THE MORAL FIXED POINTS: REPLY TO CUNEO AND SHAFER-LANDAU

Similar documents
ARE THE MORAL FIXED POINTS CONCEPTUAL TRUTHS?

MORAL FIXED POINTS AND CONCEPTUAL DEFICIENCY: REPLY TO INGRAM (2015)

Shafer-Landau's defense against Blackburn's supervenience argument

STILL NO REDUNDANT PROPERTIES: REPLY TO WIELENBERG

TWO ACCOUNTS OF THE NORMATIVITY OF RATIONALITY

Terence CUNEO, The Normative Web. An Argument for Moral Realism. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2008, 263 pp., 46.99, ISBN

The Tempering of a Defense: Further Critiques Against Error Theory in Light of Russ Shafer- Landau s Ethical Nonnaturalism

Well-Being, Disability, and the Mere-Difference Thesis. Jennifer Hawkins Duke University

Dissolving the Debunker s Puzzle

Understanding Truth Scott Soames Précis Philosophy and Phenomenological Research Volume LXV, No. 2, 2002

Right-Making, Reference, and Reduction

THE UNBELIEVABLE TRUTH ABOUT MORALITY

David Enoch s Taking Morality Seriously (Oxford University Press 2011) is the latest in

Self-Evidence and A Priori Moral Knowledge

Epistemic Normativity for Naturalists

Oxford Scholarship Online Abstracts and Keywords

AGAINST THE BEING FOR ACCOUNT OF NORMATIVE CERTITUDE

2210 Speedway, Stop C3500, WAG 316, Austin, TX (936)

Non-naturalism and Normative Necessities

HYBRID NON-NATURALISM DOES NOT MEET THE SUPERVENIENCE CHALLENGE. David Faraci

Philosophical Issues, vol. 8 (1997), pp

Review of Erik J. Wielenberg: Robust Ethics: The Metaphysics and Epistemology of Godless Normative Realism

DISCUSSION PRACTICAL POLITICS AND PHILOSOPHICAL INQUIRY: A NOTE

World without Design: The Ontological Consequences of Natural- ism , by Michael C. Rea.

On Searle on Human Rights, Again! J. Angelo Corlett, San Diego State University

Is God Good By Definition?

HOW TO BE (AND HOW NOT TO BE) A NORMATIVE REALIST:

Ergo JOURNAL OF PHILOSOPHY

Conditions of Fundamental Metaphysics: A critique of Jorge Gracia's proposal

Non-naturalism and Normative Necessities

The Puzzle of Pure Moral Motivation

The Nature and Explanatory Ambitions of Metaethics. By Tristram McPherson (Ohio State University) and David Plunkett (Dartmouth College)

A Rational Solution to the Problem of Moral Error Theory? Benjamin Scott Harrison

Anderson and Velleman s Kantian Thesis : A Case-Study in the Serpent Windings of Ethical Taxonomy

How Successful Is Naturalism?

Stang (p. 34) deliberately treats non-actuality and nonexistence as equivalent.

Truly Normative Matters: An Essay on the Value of Truth

Debunking Evolutionary Debunking

What God Could Have Made

Insider and Outsider Scholarship in Bahá í Studies

Truth At a World for Modal Propositions

Introduction. The Nature and Explanatory Ambitions of Metaethics

Divine omniscience, timelessness, and the power to do otherwise

Philosophy 125 Day 1: Overview

NON-COGNITIVISM AND THE PROBLEM OF MORAL-BASED EPISTEMIC REASONS: A SYMPATHETIC REPLY TO CIAN DORR

CONCEPTUALIZING QUEERNESS

Luck, Rationality, and Explanation: A Reply to Elga s Lucky to Be Rational. Joshua Schechter. Brown University

THE METAPHYSICS OF REASONS

Need Evolutionary Debunking Arguments Rely on a Particular Metaphysical Construal of Evaluative Facts?

DO NORMATIVE JUDGEMENTS AIM TO REPRESENT THE WORLD?

Philosophy 125 Day 21: Overview

Moral Objectivism. RUSSELL CORNETT University of Calgary

Kantian Humility and Ontological Categories Sam Cowling University of Massachusetts, Amherst

Hybridizing moral expressivism and moral error theory

REASON AND PRACTICAL-REGRET. Nate Wahrenberger, College of William and Mary

Primary and Secondary Qualities. John Locke s distinction between primary and secondary qualities of bodies has

Introduction to Cognitivism; Motivational Externalism; Naturalist Cognitivism

The form of relativism that says that whether an agent s actions are right or wrong depends on the moral principles accepted in her own society.

Smith s Incoherence Argument for Moral Rationalism

AN ACTUAL-SEQUENCE THEORY OF PROMOTION

The Limits of Normative Detachment 1 Nishi Shah Amherst College Draft of 04/15/10

Non-Realist Cognitivism, Truth and Objectivity

Explanatory Indispensability and Deliberative Indispensability: Against Enoch s Analogy Alex Worsnip University of North Carolina at Chapel Hill

MAKING A METAPHYSICS FOR NATURE. Alexander Bird, Nature s Metaphysics: Laws and Properties. Oxford: Clarendon, Pp. xiv PB.

NATURALISED JURISPRUDENCE

Ethics of Justification A Defence of Contractualism

EXTERNALISM AND THE CONTENT OF MORAL MOTIVATION

AN OUTLINE OF CRITICAL THINKING

Review of Nathan M. Nobis s Truth in Ethics and Epistemology

MORAL CONCEPTS AND MOTIVATION 1. Mark Greenberg UCLA

What is the "Social" in "Social Coherence?" Commentary on Nelson Tebbe's Religious Freedom in an Egalitarian Age

Ethical non-naturalism

Kant and the Problem of Metaphysics 1. By Tom Cumming

Postmodal Metaphysics

Ethics is subjective.

Judith Jarvis Thomson s Normativity

Lecture 2: What Ethics is Not. Jim Pryor Guidelines on Reading Philosophy Peter Singer What Ethics is Not

The Rightness Error: An Evaluation of Normative Ethics in the Absence of Moral Realism

BOOK REVIEWS. The arguments of the Parmenides, though they do not refute the Theory of Forms, do expose certain problems, ambiguities and

ALTERNATIVE SELF-DEFEAT ARGUMENTS: A REPLY TO MIZRAHI

ON LEAVING ROOM FOR DOUBT: USING FREGE-GEACH TO ILLUMINATE EXPRESSIVISM S PROBLEM WITH OBJECTIVITY

CHECKING THE NEIGHBORHOOD: A REPLY TO DIPAOLO AND BEHRENDS ON PROMOTION

The Philosophical Review, Vol. 100, No. 3. (Jul., 1991), pp

In Defense of Culpable Ignorance

Epistemic Consequentialism, Truth Fairies and Worse Fairies

Ethics (ETHC) JHU-CTY Course Syllabus

Debunking Evolutionary Debunking. Katia Vavova Mount Holyoke College

In this paper I will critically discuss a theory known as conventionalism

DESIRES AND BELIEFS OF ONE S OWN. Geoffrey Sayre-McCord and Michael Smith

IN DEFENSE OF THE PRIMACY OF THE VIRTUES

Nozick and Scepticism (Weekly supervision essay; written February 16 th 2005)

Has Nagel uncovered a form of idealism?

Mark Schroeder s Hypotheticalism: Agent-neutrality, Moral Epistemology, and Methodology

2210 Speedway, Stop C3500, WAG 316, Austin, TX (936)

A DEFENCE OF METAPHYSICAL ETHICAL NATURALISM

Bart Streumer, Unbelievable Errors, Oxford: Oxford University Press, ISBN

There is no need to explain who Hilary Putnam is in light of the sheer number of books and articles on his work that have appeared over the past

The ontology of human rights and obligations

2 Why Truthmakers GONZALO RODRIGUEZ-PEREYRA 1. INTRODUCTION

The Many Problems of Memory Knowledge (Short Version)

Transcription:

DISCUSSION NOTE THE MORAL FIXED POINTS: REPLY TO CUNEO AND SHAFER-LANDAU BY STEPHEN INGRAM JOURNAL OF ETHICS & SOCIAL PHILOSOPHY DISCUSSION NOTE FEBRUARY 2015 URL: WWW.JESP.ORG COPYRIGHT STEPHEN INGRAM 2015

The Moral Fixed Points: Reply to Cuneo and Shafer-Landau A CCORDING TO TERENCE CUNEO and Russ Shafer- Landau, moral nonnaturalists should accept that certain substantive moral propositions are conceptual truths. 1 They call these the moral fixed points, and offer examples like the following: It is pro tanto wrong to engage in the recreational slaughter of a fellow person. There is some moral reason to offer aid to those in distress, if such aid is very easily given and comes at very little expense. If acting justly is costless, then, ceteris paribus, one should act justly. I am sympathetic to moral nonnaturalism, but I am skeptical about the direction in which Cuneo and Shafer-Landau want to take it. We have reason to deny that those who reject the so-called moral fixed points are conceptually deficient, and this undermines the proposal that these moral propositions are conceptual truths. 1. The Proposal Cuneo and Shafer-Landau (411-12) offer the following proposal: There are nonnatural moral truths. These truths include the moral fixed points, which are a species of conceptual truth, as they are propositions that are true in virtue of the essences of their constituent concepts. This is designed to be compatible with any construal of the natural/nonnatural distinction. Cuneo and Shafer-Landau (401-02) prefer a metaphysical construal, on which moral properties and facts are sui generis. The provocative claim is that some nonnatural moral truths are conceptual truths. Conceptual truths are glossed as propositions that are true in virtue of the essences of their constituent concepts. It is of the essence of the concept being human, for example, that it applies to exactly those things that are human. On this view, a proposition [that x is F] is a conceptual truth if it belongs to the essence of F that, necessarily, anything that satisfies x also satisfies F. In the moral case, Cuneo and Shafer-Landau (410) suggest that the moral proposition [that recreational slaughter of a fellow person is wrong] is a conceptual truth in case it belongs to the essence of the concept being wrong that, necessarily, if anything satisfies the concept recreational slaughter of a fellow person, 1 T. Cuneo and R. Shafer-Landau (2014) The Moral Fixed Points: New Directions for Moral Nonnaturalism, Philosophical Studies 171(3): 399-443. All page references are to this text.

it also satisfies the concept being wrong. 2 Cuneo and Shafer-Landau think that this proposal helps answer criticisms of nonnaturalism. 3 However, I am skeptical about there being substantive moral propositions that are conceptual truths. 2. Conceptual Deficiencies If a proposition is a conceptual truth, anyone who rejects it is conceptually deficient in some way. They fail to possess the relevant concepts, or they possess them but fail to understand them, or they possess and understand them but fail to appreciate their implications. To accept Cuneo and Shafer-Landau s proposal is thus to charge those who reject the moral fixed points with conceptual deficiency. However, it is not obvious that those who actually reject the moral fixed points are conceptually deficient. Error theorists, for example, reject the moral fixed points. Are they conceptually deficient? First, what is error theory? The error theorist agrees with the nonnaturalist about the nature of moral discourse, accepting that our use of moral terms involves a nonnegotiable commitment to nonnatural moral properties and facts. However, error theorists disagree with nonnaturalists about metaphysics. They reject nonnatural moral properties and facts, and thus say that moral discourse is in systematic error. The error theorist will thus reject any suggested moral fixed point, saying that it commits us to an unacceptable ontology. Now, if we have reason to deny that error theorists are conceptually deficient, we have reason to deny that the moral fixed points are conceptual truths. So, the key question is this: Are error theorists conceptually deficient in their rejection of the moral fixed points? Cuneo and Shafer-Landau (412-15, 438-39) are sensitive to a version of this worry, acknowledging that their proposal may appear uncharitable to the error theorist. They respond as follows: Nonnaturalists hold that the degree to which the moral fixed points are evident is quite high. But nonnaturalists do not maintain that the moral fixed points are maximally evident. It is possible to wonder, for example, whether one has failed to appreciate the force of various antirealist arguments. It is also possible to wonder whether there is something deeply defective about our moral concepts, which we have not yet appreciated, which would render them incapable of referring to moral properties if any were to exist (414). Cuneo and Shafer-Landau are committed to the accusation of conceptual deficiency, but they allow that error theorists (and their arguments) can and should be taken seriously. They are thus not uncharitable. This response seems a respectable answer to the lack of charity objection, but the matter does not end there. We do not just want to know whether it is 2 Cuneo and Shafer-Landau (408-10) do not identify conceptual truths with analytic truths. They see analytic truths as formal and vacuous, but allow that conceptual truths (including the moral fixed points) can be substantive. 3 They think that it helps answer objections concerning moral disagreement, evolutionary debunking and moral supervenience. 2

uncharitable to accuse the error theorist of conceptual deficiency. We want to know whether the error theorist is actually conceptually deficient. Cuneo and Shafer-Landau do not, as far as I can see, address this more fundamental problem. We are dealing with different points here: To ask whether one can accuse error theorists of conceptual deficiency while taking their views seriously is one thing, but to ask whether error theorists are actually conceptually deficient is another. Even if Cuneo and Shafer-Landau are not being uncharitable, it is possible to deny that error theorists are conceptually deficient (and thus that the moral fixed points are conceptual truths). After all, nonnaturalists cannot charge error theorists with failure to possess or understand moral concepts both parties agree about the nature of moral discourse. Their disagreement is metaphysical rather than conceptual. So the accusation must be that error theorists fail to appreciate what their moral concepts imply. However, it is not enough to simply accuse error theorists of failing to appreciate what their concepts imply. One has to make the case for this accusation, otherwise it is just ad hoc. If the charge of conceptual deficiency remains unsubstantiated, we are entitled to deny that error theorists are conceptually deficient in their rejection of the moral fixed points. And this would entitle us to deny that the moral fixed points are conceptual truths. How, then, might one make a case for thinking that error theorists fail to appreciate the implications of their moral concepts? One suggestion that we might draw from Cuneo and Shafer-Landau s discussion is that error theorists are misled by sophisticated (but unsound) arguments. It is a mistake, Cuneo and Shafer-Landau say, to reject highly evident ethical propositions (like the moral fixed points) by appeal to highly controversial metaethical claims (like the claim that moral properties and facts are queer, or that moral beliefs can be debunked). Cuneo and Shafer- Landau diagnose error theorists as falling foul of this suspect philosophical methodology (438). What exactly they are getting at here is not clear, but they seem to be gesturing at the following line of thought. In philosophical inquiry, good practice involves seeking to accommodate our intuitions about our chosen topic by developing theories that vindicate these intuitions. The error theorist fails to follow good philosophical practice, for their theory repudiates our strongest intuitions by rejecting the moral fixed points. In other words, it is suggested that we can provide indirect support to the charge of conceptual deficiency by pointing to a questionable methodology. The error theorist misses the implications of their concepts as a result of a distorting process of philosophical reasoning, one that gives too much weight to contentious metaethical claims, and too little to first-order moral intuitions. The conceptual deficiency charge is thus not an ad hoc maneuver designed to save the proposal that the moral fixed points are conceptual truths, for the charge is supported indirectly by a methodological diagnosis of the error theorist s situation. However, if this is what Cuneo and Shafer-Landau are getting at, it is not compelling. First off, note that the methodology of which Cuneo and Shafer- Landau are suspicious is widely employed in philosophy. Claims that 3

seem intuitively plausible are often given up in light of deeper reflection and more considered argument. To give some examples, it is intuitively very plausible that time is real, that scientific investigation delivers true theories of reality, that human beings have free will and that moral agents have reasonably stable character traits. Yet, these claims are subject to apparently legitimate debate, and there are philosophers who reject them by appealing to controversial philosophical arguments. If this methodology is suspect when used by error theorists, then it is presumably suspect when used by any philosopher. Perhaps it is indeed a bad methodology wherever it is applied, but we should recognize that a wide range of fields in philosophy would be radically altered if philosophers were directed only to construct theories that accommodate our intuitions. More importantly, Cuneo and Shafer-Landau are wrong to suggest that error theorists operate with a bad methodology. Consider a rough guide to philosophical inquiry. Step one: Identify your intuitions and make them consistent. Step two: Develop a theory that can vindicate these considered intuitions. Test this theory by standard criteria for theory selection. If it passes, accept the theory. If it fails, move to step three. Step three: Revise your theory. If the theory remains problematic, move to step four. Step four: Acknowledge that the intuitions with which you started are in error. Explain why this so. We can understand error theorists as having undergone this process. Most people are likely to find that their moral intuitions, including the moral fixed points, are highly evident. So most error theorists start at step one by attempting to get their moral intuitions in order. They then proceed to step two, and find that nonnaturalism is the most compelling way to vindicate their moral intuitions. However, in testing this theory, error theorists judge it unacceptable. (Perhaps they find nonnatural properties and facts intolerably mysterious.) They thus move to step three, perhaps attempting to naturalize moral properties and facts. But they find that this theory fails to vindicate their moral intuitions. Despite their best efforts, they cannot find a theory that succeeds both in vindicating their moral intuitions and in being ontologically respectable. So, they move to step four. They acknowledge and explain the errors in those moral intuitions that seem highly evident. In short, they arrive at error theory. We can debate whether error theorists are correct. The nonnaturalist may say that the error theorist makes a mistake at step two in thinking nonnaturalism mysterious. Alternatively, one might suggest that the error theorist makes a mistake at step three. This is what expressivists and moral naturalists will say. Either way, there is nothing wrong with the error theorist s methodology. Indeed, it seems that they have proceeded entirely legitimately along our (admittedly rough) four-step program. Importantly, this removes the suggested support for the conceptual deficiency charge. Cuneo and Shafer-Landau lose their justification for saying that error theorists are conceptually deficient in rejecting the moral fixed points. This charge is unsubstantiated and ad hoc, so entirely deniable. 4

3. Conclusion If the charge that error theorists are conceptually deficient in their rejection of the moral fixed points is deniable, so is the claim that the moral fixed points are conceptual truths. Despite being sympathetic to nonnaturalism, I am therefore skeptical of the direction in which Cuneo and Shafer-Landau want to take it. 4 University of Sheffield Department of Philosophy stephen.ingram@sheffield.ac.uk 4 Thanks to Jimmy Lenman for discussion. Thanks also to Lizzy Kirkham, Denise Fox and Shirley Carter. This paper was written during an AHRC doctoral scholarship. 5