Multiple realizability and functionalism

Similar documents
The Mind/Body Problem

Kripke on the distinctness of the mind from the body

Belief, Rationality and Psychophysical Laws. blurring the distinction between two of these ways. Indeed, it will be argued here that no

CHRISTIANITY AND THE NATURE OF SCIENCE J.P. MORELAND

Saul Kripke, Naming and Necessity

Dualism: What s at stake?

BEYOND CONCEPTUAL DUALISM Ontology of Consciousness, Mental Causation, and Holism in John R. Searle s Philosophy of Mind

Verificationism. PHIL September 27, 2011

To be able to define human nature and psychological egoism. To explain how our views of human nature influence our relationships with other

Functionalism and the Chinese Room. Minds as Programs

REVIEW. Hilary Putnam, Representation and Reality. Cambridge, Nass.: NIT Press, 1988.

IN THIS PAPER I will examine and criticize the arguments David

Tony Chadwick Essay Prize 2006 Winner Can we Save Qualia? (Thomas Nagel and the Psychophysical Nexus ) By Eileen Walker

Debate on the mind and scientific method (continued again) on

Chapter 2 Human Nature

Ayer on the criterion of verifiability

Thomas Nagel, What is it like to be a bat?

Logical behaviourism

Session One: Identity Theory And Why It Won t Work Marianne Talbot University of Oxford 26/27th November 2011

Possibility and Necessity

Theories of propositions

Introduction to Philosophy Fall 2018 Test 3: Answers

The Mind-Body Problem

METAPHYSICS OF MIND. Thomas W. Polger Department of Philosophy University of Cincinnati

Review Tutorial (A Whirlwind Tour of Metaphysics, Epistemology and Philosophy of Religion)

PHILOSOPHY OF KNOWLEDGE & REALITY W E E K 4 : I M M A T E R I A L I S M, D U A L I S M, & T H E M I N D - B O D Y P R O B L E M

All philosophical debates not due to ignorance of base truths or our imperfect rationality are indeterminate.

Chalmers, "Consciousness and Its Place in Nature"

Can Rationality Be Naturalistically Explained? Jeffrey Dunn. Abstract: Dan Chiappe and John Vervaeke (1997) conclude their article, Fodor,

ON QUINE, ANALYTICITY, AND MEANING Wylie Breckenridge

Van Inwagen's modal argument for incompatibilism

Qualitative and quantitative inference to the best theory. reply to iikka Niiniluoto Kuipers, Theodorus

PHILOSOPHY OF KNOWLEDGE & REALITY W E E K 3 D A Y 2 : I M M A T E R I A L I S M, D U A L I S M, & T H E M I N D - B O D Y P R O B L E M

DNA, Information, and the Signature in the Cell

Lecture 8 Property Dualism. Frank Jackson Epiphenomenal Qualia and What Mary Didn t Know

Multiple Realizability, Qualia and Natural Kinds

1. Introduction Formal deductive logic Overview

Now consider a verb - like is pretty. Does this also stand for something?

Mistaking Category Mistakes: A Response to Gilbert Ryle. Evan E. May

Hilary Putnam (1926 )

Introduction to Philosophy Fall 2015 Test 3--Answers

Philosophy Epistemology Topic 5 The Justification of Induction 1. Hume s Skeptical Challenge to Induction

145 Philosophy of Science

Philosophy 5340 Epistemology. Topic 6: Theories of Justification: Foundationalism versus Coherentism. Part 2: Susan Haack s Foundherentist Approach

Faith and Philosophy, April (2006), DE SE KNOWLEDGE AND THE POSSIBILITY OF AN OMNISCIENT BEING Stephan Torre

General Philosophy. Dr Peter Millican,, Hertford College. Lecture 4: Two Cartesian Topics

PHILOSOPHY 4360/5360 METAPHYSICS. Methods that Metaphysicians Use

Scientific Arguments

Lecture 18: Rationalism

Determinism defined: Every event has a cause/set of causes; if its cause occurs, then the effect must follow.

Some proposals for understanding narrow content

Van Fraassen: Arguments concerning scientific realism

FOREWORD: ADDRESSING THE HARD PROBLEM OF CONSCIOUSNESS

John R. Searle, Minds, brains, and programs

Department of Philosophy TCD. Great Philosophers. Dennett. Tom Farrell. Department of Surgical Anatomy RCSI Department of Clinical Medicine RCSI

The Philosophy of Mind I. The Cartesian View of Mind: Substance Dualism A. The Basics of Mind and Body: There are four general points that, for our

Trinity & contradiction

Free will & divine foreknowledge

Philosophy 5340 Epistemology Topic 4: Skepticism. Part 1: The Scope of Skepticism and Two Main Types of Skeptical Argument

Is mental content prior to linguistic meaning?

Martin s case for disjunctivism

BonJour Against Materialism. Just an intellectual bandwagon?

The Stimulus - Possible Arguments. Humans are made solely of material Minds can be instantiated in many physical forms Others?

Please remember to sign-in by scanning your badge Department of Psychiatry Grand Rounds

Philosophy Epistemology. Topic 3 - Skepticism

Are There Reasons to Be Rational?

Minds, Brains, and Programs

Nancey Murphy, Bodies and Souls, or Spirited Bodies? (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2006). Pp. x Hbk, Pbk.

THE MEANING OF OUGHT. Ralph Wedgwood. What does the word ought mean? Strictly speaking, this is an empirical question, about the

The Mind-Body Problem

Lecture 5 Philosophy of Mind: Dualism Barbara Montero On the Philosophy of the Mind

24.09 Minds and Machines spring an inconsistent tetrad. argument for (1) argument for (2) argument for (3) argument for (4)

Meaning and Privacy. Guy Longworth 1 University of Warwick December

out in his Three Dialogues and Principles of Human Knowledge, gives an argument specifically

The Soul. 1. Introduction. 2. The Soul is an Astral Body. Eric Steinhart

THE TWO-DIMENSIONAL ARGUMENT AGAINST MATERIALISM AND ITS SEMANTIC PREMISE

Conceptual idealism without ontological idealism: why idealism is true after all

Detachment, Probability, and Maximum Likelihood

What does it mean if we assume the world is in principle intelligible?

Is the Existence of the Best Possible World Logically Impossible?

2. Refutations can be stronger or weaker.

Chapter 5: Freedom and Determinism

Merricks on the existence of human organisms

C. Exam #1 comments on difficult spots; if you have questions about this, please let me know. D. Discussion of extra credit opportunities

Causation and Free Will

Unit. Science and Hypothesis. Downloaded from Downloaded from Why Hypothesis? What is a Hypothesis?

Logic and Pragmatics: linear logic for inferential practice

Putnam, Koethe, and Metaphysical Realism

Unit VI: Davidson and the interpretational approach to thought and language

The Problem of Freewill. Blatchford, Robert, Not Guilty

Reflections on the Ontological Status

Divine omniscience, timelessness, and the power to do otherwise

Responses to the sorites paradox

Part II: How to Evaluate Deductive Arguments

BERKELEY, REALISM, AND DUALISM: REPLY TO HOCUTT S GEORGE BERKELEY RESURRECTED: A COMMENTARY ON BAUM S ONTOLOGY FOR BEHAVIOR ANALYSIS

A Philosophical Critique of Cognitive Psychology s Definition of the Person

CONCEIVABILITY ARGUMENTS KATALIN BALOG. A Dissertation submitted to the. Graduate School-New Brunswick. Rutgers, The State University of New Jersey

BOOK REVIEW: Gideon Yaffee, Manifest Activity: Thomas Reid s Theory of Action

The knowledge argument

Transcription:

Multiple realizability and functionalism phil 30304 Jeff Speaks September 4, 2018 1 The argument from multiple realizability Putnam begins The nature of mental states by agreeing with a lot of claims that we saw Smart making. Putnam agrees with Smart that it is coherent to think of the identification of pains and other mental states with brain states as the same kind of claim as other theoretical identifications in science, and agrees further that the fact that one can know that one is in pain without knowing much about one s brain state does not show that pains = brain states. (As Putnam points out, and as Smart did, if this argument was good it would count against almost any scientific theoretical identification.) His argument against the view is not that it is nonsense, but that when we look at what it would take for the identity theory to be true, we can see that it is very unlikely to be true: Consider what the brain state theorist has to do to make good his claims. He has to specify a physical-chemical state such that any organism (not just a mammal) is in pain if and only if (a) it possesses a brain of a suitable physicalchemical structure; and (b) its brain is in that physical-chemical state. This means that the physical-chemical state in question must be a possible state of a mammalian brain, a reptilian brain, a mollusc s brain... etc. At the same time it must not be a possible... state of the brain of any physically possible creature that cannot feel pain. Even if such a state can be found, it must be nomologically certain that it will also be a state of the brain of any extraterrestrial life that may be found that will be capable of feeling pain before we can even entertain the supposition that it may be pain.... Finally, the hypothesis becomes still more ambitious when we realize that the brain-state theorist is not just saying that pain is a brain state; he is, of course, concerned to maintain that every psychological state is a brain state. Thus if we can find even one psychological predicate which can clearly be applied to both a mammal and an octopus... but whose physical-chemical correlate is different in the two cases, the brain-state theory has collapsed. (436-7) Arguments of this form against identity theories of mental states are sometimes called arguments from multiple realizability. The core assumption is the assumption that very

different kinds of creatures might have certain mental properties in common like feeling a certain pain but not have the relevant physical properties in common. One might state Putnam s argument from multiple realizability against the identity theory as follows, letting M be some arbitrary mental property: 1. Distinct creatures both have M despite having no interesting physical-chemical properties in common. 2. If distinct creatures both have M despite having no interesting physicalchemical properties in common, then M is not identical to any physical-chemical property. C. M is not identical to any physical-chemical property. (1,2) How should the identity theorist respond? How would Smart reply? A different version of the argument from multiple realizability starts not with the assumption that different actual organisms have the same mental state without having the relevant physical-chemical properties in common, but with the weaker assumption that it is possible that distinct creatures have the same mental state without having the relevant physical-chemical properties in common. Surely, after all, it is possible that some alien made of silicone feel pain. That version of the argument might be stated like this: 1. It is possible that distinct creatures both have M despite having no interesting physical-chemical properties in common. 2. If it is possible that distinct creatures both have M despite having no interesting physical-chemical properties in common, then M is not identical to any physical-chemical property. C. M is not identical to any physical-chemical property. (1,2) How would Smart respond to this version of the argument? 2 Functionalism: a new theory of mental properties Though he rejects the identity theory, Putnam does not think of mental properties as non-physical properties of an immaterial soul (like Descartes) or as logical constructions out of behavior (like Ryle). Instead, he introduces a new theory of mental states, which he expresses as the view that a mental state like pain is a functional state of a whole organism. (433) What does he mean by this? He says: To explain this it is necessary to introduce some technical notions... a Probabilistic Automaton is defined [as a machine such that] the transitions between states are allowed to be with various probabilities rather than being deterministic.... I shall assume the notion of a Probabilistic Automaton has been generalized to allow for sensory inputs and motor outputs that is, the Machine Table specifies, for every possible combination of a state and a complete set of sensory inputs an instruction which determines the probability of the next state, and also the probabilities of the motor outputs.... I shall 2

also assume that the physical realization of the sense organs responsible for the various inputs, and of the motor organs, is specified, but that the states and the inputs themselves are, as usual, specified only implicitly i.e. by the set of transition probabilities given by the Machine Table. Are you a probabilistic automaton, in this sense? Putnam s idea is that whether you have a certain mental property is determined by what sort of probabilistic automaton you are. To see how, exactly, this is supposed to work, it will be useful to have a look at the way functionalism is introduced in David Lewis Psychophysical and theoretical identifications (on the web site as an optional reading). Lewis introduces functionalism via his example of the detective story: We are assembled in the drawing room of the country house; the detective reconstructs the crime. That is, he proposes a theory designed to be the best explanation of phenomena we have observed: the death of Mr. Body, the blood on the wallpaper, the silence of the dog in the night, the clock seventeen minutes fast, and so on. He launches into his story: X, Y and Z conspired to murder Mr. Body. Seventeen years ago, in the gold fields of Uganda, X was Body s partner... Last week, Y and Z conferred in a bar in Reading... Tuesday night at l1:17, Y went to the attic and set a time bomb... Seventeen minutes later, X met Z in the billiard room and gave him the lead pipe... Just when the bomb went off in the attic, X fired three shots into the study through the French windows... And so it goes: a long story. Let us pretend that it is a single long conjunctive sentence. The story contains the three names X, Y and Z. The detective uses these new terms without explanation, as though we knew what they meant. But we do not. We never used them before, at least not in the senses they bear in the present context. All we know about their meanings is what we gradually gather from the story itself. (250) The point of this is that there is a sense in which the story describes, or purports to describe, three people. X stands for whoever did the stuff the story ascribes to X, Y stands for whoever did the stuff the story ascribes to Y etc. Another way to put that is that there is a certain role in the story corresponding to each of these letters. For the letter to stand for a person is for the person to realize that role: Suppose that after we have heard the detective s story, we learn that it is true of a certain three people: Plum, Peacock and Mustard. If we put the name Plum in place of X, Peacock in place of Y, and Mustard in place of Z throughout, we get a true story about the doings of those three people. We will say that Plum, Peacock and Mustard together realize (or are a realization of) the detective s theory. (251) 3

Lewis s idea is that words for mental states, like feels pain and believes that there is beer in the fridge, are like the letters in the detective story: they stand for whatever state realizes a certain role. In the case of mental properties, in place of a detective story we have a story about the connections between sensory inputs, mental states, and behavioral outputs. Suppose, for example, we are interested in the mental property believes that there is beer in the fridge. Then our story might include claims like the following: he will believe that there is beer in the refrigerator. If someone wants beer and believes that there is beer in the refrigerator, then he will go to the refrigerator and get a beer. If someone believes that there is beer in the refrigerator, then he believes that there is beer somewhere. If someone believes that there is a Budweiser in the refrigerator, then he believes that there is beer in the refrigerator. If someone intends to get a beer out of the refrigerator, then he believes that there is a beer in the refrigerator. If we think of claims like these as comprising a (somewhat boring) story, then the story has a number of characters. One of these characters is the belief that there is beer in the refrigerator: he will believe that there is beer in the refrigerator. If someone wants beer and believes that there is beer in the refrigerator, then he will go to the refrigerator and get a beer. If someone believes that there is beer in the refrigerator, then he believes that there is beer somewhere. If someone believes that there is a Budweiser in the refrigerator, then he believes that there is beer in the refrigerator. If someone intends to get a beer out of the refrigerator, then he believes that there is a beer in the refrigerator. As in the detective story, let s introduce a label for the belief that there is beer in the refrigerator; let s call it state X : he will be in state X. If someone wants beer and is in state X, then he will go to the refrigerator and get a beer. If someone is in state X, then he believes that there is beer somewhere. 4

If someone believes that there is a Budweiser in the refrigerator, then he is in state X. If someone intends to get a beer out of the refrigerator, then he is in state X. As in the case of the detective story, corresponding to this label state X is a certain role in the story: state X stands for whatever state one is in when one is in front of an open refrigerator which has beer in it, and which, together with the desire for beer, causes one to go to the refrigerator and get a beer, and which one is in when one believes that there is a Budweiser in the fridge.... In the case of the detective story, we said that a person could realize one of the roles in the story if they did all of the things which the role included. Just so, in this case, we can say that an internal state of a person can realize the state X role in our story if it does all of the things included in the role. What is the property of believing that there is beer in the fridge? It is the property of having a state which realizes the role laid out in claims like the ones above. (Of course, a realistic story will contain many more claims.) How might this work for the property of having a toothache? If you understand all of that, then you can understand functionalism. Functionalism is the idea that we can tell a (much longer) story like this for every mental property. Each one of these stories defines, corresponding to each mental property, a certain role (sometimes called a functional role). What it is for someone to have that mental property, according to the functionalist, is for them to have some state which realizes that role. Let s consider a few objections to functionalism, as stated. Objection 1: the theory is circular, since it defines one mental property in terms of other mental properties. This is correct. Really, to explain the functional role with which a mental state is identified, we would have to replace every occurrence of a term for a mental state with a label. So our example would really be more like he will be in state X. If someone is in state Y and is in state X, then he will go to the refrigerator and get a beer. If someone is in state X, then he is in state Z. If someone is in state A, then he is in state X. If someone is in state B, then he is in state X. This makes it more like the example of the detective story, in which we have multiple characters. Does the view look less plausible when we make it non-circular? 5

Objection 2: no person has states which exactly fit the above functional role. After all, it is not always the case that when I desire a beer and believe that there is a beer in the fridge, I will go to the fridge and get the beer. This is why Putnam characterizes his theory in terms of a probabilistic, rather than a deterministic, automaton. If we think that psychological laws will always be merely probabilistic, it seems that any plausible functionalist theory will have to be qualified to respect this fact. Objection 3: Putnam s super-super-spartans don t have any state which realizes the functional role of pain, since they have no state which typically causes them to wince, cry out, etc. But, despite this, they feel pain. So the same examples which show that behaviorism is false also show that functionalism is false. How would Putnam respond to this objection? 3 Is functionalism a form of materialism? The kind of functionalist theory we have been talking about seems very different than Descartes view of mental properties. But Putnam says that his theory is not incompatible with dualism. What s going on? Let s suppose that we have some description of the functional role of pain call this the pain role. Then Putnam s theory is: The property of being in pain = the property of having some state which plays the pain role. State here seems to mean just property. So we could restate the view as The property of being in pain = the property of having some property which plays the pain role. Playing the pain role is what is sometimes called a higher-order property: it is a property of properties. In my case, a property of neurons might have this higher-order property; in the case of an alien, it might be some property of a bunch of silicone; in the case of an angel, it might be some non-physical property. So far as the functionalist is concerned, which property plays this role does not matter to feel pain is just to have some property or other which plays this role. So it is unlike the identity theory in that it is compatible with substance dualism; but it is unlike Descartes view in that it is compatible with materialism. How does functionalism fare with respect to the problems we have seen for the other three views of mental properties we have discussed? 6