Emptiness Appraised: A Critical Study of Nagarjuna's Philosophy (review)

Similar documents
Empty Words: Buddhist Philosophy and Cross-Cultural Interpretation (review)

Philosophers of Nothingness: An Essay on the Kyoto School (review)

Studies in Buddhist Philosophy by Mark Siderits (review)

Defending the Semantic Interpretation: A Reply to Ferraro

PHIL 445 / PHIL 510B / AAAS 482P: Buddhist Metaphysics Fall 2017

1 Hans Jonas, The Imperative of Responsibility: In Search of an Ethics for the Technological Age (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1984), 1-10.

PRELIMINARY. Asian Mahayana (Great Vehicle) traditions of Buddhism, Nagarjuna. easily resorted to in our attempt to understand the world.

Against a Hindu God: Buddhist Philosophy of Religion in India (review)

CLARIFYING MIND An Introduction to the Tradition of Pramana

Access provided by National Taiwan University (10 Aug :00 GMT)

The Truth of Nagarjuna: Something Beyond Nirvana

Philosophy East and West, Volume 65, Number 3, July 2015, pp (Review) DOI: /pew

A Philosophical Study of Nonmetaphysical Approach towards Human Existence

Has Nagel uncovered a form of idealism?

ROUGH OUTLINE FOR EMPTINESS, BUDDHISM, NAGARJUNA

Philosophy as a Path: A Memoir and Tribute to Robert Thurman. Instead of writing an academic paper for this Festschrift, I ve chosen to write the

At the Frontiers of Reality

NOTES ON HOW TO SEE YOURSELF AS YOU REALLY ARE

Examining the Bodhisattva s Brain

Pyrrhonism: How the Ancient Greeks Reinvented Buddhism

Deontological Perspectivism: A Reply to Lockie Hamid Vahid, Institute for Research in Fundamental Sciences, Tehran

Christian Lotz, Commentary, SPEP 2009 Formal Indication and the Problem of Radical Philosophy in Heidegger

4/30/2010 cforum :: Moderator Control Panel

What Should We Believe?

The Greatest Mistake: A Case for the Failure of Hegel s Idealism

INVESTIGATING THE PRESUPPOSITIONAL REALM OF BIBLICAL-THEOLOGICAL METHODOLOGY, PART II: CANALE ON REASON

In Epistemic Relativism, Mark Kalderon defends a view that has become

On Nāgārjuna s Ontological and Semantic Paradox

Two Kinds of Ends in Themselves in Kant s Moral Theory

A HOLISTIC VIEW ON KNOWLEDGE AND VALUES

Who Has the Burden of Proof? Must the Christian Provide Adequate Reasons for Christian Beliefs?

BUDDHIST PHILOSOPHY. Office hours: I will be delighted to talk with you outside of class. Make an appointment or drop by during my office hours:

Truth and Realism. EDITED BY PATRICK GREENOUGH AND MICHAEL P. LYNCH. (Oxford: Clarendon Press, Pp. ix Price h/b, p/b.

NAGARJUNA (2nd Century AD) THE FUNDAMENTALS OF THE MIDDLE WAY (Mulamadhyamaka-Karika) 1

Contents. Guy Prentiss Waters. Justification and the New Perspectives on Paul: A Review and Response. P&R, pp.

Faults and Mathematical Disagreement

Reason and Explanation: A Defense of Explanatory Coherentism. BY TED POSTON (Basingstoke,

Teachur Philosophy Degree 2018

Department of Philosophy. Module descriptions 20118/19. Level C (i.e. normally 1 st Yr.) Modules

Denis Seron. Review of: K. Mulligan, Wittgenstein et la philosophie austro-allemande (Paris: Vrin, 2012). Dialectica

Are There Moral Facts

Saving the Substratum: Interpreting Kant s First Analogy

Wittgenstein on The Realm of Ineffable

Philosophy 5340 Epistemology Topic 4: Skepticism. Part 1: The Scope of Skepticism and Two Main Types of Skeptical Argument

Department of Philosophy. Module descriptions 2017/18. Level C (i.e. normally 1 st Yr.) Modules

From Transcendental Logic to Transcendental Deduction

Under contract with Oxford University Press Karen Bennett Cornell University

Kant and the Problem of Metaphysics 1. By Tom Cumming

Introductory Kant Seminar Lecture

In 1971, Antony Flew wrote:

Canadian Society for Continental Philosophy

Contents. PA RT I Africa 1. PAR T I I West Asia, North Africa, and Spain 43. Preface ix Time Line xiv

Rationalist-Irrationalist Dialectic in Buddhism:

MODELS CLARIFIED: RESPONDING TO LANGDON GILKEY. by David E. Klemm and William H. Klink

Mohammad Reza Vaez Shahrestani. University of Bonn

Robert Kiely Office Hours: Monday 4:15 6:00; Wednesday 1-3; Thursday 2-3

ALTERNATIVE SELF-DEFEAT ARGUMENTS: A REPLY TO MIZRAHI

Some Notes Toward a Genealogy of Existential Philosophy Robert Burch

World without Design: The Ontological Consequences of Natural- ism , by Michael C. Rea.

Searching for an Educational Response to Nihilism in Our Time: An Examination of Keiji Nishitani s Philosophy of Emptiness 1

Pihlström, Sami Johannes.

AN INTRODUCTION TO CERTAIN BUDDHIST PHILOSOPHICAL CONCEPTS

Religious Studies. Name: Institution: Course: Date:

1/10. The Fourth Paralogism and the Refutation of Idealism

LUCIAN BLAGA UNIVERSITY OF SIBIU ANDREI ȘAGUNA FACULTY OF ORTHODOX THEOLOGY

Critiquing the Western Account of India Studies within a Comparative Science of Cultures

The Character of Space in Kant s First Critique By Justin Murphy October 16, 2006

BOOK REVIEWS. Duke University. The Philosophical Review, Vol. XCVII, No. 1 (January 1988)

FIRST STUDY. The Existential Dialectical Basic Assumption of Kierkegaard s Analysis of Despair

Chapter 2. Moral Reasoning. Chapter Overview. Learning Objectives. Teaching Suggestions

The Heart of Wisdom Sūtra Bhagavatī-Prajñāpāramitā-Hṛdaya-Sūtra

Buddhism s Engagement with the World. April 21-22, University of Utah

OSSA Conference Archive OSSA 3

NATURALISED JURISPRUDENCE

Constructive-isms: A Conversation on Some Constructivist Contexts. Spencer A. McWilliams.

Language and Emptiness: A Diagrammatic Comparative Study of Martin Heidegger, Ludwig Wittgenstein and Nāgārjuna

Introduction. 1 See C. Beckwith (2015), McEvilly (2012), Kuzminsky (2008) and Garfield (1990).

Examining the nature of mind. Michael Daniels. A review of Understanding Consciousness by Max Velmans (Routledge, 2000).

* Dalhousie Law School, LL.B. anticipated Interpretation and Legal Theory. Andrei Marmor Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1992, 193 pp.

Reflections on sociology's unspoken weakness: Bringing epistemology back in

THE CRISIS OF THE SCmNCES AS EXPRESSION OF THE RADICAL LIFE-CRISIS OF EUROPEAN HUMANITY

Theoretical Virtues in Science


What Must There be to Account for Being?

Positivism A Model Of For System Of Rules

ELEONORE STUMP PENELHUM ON SKEPTICS AND FIDEISTS

Direct Realism and the Brain-in-a-Vat Argument by Michael Huemer (2000)

Illusionism and Givenness: Comments on Frankish *

Nothingness In ASIAN Philosophy

A Philosophical Critique of Cognitive Psychology s Definition of the Person

Review of Evidentialism and the Will to Believe. By Scott Aikin. Bloomsbury: London, pp. $120 I

In Search of the Ontological Argument. Richard Oxenberg

Resolutio of Idealism into Atheism in Fichte

On Searle on Human Rights, Again! J. Angelo Corlett, San Diego State University

Critique of Cosmological Argument

THE UNIVERSITY OF WESTERN ONTARIO DEPARTMENT OF PHILOSOPHY Undergraduate Course Outline PHIL3501G: Epistemology

The Ethics of Śaṅkara and Śāntideva: A Selfless Response to an Illusory World

The Logic of Uddyotakara The conflict with Buddhist logic and his achievement

Philosophical Review.

Evil and/or/as The Good: Omnicentrism, Intersubjectivity, and Value Paradox in Tiantai Buddhist Thought (review)

Transcription:

Emptiness Appraised: A Critical Study of Nagarjuna's Philosophy (review) William Edelglass Philosophy East and West, Volume 53, Number 4, October 2003, pp. 602-605 (Review) Published by University of Hawai'i Press DOI: https://doi.org/10.1353/pew.2003.0036 For additional information about this article https://muse.jhu.edu/article/47273 Access provided by National Taiwan University (7 Sep 2017 08:04 GMT)

Emptiness Appraised: A Critical Study of Nāgārjuna s Philosophy. By David F. Burton. Richmond: Curzon Press, 1999. Pp. xv þ 233. Reviewed by William Edelglass Emory University An oft-quoted Buddhist adage urges the practitioner to test Buddhist teachings with analytic reasoning. The teachings should not be accepted dogmatically, many Buddhist traditions emphasize, but tested as gold is analyzed to determine its true value. In his carefully argued book Emptiness Appraised: A Critical Study of Nāgārjuna s Philosophy, David Burton, who informs the reader that he is undertaking his study as a Buddhist seeking to understand the tradition to which he is committed, has sought to put Nāgārjuna s philosophy of emptiness (śūnyatā) to the test of critical reason. The result, according to Burton, is a resounding failure: Nāgārjuna s arguments, he claims, are generally fallacious, and their most significant conclusions philosophically untenable. Burton describes his project as twofold: the ascertainment and appraisal of Nāgārjuna s philosophy of śūnyatā. By giving a thorough exposition of Nāgārjuna s understanding of śūnyatā Burton ambitiously hopes to resolve debates between the many competing interpretations of Nāgārjuna s thought. Although his arguments are based on close readings of the texts and occasionally draw on Indian and Tibetan sources, Burton is not primarily interested in philological questions or tracing the various commentarial traditions. The central concern of this text is philosophical, an inquiry into the epistemological and ontological consequences of Nāgārjuna s philosophical use of śūnyatā. In the first part of the book Burton addresses three questions: What is the status of Nāgārjuna s knowledge claims, and more specifically, is Nāgārjuna a skeptic? How is Nāgārjuna s claim that ultimate knowledge is nonconceptual to be understood? And, does Nāgārjuna s account of śūnyatā entail nihilism? The second part of the book is concerned with the motivation and philosophical success of Nāgārjuna s critiques of Nyāya epistemology. Nāgārjuna famously claims to hold no view, and, further, that those who hold śūnyatā as a view are incurable. For this reason Matilal, Hayes, and numerous other scholars have characterized Nāgārjuna as a skeptic. What, then, Burton asks, is the status of Nāgārjuna s knowledge claims that all entities lack an essence, or ownnature (svabhāva)? To answer this question Burton gives an account of both Academic and Pyrrhonian Skepticism, and shows that Nāgārjuna is not a skeptic in either of these two classical senses. That is, Nāgārjuna does not argue that knowledge of things as they are is impossible, nor does he argue that there is no legitimate rational adjudication between views. Instead, Nāgārjuna claims that he does have knowledge of how things are, most prominently the knowledge that all entities lack svabhāva, and thus he cannot be considered a skeptic. The knowledge claim that all entities lack svabhāva leads, according to Burton, to a paradox in Nāgārjuna s thought. For Nāgārjuna also claims that reality is ultimately nonconceptual and inexpressible. If reality is ultimately beyond concept and expression, how can Nāgārjuna conceive of and express the ultimate nature of 602 Philosophy East & West Volume 53, Number 4 October 2003 602 605 > 2003 by University of Hawai i Press

things as śūnyatā? Burton suggests two possible responses: either Nāgārjuna is equivocating in his use of the word reality, or he is using language imprecisely and really does not intend to characterize the knowledge of ultimate reality as beyond concept or expression, but is instead describing the meditative experience of knowing that reality. Burton considers the latter interpretation to have been Nāgārjuna s position, but argues that both interpretations are philosophically and spiritually barren. According to Burton, once Nāgārjuna has made the distinction between unconceptualizable ultimate truth and conventional truth that can be conceptualized, it will be impossible to understand how the two levels of truth and reality can relate to each other. Moreover, according to Burton, there can be no śūnyatā of entities as objects for meditative knowledge because Nāgārjuna is a nihilist whose philosophy entails that there are no entities at all. Burton s interpretation differs from Thomas Wood s reading of Nāgārjuna as a nihilist. Unlike Wood and most other contemporary commentators who interpret Mādhyamaka as a form of nihilism, Burton believes that Nāgārjuna was an unwitting nihilist. That is, Burton agrees with Nāgārjuna s Buddhist and Hindu opponents, who argued that despite his claims to navigate a middle path between eternalism and nihilism, Nāgārjuna misunderstood the consequences of his own position. It is therefore a misnomer to call Nāgārjuna s thought a philosophy of the Middle Way, according to Burton, for, as the Buddhist opponents insisted, Mādhyamaka nihilism destroys the Buddhist path. Nāgārjuna considered dependent origination (pratītyasamutpāda) and śūnyatā to be inextricable. This was not the case, Burton emphasizes, for certain Abhidharmikas, who regarded the atomic parts (dharmas) of conceptually constructed things as subject to pratītyasamutpāda and yet possessing svabhāva. Dharmas are free of causes and conditions only in the particular sense of not being conditioned by parts, which by definition they lack. Otherwise, according to some traditions of Abhidharma philosophy, dharmas, because they are subject to birth, duration, and decay, are subject to pratītyasamutpāda. Burton argues that after linking pratītyasamutpāda and śūnyatā Nāgārjuna was compelled to deny svabhāva to all entities in order to maintain the Buddhist doctrine of pratītyasamutpāda. The conditions for the possibility of a conceptually constructed entity, according to Burton, include at least something or someone who does the constructing, and a material, such as the dharmas, out of which the entity is to be constructed. It is nonsensical, he claims, for a conceptually constructed subject to conceptually construct the world, for this leads to an infinite regress. And without unconstructed material that is given there can be no conceptual construction. Burton concludes that contrary to Nāgārjuna s own intentions, the claim that all entities lack svabhāva entails nihilism. Nāgārjuna s rejection of realist ontology is accompanied by sustained critiques of realist epistemology. Burton devotes the second part of his study to an exposition and critical analysis of these critiques as Nāgārjuna articulates them in the Vigrahavyāvartanī and the Vaidalyaprakaraṅa. Beginning with an account of the Nyāya theory of valid means of knowledge ( pramāṅas), Burton systematically treats Nāgār- Book Reviews 603

juna s diverse arguments against Nyāya realist epistemology. It should come as no surprise that Burton finds all Nāgārjuna s arguments to be invalid. According to Burton, these arguments are unable to demonstrate that there are no entities independent of conceptual construction, and, furthermore, they fail to show that we cannot have valid knowledge of entities. As the first part of his study constituted a defense of Nāgārjuna s Abhidarmika opponents, so here Burton defends Nyāya realism from Nāgārjuna s attacks. Any reader familiar with Nāgārjuna s Buddhist commentators or recent Mādhyamaka scholarship will recognize Burton s analyses as controversial and provocative. Each of Burton s major conclusions, for example, is contrary to Jay Garfield s dge-lugs-pa inspired interpretation, arguably the most philosophically compelling account of Nāgārjuna by a Western scholar. According to Garfield s interpretation, Nāgārjuna is not making claims concerning ultimate reality but is instead arguing against the very possibility of making ontological claims about what lies behind the dependently arisen conventional world. Moreover, Garfield offers a persuasive account of how one can make sense of conventionally constructed entities without presupposing ultimate entities that somehow stand behind them. Garfield is not alone in giving a sympathetic and philosophically coherent interpretation of Nāgārjuna; there is a significant body of literature devoted precisely to the question of how Nāgārjuna s account of śūnyatā, pratītyasamutpāda, and the two truths (satyadvaya) account for the existence and knowledge of the intersubjective, phenomenal world. One of the weaknesses of Burton s study is his failure to address these interpretations that differ so significantly from his own. In Burton s defense it should be remembered that he is not primarily interested in philological or historical investigations, or in extensive explication of the work of other scholars, but in addressing particular philosophical problems and pursuing them to their conclusions. This study often seems to be a work of Anglo-American analytic philosophy that happens to be treating issues raised by Nāgārjuna s epistemology and ontology. Burton repeatedly demonstrates deft philosophical reasoning and patience in following his arguments. But his interpretation occasionally suffers from the limitations of his particular philosophical framework. For example, Burton s rejection of the possibility of nonconceptual discrimination is significant for his argument, yet he disregards the many persuasive phenomenological accounts of nonconceptual discrimination. 1 His realist critique of the notion that conceptually constructed entities do not require further entities from which they are constructed ( it is implausible and unintelligible ) seems philosophically unimaginative. The history of philosophy in the East and the West has plenty of subtle arguments for one variety or another of this position. 2 The occasional limitations of Burton s philosophical framework raise the thorny issue of interpretation. The terse and often obscure verses in works attributed to Nāgārjuna have led to an extraordinary diversity of interpretation in Buddhist traditions and Western scholarship. For this reason many contemporary Western translators and interpreters of Mādhyamaka philosophy make at least a nod to Gadamerian hermeneutics in an attempt to understand how the text can justify such an 604 Philosophy East & West

abundance of diverse meaning. In contrast, Burton argues that a trans-cultural and trans-historical rationality can bridge the interpretive challenges of time, tradition, and language between contemporary Western scholars and Nāgārjuna, despite the obscurity of the texts, themselves veiled under millennia of accumulated commentarial traditions. This is not to say that Burton believes there is always one definitive meaning of a particular verse, but he considers the possibilities of legitimate interpretation to be limited, and a reasonable and systematic exegesis ought to be able to interpret and critique each one. He therefore rejects Andrew Tuck s claim that as interpreters we are limited by our own cultural horizons, a claim for which Burton s own Anglo-American philosophical limitations seem to provide evidence. Burton s final evaluation is that although philosophically untenable, Nāgārjuna s thought deserves to be studied because it raises deep philosophical issues. Some readers will read Burton s careful arguments and close textual analysis and consider it admirably intrepid scholarship; others will regard his unsympathetic interpretation as naïvely brash. There is no doubt, however, that Burton s exposition and appraisal raise important philosophical and interpretive questions for the study of Mādhyamaka. Notes 1 Curiously, Burton cites Heidegger s notion of Zuhandenheit as an example of implicit conceptualization, although Heidegger emphasizes that it is precisely not a cognitive process. 2 Again, Burton makes a strange choice in citing Husserl to support his own argument. Burton claims to agree with Husserl that the structure of consciousness is intentional; in other words, consciousness is always consciousness of. Because consciousness always requires a subject pole and an object pole, Burton argues that if consciousness is to exist, then there must be an entity at the object pole. But Husserl, who was often understood to be an idealist by his contemporaries, especially following the publication of Ideas I and Cartesian Meditations, occasionally argues for a position that bears some similarity to the one Burton is attacking. Moreover, a philosophical defense of Nāgārjuna could draw on the Husserlian understanding of hyle. Philosophers of Nothingness: An Essay on the Kyoto School. By James W. Heisig. Honolulu: University of Hawai i Press, 2001. Pp. xii þ 380. Reviewed by Curtis Rigsby Office of the History of Japanese Philosophy at Kyoto University; East-West Center; and University of Hawai i Philosophers of Nothingness: An Essay on the Kyoto School by James W. Heisig is the first major work in English to offer such a complete introduction to the thought of the Kyoto School. It analyzes the School s three core figures, Nishida Kitarō, Tanabe Hajime, and Nishitani Keiji, whom Heisig, using Takeuchi Yoshinori s terminology (p. 176), has elsewhere referred to as the triangulation around which the School is Philosophy East & West Volume 53, Number 4 October 2003 605 612 605 > 2003 by University of Hawai i Press