person who asks for an explanation does not see how (or why) something happens as it does; the explanation reduces that puzzlement; and may achieve the aha, now I see response. There are some obvious objections to this theory: people may have their puzzlement reduced by all sorts of things other than an explanation, familiarity in particular; more importantly, the well-conducted mind has its (rational) puzzlement reduced only by a real explanation. The psychological impact must be parasitic on the purported logical weight of the explanation. This is worth dividing into two aspects, the formal and substantive; the formal is a matter of whether if things are as the explanation says, the explanation would be sound; the substantive a matter of whether things are indeed as the explanation says. (For instance, anti-biotics combat bacterial infections only; if I give you anti-biotics and your flu gets better, it is not because of the anti-biotics because flu is caused by a virus. Formally, an explanation that runs everyone treated with anti-biotics gets over flu; Jones was treated with anti-biotics; so Jones got over flu is fine; substantively 3

it s not. And this is true even though there are many true propositions about infections that are treatable with anti-biotics.) Causal explanation and its analysis; I will run through this week briefly and next week less briefly the main claims of the so-called hypothetico-deductive account of explanation. It was for many years canonical; its pedigree goes back to Mill, to Whewell, and perhaps to Hume. One of its virtues is that it is built firmly on ordinary deductive logic; another is that it separates formal and substantive adequacy; a third is that it illuminates if it doesn t wholly explain the nature of causal explanation; a fourth is that it shows the role of generalizations and especially causal laws in explanation; and it can in Popper it is the main feature of the theory show the importance of disconfirming experiments. The shape is: explanans explains explanandum by providing a valid deductive argument in which the explanans sentences entail the explanandum sentence(s); the explanans must contain at least one general statement; and the explanans must be true or at least well-confirmed. Now we need a few examples... Causal laws and accidental generalizations. Not all requests for explanation are requests for causal explanation: eg, a demand for a translation or an interpretation of a poem or play or novel. Requests for the explanation of events are almost always causal (some are requests for meanings); imagine Jones dead on the floor, or the broken window. We want to know: what made that happen? Ordinarily, we adduce a singular causal claim the brick hit it, he swallowed cyanide; the usual h-d account is that we offer sketches of a full explanation. There are other views, eg, that we think of things as exerting natural powers. The standard empiricist view is that talk of natural powers is unacceptably metaphysical; causal connections are simply whenever A then B. This requires an 4

account of the difference between causal and accidental generalizations, which in most modern accounts has invoked the role of causal claims in supporting counterfactuals. The canonical claim is that the basic causal generalizations are laws; these strictly, are timeless and hypothetical, and have three major virtues: precision, universality, generality. That raises the nasty question: are there any laws in social science? Mill said not, for interesting reasons. Is all this misguided? The first version of naturalism clear enough to attack was Mill s in System of Logic. It duly provided the target for in particular Dilthey, who argued that there was a categorical or conceptual distinction between the sciences of nature and the sciences of culture; the former rested on causal explanation, the latter on interpretative understanding; absurdly, Mill s distinction between the physical and moral sciences those where mental phenomena were not, and were, involved which was supposed to show that both were natural sciences was translated as the distinction between Naturewissenschaften and Geisteswissenschaften, which was supposed to indicate a sharp break between them. 5