Truth and Realism. EDITED BY PATRICK GREENOUGH AND MICHAEL P. LYNCH. (Oxford: Clarendon Press, Pp. ix Price h/b, p/b.

Similar documents
World without Design: The Ontological Consequences of Natural- ism , by Michael C. Rea.

To appear in The Journal of Philosophy.

1 Why should you care about metametaphysics?

In Epistemic Relativism, Mark Kalderon defends a view that has become

David Copp, ed., The Oxford Handbook of Ethical Theory, Oxford: Oxford University

Philosophical reflection about what we call knowledge has a natural starting point in the

Philosophia Scientiæ Travaux d'histoire et de philosophie des sciences (Anti-)Realisms: The Metaphysical Issue. Publisher Editions Kimé

Naturalism and is Opponents

145 Philosophy of Science

The linguistic-cultural nature of scientific truth 1

Luck, Rationality, and Explanation: A Reply to Elga s Lucky to Be Rational. Joshua Schechter. Brown University

The Illusion of Scientific Realism: An Argument for Scientific Soft Antirealism

Faults and Mathematical Disagreement

THE CONDITIONS OF MORAL REALISM

INTUITION AND CONSCIOUS REASONING

Does the Skeptic Win? A Defense of Moore. I. Moorean Methodology. In A Proof of the External World, Moore argues as follows:

Does Moral Discourse Require Robust Truth? Fritz J. McDonald Assistant Professor Oakland University. Abstract

REALISM/ANTI-REALISM

Tuomas E. Tahko (University of Helsinki)

Three Paradigms of Scientific Realism: A Truthmaking Account

Realism and Idealism Internal realism

Philosophical Issues, vol. 8 (1997), pp

To Appear in Philosophical Studies symposium of Hartry Field s Truth and the Absence of Fact

Generic truth and mixed conjunctions: some alternatives

Austere Realism: Contextual Semantics Meets Minimal Ontology, by Terence Horgan and Matjaž Potr

Realism and the success of science argument. Leplin:

PLEASE SCROLL DOWN FOR ARTICLE

Issue 4, Special Conference Proceedings Published by the Durham University Undergraduate Philosophy Society

Theoretical Virtues in Science

Epistemology for Naturalists and Non-Naturalists: What s the Difference?

A Logical Approach to Metametaphysics

All philosophical debates not due to ignorance of base truths or our imperfect rationality are indeterminate.

Under contract with Oxford University Press Karen Bennett Cornell University

Reactions & Debate. Non-Convergent Truth

REALISM AND ANTI-REALISM: DUMMETT'S CHALLENGE

Shafer-Landau's defense against Blackburn's supervenience argument

Critical Scientific Realism

From Necessary Truth to Necessary Existence

Putting Pluralism in its Place 1

Intro to Ground. 1. The idea of ground. 2. Relata. are facts): F 1. More-or-less equivalent phrases (where F 1. and F 2. depends upon F 2 F 2

On The Logical Status of Dialectic (*) -Historical Development of the Argument in Japan- Shigeo Nagai Naoki Takato

A Priori Skepticism and the KK Thesis

Deflationism about Truth and Meaning

Constructive Logic, Truth and Warranted Assertibility

Three easy points on relative truth

1. Why were you initially drawn to epistemology (and what keeps you interested)?

Van Fraassen s Appreciated Anti-Realism. Lane DesAutels. I. Introduction

Cory Juhl, Eric Loomis, Analyticity (New York: Routledge, 2010).

Rule-Following and the Ontology of the Mind Abstract The problem of rule-following

Heidegger, Arthur Fine, and the Natural Ontological Attitude

Truth At a World for Modal Propositions

Bayesian Probability

LOCKE STUDIES Vol ISSN: X

Review of Constructive Empiricism: Epistemology and the Philosophy of Science

Intuition as Philosophical Evidence

Areas of Specialization and Competence Philosophy of Language, History of Analytic Philosophy

Metametaphysics. New Essays on the Foundations of Ontology* Oxford University Press, 2009

RESPECTING THE EVIDENCE. Richard Feldman University of Rochester

BOOK REVIEWS. Duke University. The Philosophical Review, Vol. XCVII, No. 1 (January 1988)

The Question of Metaphysics

AMANDA BRYANT. Department of Philosophy Trent University 1600 West Bank Drive Peterborough, Ontario K9L 0G2

ASSESSOR RELATIVISM AND THE PROBLEM OF MORAL DISAGREEMENT

Seigel and Silins formulate the following theses:

Empiricism. Otávio Bueno Department of Philosophy University of Miami Coral Gables, FL

The Positive Argument for Constructive Empiricism and Inference to the Best

Russell on Metaphysical Vagueness

Minerva Access is the Institutional Repository of The University of Melbourne

Philosophy Courses in English

Introduction. September 30, 2011

Book Reviews 427. University of Manchester Oxford Rd., M13 9PL, UK. doi: /mind/fzl424

CLASS PARTICIPATION IS A REQUIREMENT

Henrik Ahlenius Department of Philosophy ETHICS & RESEARCH

Stance relativism: empiricism versus metaphysics

Department of Philosophy. Module descriptions 2017/18. Level C (i.e. normally 1 st Yr.) Modules

(1) a phrase may be denoting, and yet not denote anything e.g. the present King of France

UC Berkeley UC Berkeley Previously Published Works

Are There Moral Facts

Huemer s Clarkeanism

FACING UP TO THE SORITES PARADOX. Terry Horgan. University of Memphis

REVIEW. Sungho Choi Philosophy Dept., Kyung Hee University Seoul, Republic of Korea Brit. J. Phil. Sci. 62 (2011),

One of the central concerns in metaphysics is the nature of objects which

Resemblance Nominalism and counterparts

Horwich and the Liar

Science as a Guide to Metaphysics? Katherine Hawley, University of St Andrews, June

Stance relativism: empiricism versus metaphysics

Epistemic Contextualism as a Theory of Primary Speaker Meaning

Vagueness and Borderline Cases

WHAT DOES KRIPKE MEAN BY A PRIORI?

Postmodal Metaphysics

Contextualism and the Epistemological Enterprise

Self-Evidence and A Priori Moral Knowledge

A copy can be downloaded for personal non-commercial research or study, without prior permission or charge

Brian Cutter Curriculum Vitae. University of Notre Dame Phone: Malloy Hall Notre Dame, IN 46556

WRIGHT ON BORDERLINE CASES AND BIVALENCE 1

THE SEMANTIC REALISM OF STROUD S RESPONSE TO AUSTIN S ARGUMENT AGAINST SCEPTICISM

Kitcher, Correspondence, and Success

2014 THE BIBLIOGRAPHIA ISSN: Online First: 21 October 2014

Knowledge, Safety, and Questions

Defationary truth and truth-aptness illuminated by language and norms: Paul Horwich, Huw Price, and Michael Lynch

what makes reasons sufficient?

Transcription:

Truth and Realism. EDITED BY PATRICK GREENOUGH AND MICHAEL P. LYNCH. (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 2006. Pp. ix + 253. Price 45.00 h/b, 18.99 p/b.) This book collects papers presented at a conference of the same title at the University of St Andrews in 2004. Disputes over realism, in the very general philosophical sense of this term, persist with little hope of resolution or consensus. It is thus unsurprising to find the core of realism characterized in many ways in a short collection of papers. Different authors define realism in different ways, as a view centrally about truth, semantics, epistemology, or metaphysics. It is equally unsurprising then to find realism characterized elsewhere in the same book as a muddle of confusion, or as a relic of discredited philosophical doctrines. The book is divided into three sections. The first, shortest section is on truth and relativism, focusing on how to characterize the differences between relativist and nonrelativist views of various discourses. The middle section is on the second term in the book s title, realism. The final section of the book is at a higher order with respect to the earlier sections. In this section, on Methodology and the Nature of the Debates, metaphilosophical questions are raised: are there in fact any genuine, interesting disputes regarding the issues of realism? If so, how are such debates to be resolved? As the editors correctly note, there is no clear dividing line between the metaphilosophical and the philosophical issues about realism, and thus no clear dividing line between the topics pursued in the different sections of the book. The section on relativism contains three papers. Paul Boghossian s What is Relativism? is the only paper in the book not written for the St Andrews conference.

Boghossian argues that uncontroversial relativist scientific views such as the relativity of motion to a frame of reference cannot provide an acceptable model for more controversial relativist views, such as relativism about morality. Crispin Wright, in Intuitionism, Realism, Relativism, and Rhubarb, argues that the ordinary view of disagreements of taste leads to puzzles. These puzzles can only be adequately resolved, according to Wright, based on a formulation of relativism about taste in terms of truth as superassertibility. J.C. Beall, in a response to Wright, contends that such disputes are better characterized by a relativized version of the correspondence theory of truth. The second section, on realism, opens with Michael Williams s Realism: What s Left? Williams criticizes Philip Kitcher s real realism. Real realism is the view that scientific and commonsense claims are true, and the truth of such claims is to be understood in terms of correspondence truth. Williams argues that Kitcher s account is based on an ill-motivated neo-cartesian account of knowledge, and that in light of a Sellarsian neo-pragmatist account of the kind Williams has argued for elsewhere, a more deflationary kind of realism is better warranted. Michael Devitt s Scientific Realism defends the view that the unobservable entities invoked in scientific theories exist, refining a familiar defense of this view based on the success of science. He then argues against skepticism about unobservables, addressing concerns about the underdetermination of theories by evidence and the pessimistic meta-induction from the nonexistence of the unobservables posited by theories in the past. The arguments are presented in Devitt s characteristically clear and forthright style. Christopher Gauker, in his critique of Devitt, focuses critically on Devitt s view that the existence of unobservables is fundamentally not a semantic issue.

The criticisms of Devitt, mostly aimed at the deflationary theory of truth, seem misdirected, and Gauker does not articulate a clear semantic alternative to Devitt s metaphysical account of scientific realism. Even among those philosophers who hold that realism is a metaphysical issue, there are many possible incompatible realisms. Terry Horgan and Matjaz Potrc, in Abundant Truth in an Austere World, make a case for an austere metaphysical realism, one that claims that a range of entities, from common household objects like chairs to complex entities such as nations, do not really exist. The sense that many people have that such objects do exist is explained away as a competence-performance error akin to the Mueller-Lyre optical illusion Any normal person telling a philosopher that chairs really do exist has failed, according to Horgan and Potrc, to recognize that the contextually relevant standards for talk about chairs has shifted in an serious ontological dispute. Horgan and Potrc then argue that, contrary to what might be expected, common sense considerations weigh in favor of their elimination of chairs from the cosmos. When common sense goes reflective about metaphysics, it seeks a systematic theory of the composition of objects, yet there is no such theory, thus common sense leads us to eventually a rejection of composite objects like chairs (p. 152). Common sense also recognizes the vague boundaries of such objects, and appreciates, at least viscerally, that the right ontology cannot include such items (p. 154). These are, at best, questionable assertions about common sense, as Mark Richard notes in his critique of Horgan and Potrc. Richard ably shows how alternative approaches to problems raised by the composition of objects and vagueness avoid the counterintuitive consequences accepted by Horgan and Potrc.

Richard closes his paper by discussing philosophical method, casting doubt on the usefulness of linguistic approaches to metaphysical problems. This forms a nice segueway to the final section of the book, on methodology. Timothy Williamson, in the short paper opening this section, Must do Better, cites examples of apparent philosophical progress, such as the development of modal logic in the 20 th century. Williamson hopes for similar progress in realism disputes. Williamson charges that recent writing on realism contains too much imprecision, obscurity, and vagueness. More damningly, belief in realist or antirealist doctrines is, according to Williamson, often based on wishful thinking and susceptibility to charismatic authority figures rather than actual argument (p. 186). Williamson makes these claims, unfortunately, without citation of any specific work or philosopher. The paper ends with a plea for clearer methods and more rigor, without making a case for any specific methods. Paul Horwich, in A World Without Isms, argues against relativism, fictionalism, and error theories about apparently weird facts, such as modal and moral facts. Horwich contends that each of these theories requires a distinction between belief and mere acceptance of claims, a distinction that Horwich argues cannot be made. Turning from beliefs to facts, Horwich considers the possibility that such views could be recast in terms of a distinction between robust and nonrobust facts. Horwich presents and criticizes a recent attempt by Kit Fine to make such a distinction, and ultimately claims that the search for such a distinction is based on a misguided attempt to assimilate all facts to physical facts. In light of this, Horwich suggests eschewing all talk of realism and antirealism. Marian David, in Horwich s World, contends that in spite of his rejection of the term itself, Horwich is a non-reductive realist. In light of the lack of consensus

over the dividing line between realists and antirealists noted by Horwich in his paper and exemplified in the varied conceptions running throughout this book, this stands in need of clarification. The section on methodology includes two papers on the nature and importance of intuitions. These papers, by Ernest Sosa and Michael Lynch, while rich with interesting proposals regarding the nature of a traditional philosophical method, have little to do with the concerns over realism and relativism that run throughout the rest of the volume. The final paper in the volume is a general commentary on the St Andrews conference by the late Richard Rorty. Rorty offers an unsurprisingly bracing critique of the realist/antirealist debate, largely agreeing with Williams and Horwich in dismissing more inflationary conceptions of ontology. Rorty writes that [o]ntology is more like a playground than a discipline, because whatever one says regarding ontology, one can get away with it (p. 242). This general critique of ontology attributes philosophical interest in realism to a Parmenidean search for superthings such as the One. This critique of realism, whatever its merits, is too general to capture every philosophical concern over realism Why think that philosophers concerned about scientific realism, mathematical realism, epistemic realism, secondary quality realism, or moral realism are all motivated by this Parmenidean concern? It is perhaps a sign of the kind of progress that Williamson cites that there are such a variety of ongoing disputes under the fuzzy rubric of realism, although it is hard to see the prospects for progress in these disputes given how little common ground there is even over what the term realism means. Oakland University FRITZ J. MCDONALD