think that people are generally moral relativists. I will argue that people really do believe in moral

Similar documents
Can moral facts be an explanation? naturalism and non-naturalism is whether or not there are any moral explanations

Relativism and Subjectivism. The Denial of Objective Ethical Standards

Chapter 2 Ethical Concepts and Ethical Theories: Establishing and Justifying a Moral System

Adapted from The Academic Essay: A Brief Anatomy, for the Writing Center at Harvard University by Gordon Harvey. Counter-Argument

AN OUTLINE OF CRITICAL THINKING

24.02 Moral Problems and the Good Life

What should I believe? What should I believe when people disagree with me?

In Epistemic Relativism, Mark Kalderon defends a view that has become

24.03: Good Food 2/15/17

24.00: Problems of Philosophy Prof. Sally Haslanger November 16, 2005 Moral Relativism

Ethics is subjective.

Henrik Ahlenius Department of Philosophy ETHICS & RESEARCH

World-Wide Ethics. Chapter Two. Cultural Relativism

Defining Relativism Ethical Relativism is the view that the rightness or wrongness of an action depends partially upon the beliefs and culture of the

Richard van de Lagemaat Relative Values A Dialogue

Choosing Rationally and Choosing Correctly *

Chapter 2 Reasoning about Ethics

James Rachels. Ethical Egoism

Logic, Truth & Epistemology. Ross Arnold, Summer 2014 Lakeside institute of Theology

WHY RELATIVISM IS NOT SELF-REFUTING IN ANY INTERESTING WAY

Searle vs. Chalmers Debate, 8/2005 with Death Monkey (Kevin Dolan)

Humanity's future with other races

Jackson College Introduction to World Religions Philosophy Winter 2016 Syllabus

6.041SC Probabilistic Systems Analysis and Applied Probability, Fall 2013 Transcript Lecture 3

Moral Relativism and the Argument from Disagreement

Building Your Framework everydaydebate.blogspot.com by James M. Kellams

Drafting an Argument. Main Page. Rogerian Method. Page 1 of 11

RELATIVISM, FAULTLESSNESS, AND THE EPISTEMOLOGY OF DISAGREEMENT

[name] [course] [teaching assistant s name] [discussion day and time] [question being answered] [date turned in] Cultural Relativism

Noncognitivism in Ethics, by Mark Schroeder. London: Routledge, 251 pp.

Chapter 2 Normative Theories of Ethics

The St. Petersburg paradox & the two envelope paradox

6.041SC Probabilistic Systems Analysis and Applied Probability, Fall 2013 Transcript Lecture 21

Introduction. Strategies

The activity It is important to set ground rules to provide a safe environment where students are respected as they explore their own viewpoints.

Comments on Lasersohn

Carnap s Non-Cognitivism as an Alternative to Both Value- Absolutism and Value-Relativism

Take Home Exam #1. PHI 1700: Global Ethics Prof. Lauren R. Alpert

What is the "Social" in "Social Coherence?" Commentary on Nelson Tebbe's Religious Freedom in an Egalitarian Age

Review of Nathan M. Nobis s Truth in Ethics and Epistemology

Boghossian & Harman on the analytic theory of the a priori

>> Marian Small: I was talking to a grade one teacher yesterday, and she was telling me

February s Reflection with Merlin Page 1

Running Head: AGENT VERSUS APPRAISER MORAL RELATIVISM. Agent Versus Appraiser Moral Relativism: An Exploratory Study. Author note

Theories of epistemic justification can be divided into two groups: internalist and

Lecture 6 Workable Ethical Theories I. Based on slides 2011 Pearson Education, Inc. Publishing as Pearson Addison-Wesley

MITOCW MITRES18_006F10_26_0703_300k-mp4

No Love for Singer: The Inability of Preference Utilitarianism to Justify Partial Relationships

Faith and Reason in a Postmodern World

Why are they here? William C. Treurniet and Paul Hamden

6.080 / Great Ideas in Theoretical Computer Science Spring 2008

Moral Relativism and the Problem of Immersion

The Critical Mind is A Questioning Mind

Handout Two: Argument Construction in Impromptu Speaking

Ethics. The study of right or correct behavior

* EXCERPT * Audio Transcription. Court Reporters Certification Advisory Board. Meeting, April 1, Judge William C.

There are various different versions of Newcomb s problem; but an intuitive presentation of the problem is very easy to give.

Introduction to Technical Communications 21W.732 Section 2 Ethics in Science and Technology Formal Paper #2

Extraterrestrial involvement with the human race

Do we have responsibilities to future generations? Chris Groves

MITOCW watch?v=ppqrukmvnas

PHI 1700: Global Ethics

Content Area Variations of Academic Language

Ethics Prof. Vineet Sahu Department of Humanities and Social Sciences Indian Institute of Technology-Kanpur

Does Morality Require God? 2010 James Gray

METAETHICAL MORAL RELATIVISM AND THE ANALOGY WITH PHYSICS

My First Teaching Intuition

24.01: Classics of Western Philosophy

OC THINK TANK - CLOSING THE BACK DOOR

Page 1 of 16 Spirituality in a changing world: Half say faith is important to how they consider society s problems

Moral Relativism and Conceptual Analysis. David J. Chalmers

Positions 1 and 2 are rarely useful in academic discourse Issues, evidence, underpinning assumptions, context etc. make arguments complex and nuanced

(i) Morality is a system; and (ii) It is a system comprised of moral rules and principles.

How to Generate a Thesis Statement if the Topic is Not Assigned.

The 20 Universal Laws. from Dick Sutphen s book Lighting the Light Within

CHRISTIAN COMMUNICATORS OF OHIO SPEECH AND DEBATE PROGRAM

J O S H I A H

The Pleasure Imperative

Toward a Vision. for Christian Education. A study tool for congregational education leaders

The Global Church Member Survey 2018 David Trim

Genesis 6-9: Does 'All' Always Mean All?

Situational Ethics Actions often cannot be evaluated in a vacuum. Suppose someone moves their hand rapidly forward, is that action right or wrong? The

HOW TO PRESENT THE HOLY SPIRIT BOOKLET

Philosophy of Ethics Philosophy of Aesthetics. Ross Arnold, Summer 2014 Lakeside institute of Theology

III Knowledge is true belief based on argument. Plato, Theaetetus, 201 c-d Is Justified True Belief Knowledge? Edmund Gettier

Suppose... Kant. The Good Will. Kant Three Propositions


THE CONCEPT OF OWNERSHIP by Lars Bergström

Rationality and Cooperation. Julian Nida-Rümelin Helsinki October 10th, 2007

SATISFICING CONSEQUENTIALISM AND SCALAR CONSEQUENTIALISM

4 Liberty, Rationality, and Agency in Hobbes s Leviathan

Listening Guide. Worldview Basics. A Comparison of Major Worldviews. WE102 Lesson 03 of 05

The World Forum of Spiritual Culture, Astana, Kazakhstan October

The Challenge of Cultural Relativism. James Rachels 1986 Ethics & Contemporary Issues Professor Douglas Olena

Phenomenal Knowledge, Dualism, and Dreams Jesse Butler, University of Central Arkansas

IS ACT-UTILITARIANISM SELF-DEFEATING?

Truth, Faith, and Knowledge By Travis Dickinson

1) What is the universal structure of a topicality violation in the 1NC, shell version?

Predictability, Causation, and Free Will

WHAT IS SUFISM Ali Ansari June 8, 07

Transcription:

It is often assumed that people are moral absolutists. Although Paul Boghossian supports this claim by seemingly defeating every reasonable type of relativism, Sarkissian et al. provide reason to think that people are generally moral relativists. I will argue that people really do believe in moral relativism, but that we think that all humans should agree to one universal moral code by which any member of our society should abide. I will develop and examine this argument in more detail, and argue that my theory not only explains the data from Sarkissian et al. but that it also overcomes one of Boghossian's arguments against relativism. It may seem contradictory to argue that we are relativists but at the same time we want to have a universal moral code, so I should clarify. When I say people are relativists, I mean that they don't think that there actually is an objectively true moral code that exists outside the scope of human existence. Instead, people think that humans have had a part in creating the moral code that we abide by. That is, when I say that people believe everyone should abide by a universal moral code, I am not saying that such a moral code is objectively true or right. Instead, humans try to create the optimal moral code for our society, where optimal means some combination of practical, beneficial, and reasonable, among other criteria. For example, killing people may be against our moral code because it makes our society more unstable and causes more overall harm than benefit to the members of society. Another example is donating money to charity: It is considered morally good because it usually has a net effect of benefitting people, but it is not morally required because doing so might be less reasonable and even harmful for people who have very little of their own money to begin with. I think my way of explaining how we choose the optimal moral code is fairly intuitive and it seems that most people use this type of criteria (even if sub-consciously) when trying to decide whether they believe something is right or wrong. So my claim is that people strive to find this optimal moral code, and that people generally 1

think that all humans on earth (even those from varying cultures) should follow this optimal moral code. One important claim I make is that when someone talks about morality, it is implicit that she is referring to this optimal morality that applies to everyone in our society, unless she states otherwise. Overall, I belive that this theory helps explain people's general intuitions much better than objectivism or than the standard version of relativism. Now it may still seem that I've in fact argued for a kind of moral objectivism, since I've said that people believe everyone should follow the same moral code and that there is reason to disagree over what is right and wrong. I must emphasize that although people may think that all people in our global society of humans should follow the same moral rules, that doesn't mean that people think that those rules are a pre-existing fact about the world. To further show that my view really is a type of relativism, we can compare it to the relativism of simultaneity. It is known that two events cannot be objectively simultaneous, but only simultaneous relative to some inertial reference frame. However, for many situations, there can be an optimal inertial reference frame, where in this case optimal could mean most practical, easiest to understand, or some other criteria we desire it to have. For example, there can be an optimal inertial reference frame to use when solving a specific problem, for instance the one that makes the calculations easiest. Perhaps a more relevant example is considering passengers on a plane. When one passenger is making conversation with another, and she claims that she just saw two events occur simultaneously, it is optimal to consider the inertial reference frame of the plane they are in. Unless she states otherwise, the other passengers will all intuitively assume that she is speaking relative to their current inertial reference frame. This is similar to my version of moral relativism, where the passengers on the plane are replaced with all members of our society and the plane's inertial reference frame is replaced with the optimal moral code for all of humanity. Thus, I conclude that my theory is in 2

fact a type of relativism, and can be appropriately compared with relativism about simultaneity. To provide some evidence that what people actually think about morality matches what I claim they think, let's consider the data found by Sarkissian et al. In their experiment, participants were given scenarios in which two individuals had different moral judgments about a certain scenario (i.e. one says an act is morally permissible and the other says it is not). In each case, one of the disagreeing parties was a classmate, and the other varied: it was either another classmate ( same-culture ), a person from a radically different society ( other-culture ), or an alien ( extraterrestrial ). The participants were then asked whether or not they agreed with the statement Since [X] and [Y] have different judgments about this case, at least one of them must be wrong. 1 The data they collected shows that the degree to which participants agreed to the statement at least one must be wrong decreased from the same-culture case to the other-culture case, and decreased again from other-culture to extraterrestrial. This suggests that despite popular belief, people don't actually believe in moral objectivism. This data supports my claim that people's intuitions are relativistic but that people still want an optimal moral code for all of humanity. In the first case, it is clear that the two classmates are both a part of our overall society, and it follows that they should both be able to understand the optimal moral code and thus we think they should abide by it. People believe that there can be genuine disagreement between the classmates because they are truly disagreeing about what should be included in the optimal moral code. This is different from the other-culture scenario, because people don't necessarily believe that someone from an isolated culture would have the same ideas about morals as us. Since this other culture hasn't interacted with our society at all, there is not necessarily a compelling reason to think that the moral 1. Sarkissian et al. Folk Moral Relativism, page 487. 3

code that is optimal for our society is the same moral code that is optimal for the other society. I believe that this explains why people intuitively think that their classmate and the member of the other culture can both be correct when they have opposite judgments. This is even more evident in the extraterrestrial case: the aliens certainly haven't interacted with human society before, and there is even more reason to believe that their optimal moral system could differ from ours. Since they are totally different beings with different priorities and a different way of interacting, they could feasibly have a different way of optimizing whatever criteria is important to them. The reason that people are even more relativist in the extraterrestrial case than in the other-culture case is not obvious, but I think it can be explained as follows: It is intuitively reasonable that a different human society would look for the same values in an optimal moral code as we would, whereas it would be a much bigger stretch to think that a totally different species from another planet would do the same. A human from the other culture is still a human after all, and we know he is a rational being, just like us. I think that this can explain why people have the intuition that someone from another culture might still be expected to abide by our optimal set of moral values. Overall, I have explained how Sarkissian et al's data supports my theory about people's moral beliefs. My claim about folk moral intuitions not only explains the data from Sarkissian et al., but it also helps refute one of Boghossian's arguments against relativism. Boghossian discusses three types of relativism: thoroughgoing relativism, alethic relativism, and absolutist relativism. The folk relativism that I have proposed is a type of thoroughgoing relativism (specifically, contextualism), because I say that when people make moral claims, they are really making claims about a certain moral system. Thus I will only consider Boghossian's objection to contextualism. Boghossian argues that if someone claims (1) Killing is wrong 4

and someone else claims (2) Killing is not wrong then they are intuitively disagreeing. However, a contextualist may claim that when someone claims (1), they are really claiming (3) Killing is not wrong based on my moral code M and that someone claiming (2) is claiming (4) Killing is not wrong based on my moral code M* Boghossian concludes that since both (3) and (4) can be true, it doesn't make sense for there to be any disagreement between the speakers, and so contextualism must be wrong since there is disagreement. 2 However, on my view, the people are not actually disagreeing about whether or not a statement is true relative to M or to M*, but that the real disagreement lies in whether or not it should be true relative to the optimal moral code for humanity. They argue over whether the specific feature of M or that of M* is better suited to optimize our moral code. It is intuitive that there can be genuine disagreement about which moral beliefs are the most beneficial, practical, or any property we want to optimize. Thus it is intuitive that there can be genuine disagreement between the speakers of (1) and (2), even if they are relativists. They can agree that moral values are not objective, yet still argue which moral values are most optimal for society. Thus my theory about folk morality defeats Boghossian's argument. What happens when somebody joins our society? Under my theory, newborn children of members of society are automatically expected to comply with our moral code, and this is pretty clear because most people would intuitively agree that a child gets her morals from her family and 2. Boghossian, Paul. Three Kinds of Relativism 5

community. However, the more interesting case to be considered is when someone who already follows a different moral code integrates into our society. Since it is less clear whether humans of a different culture are actually a part of the greater global society or not, I will consider only the extraterrestrial case in this essay.if a distant planet (call it Grogor) sent a ship of aliens (call them Grogs) to Earth, people wouldn't expect that the Grogs would already have the same moral code as us. Suppose they don't. If the Grog stepped off his ship and somehow communicated that he thought killing was not wrong, then my theory says that most people wouldn't say the alien has an objectively incorrect moral view, and this is supported by the data collected by Sarkissian et al. However, suppose that the Grogs decide to stay on Earth and integrate into our society (supposing that there are no physical constraints that prevent this and that they can learn to communicate with us effectively). I expect the transition period may be more uncertain, so let's suppose that the Grogs have settled in a bit: they have learned the necessary practical details about living on earth and interacting with humans. At this point, my theory says that we would then expect the Grogs to comply with our moral code, and that if one expressed killing is not wrong we would now say that he does have the wrong moral view! At first, my argument may seem like a double standard or a contradiction; however, it makes sense in light of what I claim our moral theory is based on. I claimed that our optimal moral code incorporates values like being overall beneficial and producing happiness, among other criteria. If a Grog living on his home planet thought that killing was not wrong, it would not change the balance of benefits, happiness, or any other quality of human life, so we would have no reason to care what the alien does on Grogor, and we would not say that his moral judgment is wrong. However, when the Grog makes the decision to become part of our society, that commitment comes with the responsibility of abiding by our moral code. If a Grog were to kill a person on Earth, it would have a very negative effect on 6

many people in society, so it would not be considered morally wrong. My conclusion is that someone can only make moral judgments about a member of his or her own society. This distinction follows from my theory that moral codes arise from a combination of values important to that specific society, and it is evidenced by the data from Sarkissian et al. In conclusion, I have provided reason to believe the theory that people are moral relativists, but that we still expect all people on Earth should have a universal moral code, one based on some combination of practicality, happiness-creating, and other criteria. I have examined features this theory and I have shown that this theory is supported by Sarkissian et al's data, and that it can overcome one of Boghossian's objections to moral relativism. 7

MIT OpenCourseWare http://ocw.mit.edu 24.230 Meta-ethics Fall 2015 For information about citing these materials or our Terms of Use, visit: http://ocw.mit.edu/terms.