Philosophy 125 Day 13: Overview

Similar documents
Philosophy 125 Day 12: Overview

Philosophy 125 Day 4: Overview

Retrospective Remarks on Events (Kim, Davidson, Quine) Philosophy 125 Day 20: Overview. The Possible & The Actual I: Intensionality of Modality 2

Nominalism III: Austere Nominalism 1. Philosophy 125 Day 7: Overview. Nominalism IV: Austere Nominalism 2

Lecture 3: Properties II Nominalism & Reductive Realism. Lecture 3: Properties II Nominalism & Reductive Realism

Philosophy 125 Day 21: Overview

Philosophy 125 Day 8: Overview

Early Russell on Philosophical Grammar

Are All Universals Instantiated?

Philosophy 125 Day 1: Overview

Primitive Thisness and Primitive Identity by Robert Merrihew Adams (1979)

Fundamentals of Metaphysics

Metaphysics. A contemporary introduction. Michael J. Loux. Third edition

Presentism and eterrnalism HAROLD W. NOONAN. Department of Philosophy. University of Nottingham. Nottingham, NG72RD, UK. Tel: +44 (0)

Ibn Sina on Substances and Accidents

Nathan Oaklander IS THERE A DIFFERENCE BETWEEN ABSOLUTE AND RELATIVE SPACE?

CONTENTS A SYSTEM OF LOGIC

ARMSTRONGIAN PARTICULARS WITH NECESSARY PROPERTIES *

5 The necessary and the possible

From Transcendental Logic to Transcendental Deduction

The Ten Categories of Being. The Primacy of Substance

III Knowledge is true belief based on argument. Plato, Theaetetus, 201 c-d Is Justified True Belief Knowledge? Edmund Gettier

Van Fraassen: Arguments Concerning Scientific Realism

Saving the Substratum: Interpreting Kant s First Analogy

Bare Particulars. Theodore Sider Philosophical Perspectives 20 (2006),

Each copy of any part of a JSTOR transmission must contain the same copyright notice that appears on the screen or printed page of such transmission.

The British Empiricism

Tom Vinci. Dalhousie University

Postscript to Plenitude of Possible Structures (2016)

SIMPLICITY AND ASEITY. Jeffrey E. Brower. There is a traditional theistic doctrine, known as the doctrine of divine simplicity,

Armstrongian Particulars with Necessary Properties

Putnam: Meaning and Reference

CONTENTS III SYNTHETIC A PRIORI JUDGEMENTS. PREFACE CHAPTER INTRODUCTldN

Kantian Humility and Ontological Categories Sam Cowling University of Massachusetts, Amherst

Compresence is a Bundle A Problem for the Bundle Theory of Objects

Resemblance Nominalism and counterparts

THE PROBLEM WITH SOCIAL TRINITARIANISM: A REPLY TO WIERENGA

PHILOSOPHICAL PROBLEMS & THE ANALYSIS OF LANGUAGE

Primitive Thisness and Primitive Identity Robert Merrihew Adams

12. A Theistic Argument against Platonism (and in Support of Truthmakers and Divine Simplicity)

A Review of Neil Feit s Belief about the Self

Unifying the Categorical Imperative* Marcus Arvan University of Tampa

Possibility and Necessity

Book Reviews. The Metaphysics of Relations, by Anna Marmodoro and David Yates. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2016, 304 pages, ISBN:

Being and Substance Aristotle

What is an Argument? Validity vs. Soundess of Arguments

Humean Supervenience: Lewis (1986, Introduction) 7 October 2010: J. Butterfield

SMITH ON TRUTHMAKERS 1. Dominic Gregory. I. Introduction

Universals. If no: Then it seems that they could not really be similar. If yes: Then properties like redness are THINGS.

BOOK REVIEWS. The arguments of the Parmenides, though they do not refute the Theory of Forms, do expose certain problems, ambiguities and

Hume on Ideas, Impressions, and Knowledge

the aim is to specify the structure of the world in the form of certain basic truths from which all truths can be derived. (xviii)

The Relationist and Substantivalist Theories of Time: Foes or Friends?

Abstract Abstraction Abundant ontology Abundant theory of universals (or properties) Actualism A-features Agent causal libertarianism

Overview of Today s Lecture

Intro to Philosophy. Review for Exam 2

Russell s Problems of Philosophy

The Unmoved Mover (Metaphysics )

SIMON BOSTOCK Internal Properties and Property Realism

Broad on Theological Arguments. I. The Ontological Argument

The Work Of The Holy Spirit

Constructing the World

On possibly nonexistent propositions

1. Introduction. Against GMR: The Incredulous Stare (Lewis 1986: 133 5).

Bertrand Russell Proper Names, Adjectives and Verbs 1

The Relation of Compresence in the Bundle Theory: Four Problems

FOUNDATIONS OF EMPIRICISM

CONCRETE UNIVERSALS AND SPATIAL RELATIONS* ANTTI KESKINEN University of Tampere. MARKKU KAINÄNEN University of Helsinki

Evaluating Classical Identity and Its Alternatives by Tamoghna Sarkar

A Rate of Passage. Tim Maudlin

The Greatest Mistake: A Case for the Failure of Hegel s Idealism

Analyticity and reference determiners

Philosophy 148 Announcements & Such. Inverse Probability and Bayes s Theorem II. Inverse Probability and Bayes s Theorem III

ISSN , Volume 73, Number 1

World without Design: The Ontological Consequences of Natural- ism , by Michael C. Rea.

Against the Vagueness Argument TUOMAS E. TAHKO ABSTRACT

Is phenomenal character out there in the world?

Direct Realism and the Brain-in-a-Vat Argument by Michael Huemer (2000)

Theories of propositions

CONTENTS. INTRODUCTORY Chapter I ETHICAL NEUTRALITY AND PRAGMATISM

Properties as parts of ordinary objects. Eric T. Olson To appear in J. Keller, ed., Being, Freedom, and Method: Themes from van Inwagen, OUP.

Primitive Concepts. David J. Chalmers

Kripke on the distinctness of the mind from the body

Aspects of Western Philosophy Dr. Sreekumar Nellickappilly Department of Humanities and Social Sciences Indian Institute of Technology, Madras

George Berkeley. The Principles of Human Knowledge. Review

Philosophy Conference University of Patras, Philosophy Department 4-5 June, 2015

WHY THERE REALLY ARE NO IRREDUCIBLY NORMATIVE PROPERTIES

Physicalism and Conceptual Analysis * Esa Díaz-León.

R. M. Hare (1919 ) SINNOTT- ARMSTRONG. Definition of moral judgments. Prescriptivism

Why Four-Dimensionalism Explains Coincidence

Fred Wilson UNIVERSALS, PARTICULARS, TROPES AND BLOBS

Spinoza on the Essence, Mutability and Power of God

Issue 4, Special Conference Proceedings Published by the Durham University Undergraduate Philosophy Society

Properties as parts of ordinary objects. Eric T. Olson To appear in J. Keller, ed., Being, Freedom, and Method: Themes from van Inwagen, OUP.

Noonan, Harold (2010) The thinking animal problem and personal pronoun revisionism. Analysis, 70 (1). pp ISSN

DO WE NEED A THEORY OF METAPHYSICAL COMPOSITION?

Introductory Kant Seminar Lecture

What does it mean if we assume the world is in principle intelligible?

In Defense of Pure Reason: A Rationalist Account of A Priori Justification, by Laurence BonJour. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press,

Transcription:

Branden Fitelson Philosophy 125 Lecture 1 Philosophy 125 Day 13: Overview Reminder: Due Date for 1st Papers and SQ s, October 16 (next Th!) Zimmerman & Hacking papers on Identity of Indiscernibles online Handouts on Rigidity, Abstract Reference, and Predication and Aristotle s Division of the World are also posted online Concrete Particulars (Cont d) The Identity of Indiscernibles (II) The (II) Argument Against Realist Bundle Theory Is (II) false? (Hawthorne/Zimmerman/Hacking) Remarks on Trope Versions of Bundle Theory An Argument for Substratum Theory Problems with Substratum Theory Aristotelian Substance: A Happy Medium?

Branden Fitelson Philosophy 125 Lecture 2 Concrete Particulars VIII: Objection #2 to Bundle Theory 1 The Identity of Indiscernibles (II) Argument against Realist Bundle Theory is as follows. The realist bundle theorist accepts both (PCI) and (BT). (PCI) Agreement on all constituents entails identity. (BT) The constituents of a particular are (just) its properties. But, (PCI) and (BT) jointly imply the Identity of Indiscernibles (II): (II) Agreement on all properties entails identity. But, or so the argument continues, (II) is false. That is, it is possible for a and b to share all properties and for a and b to be numerically distinct (i.e., a b). So, the realist bundle theorist must reject either (PCI) or (BT), or both. But, (PCI) seems clearly true, and it is accepted by all parties. So, it seems that (BT) must be rejected (unless counterexamples to (II) can be blocked). Hence, the debate about realist bundle theory hinges on (II). Is it false?

Branden Fitelson Philosophy 125 Lecture 3 Concrete Particulars IX: Objection #2 to Bundle Theory 2 Loux (Black) considers a universe containing only two spheres (a and b). The spheres have the same shape, color, mass, texture, size, etc. Indeed, they seem to share all properties. As Loux puts it they are so similar that no one can tell the difference between them. Could this be a counterexample to (II)? What about the properties A = being identical with a, and B = being identical with b. Don t a and b fail to share these properties? After all, a exemplifies property A, but b does not, and b exemplifies property B, but a does not. Loux argues that the (realist) bundle theorist is not allowed to appeal to such properties, since such properties presuppose an irreducible notion of a particular: one that cannot be be understood as a bundle of attributes without simply begging the question at hand. Such properties are impure. This leads Loux to formulate a revised version of realist bundle theory (BT). (BT*) The constituents of a particular are (just) its pure properties. (BT*) and (PCI) entail something stronger than (II), namely:

Branden Fitelson Philosophy 125 Lecture 4 (II*) Agreement on all pure properties entails identity. This seems to be an argument against (realist) bundle theory that cannot be escaped by appealing to properties like A and B, which are patently impure. But, it is impossible for two different concrete objects to occupy the same region of space at a given time. So, no two concrete objects will agree with respect to those properties that specify their spatiotemporal location either. In a rebuttal on behalf of the substratum theorist, Loux says:... these properties are one and all impure. [the substratum theorist] will argue that since space and time represent relational structures, the properties that specify the spatiotemporal position of concrete objects are always properties like being 2 miles north of the Eiffel Tower properties that already presuppose or involve concrete particulars and so cannot number among the items the bundle theorist construes as constituents of concrete objects. This seems to depend on whether space-time itself is taken to be a substance as opposed to a bundle of relations. Newton vs Leibniz! [See Hacking.] Turn the tables: Why does the substratum theorist think there are two spheres here?

Branden Fitelson Philosophy 125 Lecture 5 Concrete Particulars X: Another Way Out? (Zimmerman/Hawthorne) Zimmerman (and Hawthorne) formulate another possible response to the (II)-objection on behalf of the realist bundle theorist. They suggest that the realist embrace horn #1 of the age-old Parmenidean Dilemma (Lecture 6). Recall, this horn assumes that universals are entirely located where each of their exemplifiers are located. E.g., Redness is entirely within each red sphere. On this account, universals are immanent and separate from themselves. NOTE: We are not talking about tropes here! We are talking about single universals (e.g., Courage) being located in two different places at one time. Nobody thinks that particulars are capable of this, but, as David Lewis says, this intuition was clearly made for particulars, and there may be no reason to suppose that this should also apply to universals. How does this help? If universals can be (entirely) in two places at once, then the fact that the spheres are spatially separated is not decisive in determining whether they are one and the same could be one bundle of universals, separated from itself.

Branden Fitelson Philosophy 125 Lecture 6 Concrete Particulars XI: An Argument for Substratum Theory Many people view the above argument [from not (II*) and (PCI) to not (BT*)] as a refutation of the metaphysical realist version of bundle theory [(BT*)]. Thinking more deeply bout these conditions leads, according to Loux, to a persuasive positive argument in favor of substratum theory. If (II*) is false, then there will be distinct particulars which (nonetheless) share all pure properties. For instance, think about our spheres a and b. If this is a counterexample, then a and b will share all pure properties. And, their impure properties are not useful for determining their constituents...... since our aim is to identify the constituents out of which concrete particulars are composed, the items we appeal to... cannot already presuppose the complex entities that are concrete particulars, and impure properties all do. No... impure... properties can explain the [nonidentity] of [a and b]. But, since (PCI) is true, and a b, there must be some constituent they do not share, which is not determined by any attributes a or b has bare substrata!

Branden Fitelson Philosophy 125 Lecture 7 Concrete Particulars XII: Problems for Substratum Theory 1 We already hinted at one objection to substratum theory: the epistemology of bare substrata. How can we be acquainted with or know about bare substrata? Interestingly, many bare substratum theorists (e.g., Locke, Bergmann) have been self-identifying empiricists! They have various replies to this worry: To be acquainted with numerically diverse, yet qualitatively indiscernible objects is eo ipso to be acquainted with bare substrata. Being confronted with a pair of objects related as Black s two red balls, a and b, are, we are in a perceptual context where the principles of numerical diversity in them make themselves apparent to us (how?). Since the attribute and subject are correlative concepts, it is impossible to be acquainted with an attribute without being acquainted with its subject. If attributes can be the objects of empirical awareness, so can the substrata that literally possess them (since they are the true subjects). This sounds question-begging and disingenuous. The bare substratum was not motivated on epistemic, but conceptual grounds. That should be their reply.

Branden Fitelson Philosophy 125 Lecture 8 Concrete Particulars XIII: Problems for Substratum Theory 2 Is the substratum theory even coherent? It seems to be saying: things that possess attributes are bare. But to be bare is to possess no attribute. So, are we to infer that things which possess attributes possess no attributes? There is an ambiguity in possess. To be fair, what the substratum theory is saying is that bare substrata (hence, particulars) do not possess any of their attributes necessarily All particulars have all their attributes contingently. In other words, the view is that none of the attributes of a substratum are essential to the substratum. None are constitutive of it (or of its identity). Note: This makes it clear that bundle theory (on Loux s reconstruction) and substratum theory are diametrically opposed on the question Which attributes do particulars have necessarily? Loux s BT: all; ST: none. We have already seen that it s pretty crazy to claim that particulars have all their attributes necessarily. It s also pretty weird (naively) to say they have none of their attributes necessarily. At this point, Loux rightly speculates:

Branden Fitelson Philosophy 125 Lecture 9 We are told, for example, that bare substrata have no attributes essentially; but what of this feature of bare substrata? Is it one that is merely contingently true of bare substrata? Likewise, bare substrata are said to be the literal bearers of attributes. Is this a merely contingent feature of bare substrata? Is it possible that things could be otherwise, so that not they, but some other entities played this role? Again, bare substrata are said to be the principles of numerical diversity. Might they have failed to diversify objects?... There seem to be properties that are essential to everything. E.g., the property of being self-identical, the property of being red or not red, or colored if red. There also seem to be properties that are essential to some things but not others. E.g., the property of not being identical to the number 7, the property of being red or non-red, or (perhaps) the property of being a human being. So, it seems, if there are substrata, they will have some attributes necessarily. But, if that is so, then we seem to be off on a regress. The substratum theorist now needs a new (finer-grained) substratum to serve as the literal bearer of these (essential) attributes. But, they will have some essential features...

Branden Fitelson Philosophy 125 Lecture 10 Concrete Particulars XIV: Remarks on Trope Bundle Theory The (II) argument is irrelevant to the trope version of bundle theory. No two things can share a trope. And, even if two tropes are similar, they are nonetheless distinct. So, there are no trope counterexamples to (II)! On Loux s reconstruction of trope bundle theory, bundles (which are just sets) have their members necessarily (sound familiar?). It follows that all particulars have all their attributes necessarily. But, this seems absurd. It seems that Socrates is courageous is contingent, not necessary. But, a trope bundle theorist (on Loux s rendition) cannot say (or account for) this. Perhaps we can try our non-rigidity trick here. What if we say that Socrates denotes the set of compresent attributes that we call Socrates. Surely, this is not rigid. So, it does allow Socrates to have (at least) some of his attributes contingently. But, does this lead to a satisfying explanation of the contingency of his properties? Why is Socrates contingently courageous? Hint: Is this because we might have used the name Socrates differently?

Branden Fitelson Philosophy 125 Lecture 11 Concrete Particulars XV: Aristotelian Substance 1 It seems we re faced with a choice between extremes. We can choose a theory which says that all attributes of all particulars are contingent (substratum), or we can choose a theory which says that all attributes of all particulars are necessary (standard bundle). a This seems to leave us with only two options: Go for Austere Nominalism, and deny that particulars are complexes. Or, go for a (non-rigid?) trope bundle theory (avoids (II)-argument). But, of course, this is a false dichotomy, since All X s are Y s and No X s are Y s do not exhaust the logically possible cases. A common-sensical view might be that some attributes of particulars are necessary and some are not. Loux recommends an Aristotelian account, which is like Austere nominalism in denying that particulars are complexes, but also employs a realism about universals in a way that makes some attributes necessary and some contingent. a Loux s second horn: a theory accepting (II), rather than a theory making all attributes necessary. Puzzle: why doesn t Loux state the dilemma in the obvious way here? Why retreat to (II)? Study Q.

Branden Fitelson Philosophy 125 Lecture 12 Concrete Particulars XVI: Aristotelian Substance 2 Aristotle s theory of matter and substance is subtle (it s also controversial as to what the theory is this is covered in John MacFarlane s 25A class). We ll try to keep this as simple as possible. See my handout for a more detailed picture. First, I ll try to present a picture of Aristotle s conception of substance. Then, I ll mention some problems with this picture (without too much detail). Generally, Aristotle held concrete particulars to be organic wholes, without metaphysical constituents (this aspect is like Austere Nominalism). These wholes are organized (teleologically) into kinds, which tell us what things are. E.g., Socrates is an animal. Socrates has some properties essentially (e.g., Humanhood), and others contingently (e.g., Courage). Socrates essentially (and proximally) belongs to the kind Human (infimum): that s what he is. There is a hierarchy of kinds, to which things belong essentially. Kinds at the bottom (infima) of the hierarchy are the most determinative of what things are.

Branden Fitelson Philosophy 125 Lecture 13 Concrete Particulars XVII: Aristotelian Substance 3 Secondary Substance Substance Animal Cat Human Virtue Justice Quale Knowledge Grammatical Knowledge Color White other eig ht non-substance Categories Universal non-substance Primary Substance my cat Socrates (concrete particulars) Socrates bit of gramm. knowledge (tropes?) A bit of white in Socrates teeth Particular non-substance Aristotle s Division of The World has 10 Categories, divided into Substance and Non-Substance. biological (and perhaps physical) kinds are substantive, but qualities (e.g., colors), quantities, (e.g., wavelength), and the other 8 are not. Particulars (e.g., Socrates) belong to kinds in their Category (e.g., Human) essentially, and have properties in other categories (e.g., Virtue) contingently. Kinds at bottom of tree are infima they determine what things under them are.

Branden Fitelson Philosophy 125 Lecture 14 Concrete Particulars XVIII: Aristotelian Substance 4 Loux s Aristotelian view of substance (concrete particular) vs bundle theory. The bundle theorist (on Loux s reconstruction) treats all attributes as essential or necessary. This is superessentialism, as Loux calls it. Can this be avoided? [Study question at end of my rigidity handout.] Aristotle takes some universals (kinds) to be exemplified (belonged to) necessarily, and others (qualities, etc.) to be exemplified accidentally. Bundle theory restricts the constitutive attributes to properties (no kinds). Can t the realist bundle theorist include kinds? If not, why not? S.Q. Aristotle s distinction between kinds and properties is crucial for his view. Aristotle s kinds demarcate what concrete particulars are. This is why they are essential to particulars, and properties are not. Kinds sets! Point of agreement: the being of a particular is grounded in the attributes it has (for Arsitotle, the kinds to which it belongs: the answer to What is it? ).

Branden Fitelson Philosophy 125 Lecture 15 Concrete Particulars XIX: Aristotelian Substance 5 Loux s Aristotelian view of substance (concrete particular) vs substratum Th. Substratum: the subject of attribution is a constituent of the particular. Aristotle: the subject of attribution is just is the (organic) particular itself. Substratum: Subject must exist independently of all attributes it bears. Aristotle: Subject exists independently of its contingent attributes only. Substratum: Bare substratum explains how (II) can be false (diversifier). Aristotle: Multiple exemplification of kinds explains how (II) can be false. How? I don t see this. [Study Question.] Loux simply asserts that: Aristotelians deny that there is a special problem of explaining how concrete particulars can be numerically different from each other. They insist that the multiple instantiation of a kind is, by itself, sufficient to secure the existence of numerically different particulars. Each of its instantiations is a particular that is numerically different from the others. Points of Agreement: the attributes associated with a particular require a subject, and the Identity of Indiscernibles princ. (II) is false (anachronistic?).