Review: The Objects of Thought, by Tim Crane. Guy Longworth University of Warwick

Similar documents
Empty Names and Two-Valued Positive Free Logic

Meaning and Privacy. Guy Longworth 1 University of Warwick December

Reply to Kit Fine. Theodore Sider July 19, 2013

BENEDIKT PAUL GÖCKE. Ruhr-Universität Bochum

Quantificational logic and empty names

Russell on Plurality

ZAGZEBSKI ON RATIONALITY

The Question of Metaphysics

5 A Modal Version of the

Each copy of any part of a JSTOR transmission must contain the same copyright notice that appears on the screen or printed page of such transmission.

Russell on Descriptions

TWO VERSIONS OF HUME S LAW

Leibniz, Principles, and Truth 1

In essence, Swinburne's argument is as follows:

Truth At a World for Modal Propositions

Citation for the original published paper (version of record):

The unity of the normative

Physicalism and Conceptual Analysis * Esa Díaz-León.

Postscript to Plenitude of Possible Structures (2016)

Shieva Kleinschmidt [This is a draft I completed while at Rutgers. Please do not cite without permission.] Conditional Desires.

Introduction. I. Proof of the Minor Premise ( All reality is completely intelligible )

Wright on response-dependence and self-knowledge

Boghossian & Harman on the analytic theory of the a priori

Can Rationality Be Naturalistically Explained? Jeffrey Dunn. Abstract: Dan Chiappe and John Vervaeke (1997) conclude their article, Fodor,

British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 62 (2011), doi: /bjps/axr026

Lecture 3: Properties II Nominalism & Reductive Realism. Lecture 3: Properties II Nominalism & Reductive Realism

Comments on Ontological Anti-Realism

1. Introduction. Against GMR: The Incredulous Stare (Lewis 1986: 133 5).

A Priori Bootstrapping

International Phenomenological Society

Naturalized Epistemology. 1. What is naturalized Epistemology? Quine PY4613

What is the Frege/Russell Analysis of Quantification? Scott Soames

Is there a good epistemological argument against platonism? DAVID LIGGINS

Stang (p. 34) deliberately treats non-actuality and nonexistence as equivalent.

SUPPOSITIONAL REASONING AND PERCEPTUAL JUSTIFICATION

SAVING RELATIVISM FROM ITS SAVIOUR

On possibly nonexistent propositions

EXERCISES, QUESTIONS, AND ACTIVITIES

The Names of God. from Summa Theologiae (Part I, Questions 12-13) by Thomas Aquinas (~1265 AD) translated by Brian Shanley (2006)

Can A Priori Justified Belief Be Extended Through Deduction? It is often assumed that if one deduces some proposition p from some premises

Idealism and the Harmony of Thought and Reality

SIMON BOSTOCK Internal Properties and Property Realism

Luminosity, Reliability, and the Sorites

Generic truth and mixed conjunctions: some alternatives

12. A Theistic Argument against Platonism (and in Support of Truthmakers and Divine Simplicity)

Subjective Logic: Logic as Rational Belief Dynamics. Richard Johns Department of Philosophy, UBC

Williams on Supervaluationism and Logical Revisionism

New Aristotelianism, Routledge, 2012), in which he expanded upon

The normativity of content and the Frege point

Varieties of Apriority

Attraction, Description, and the Desire-Satisfaction Theory of Welfare

Could have done otherwise, action sentences and anaphora

Lonergan on General Transcendent Knowledge. In General Transcendent Knowledge, Chapter 19 of Insight, Lonergan does several things:

On Truth At Jeffrey C. King Rutgers University

Semantic Foundations for Deductive Methods


Williamson, Knowledge and its Limits Seminar Fall 2006 Sherri Roush Chapter 8 Skepticism

Aboutness and Justification

Noncognitivism in Ethics, by Mark Schroeder. London: Routledge, 251 pp.

The Paradox of the Question

Understanding Belief Reports. David Braun. In this paper, I defend a well-known theory of belief reports from an important objection.

Theories of propositions

Is Klein an infinitist about doxastic justification?

A Liar Paradox. Richard G. Heck, Jr. Brown University

Comments on Truth at A World for Modal Propositions

THE FREGE-GEACH PROBLEM AND KALDERON S MORAL FICTIONALISM. Matti Eklund Cornell University

HAVE WE REASON TO DO AS RATIONALITY REQUIRES? A COMMENT ON RAZ

NOTES ON WILLIAMSON: CHAPTER 11 ASSERTION Constitutive Rules

Lecture 4. Before beginning the present lecture, I should give the solution to the homework problem

Ultimate Naturalistic Causal Explanations

1. Introduction Formal deductive logic Overview

Projection in Hume. P J E Kail. St. Peter s College, Oxford.

Class #13 - The Consciousness Theory of the Self Locke, The Prince and the Cobbler Reid, Of Mr. Locke's Account of Our Personal Identity

In Epistemic Relativism, Mark Kalderon defends a view that has become

Privilege in the Construction Industry. Shamik Dasgupta Draft of February 2018

IN DEFENCE OF CLOSURE

Dennett's Reduction of Brentano's Intentionality

Merricks on the existence of human organisms

In Defense of The Wide-Scope Instrumental Principle. Simon Rippon

Has Nagel uncovered a form of idealism?

Review of Constructive Empiricism: Epistemology and the Philosophy of Science

In this paper I offer an account of Christine Korsgaard s metaethical

Martin s case for disjunctivism

Why Counterpart Theory and Three-Dimensionalism are Incompatible. Suppose that God creates ex nihilo a bronze statue of a

Russell: On Denoting

Is the law of excluded middle a law of logic?

Epistemic two-dimensionalism

Is God Good By Definition?

II RESEMBLANCE NOMINALISM, CONJUNCTIONS

Philosophical Logic. LECTURE SEVEN MICHAELMAS 2017 Dr Maarten Steenhagen

Idealism and the Harmony of Thought and Reality

TWO ACCOUNTS OF THE NORMATIVITY OF RATIONALITY

PHL340 Handout 8: Evaluating Dogmatism

INTENTIONAL OBJECTS 1. Tim Crane

Two Kinds of Ends in Themselves in Kant s Moral Theory

On Possibly Nonexistent Propositions

Commentary on Sample Test (May 2005)

Let us begin by first locating our fields in relation to other fields that study ethics. Consider the following taxonomy: Kinds of ethical inquiries

SIMPLICITY AND ASEITY. Jeffrey E. Brower. There is a traditional theistic doctrine, known as the doctrine of divine simplicity,

PHILOSOPHY 4360/5360 METAPHYSICS. Methods that Metaphysicians Use

Transcription:

Review: The Objects of Thought, by Tim Crane. Guy Longworth University of Warwick 24.4.14 We can think about things that don t exist. For example, we can think about Pegasus, and Pegasus doesn t exist. Thus, there are things we can think about that don t exist. Thus, there are things that don t exist. Thus, we need an account of how there can be things that don t exist. That is, we need an account of quantificational uses of There are n Fs, and an account of uses of n Fs exist, such that (for positive n) There are n F s does not entail n Fs exist. And we need an account of the things that don t exist: an account of truths about those things, and of what determines those truths, given that truths are exhaustively determined by what exists. Such are the large tasks attempted by this useful and insightful book, and a sketch of their motivation (which Crane presents in more detail in Chapter 1.) A natural first thought would be that the tasks are needless. We don t really think about things that don t exist. Rather, we sometimes think about nothing. Thinking that there is a largest prime is not thinking about the largest prime, for there s no such thing to be thought about. Thinking that Pegasus is a winged horse is not thinking about Pegasus, for there s no Pegasus to be thought about. Alternatively, we might allow that we really do think about things that don t exist, on some reasonable understanding of thinking about, but deny that it follows that there are things that don t exist. For the alleged entailment seems to depend on the acceptability of two prior claims: claim (1) We can think about Fs that don t exist entails There are Fs we can think about that don t exist ; and claim (2) that There are Fs we can think about that don t exist is a sort of conjunction, and so entails There are Fs that don t exist. And many would balk at those claims. For example, suppose that I think that there is a largest prime. And suppose that we allow that it follows that I m thereby thinking about the largest prime. Still, it would be an implausible leap to reason in accord with claim (1), deriving that there is a largest prime that I m thinking about. And it would be even less plausible to reason in accord with claim (2), to the conclusion that there is a largest prime. One might doubt that we should accept Crane s claims, framed in terms of things, given that we wouldn t accept more specific claims, framed in terms of a largest prime. And if we don t accept Crane s claims, then we should take the claim that there are things we can think about that don t exist as a sort of loose summary of what everyone anyway accepts: people occupy intentional states that are naturally characterised by appeal to apparent singular terms, and apparent quantificational phrases, but where the singular terms do not refer, and the matrices of the phrases are not satisfied. (It will turn out that despite initial appearances, that may ultimately be a version of Crane s positive view about things that do not exist.)

Crane works hard, in chapter 1, to deflect such sceptical responses, and in chapter 2, he offers a sketch of an account of quantificational claims like the claim expressed by There is a largest prime, on which the truth of such claims need not be existence entailing. So, he wants to allow that There is a largest prime might be true while A largest prime exists is false. But the problems in this area seem to run deeper than he allows. For whatever one says about existence, it would be hard to deny that the truth of There is a largest prime requires there to be an element in the domain that satisfies the matrix is a largest prime. But there is no witness for that matrix. So, it appears that There is a largest prime cannot be true, whether or not it entails that a largest prime exists. Crane might respond by denying that there is a largest prime for reasons other than the non-existence of such a number. For example, he might deny it because a mathematical proof terminates in the claim that there is no largest prime, rather than in a claim to the effect that a largest prime does not exist. The question, then, would be this. Suppose that a benighted soul thought that there is a largest prime. According to the pattern of reasoning considered above, that would be grounds for allowing that they are thinking about a largest prime. And it might seem to follow that there is a largest prime that they are thinking about. And that would again run into the difficulty that there isn t. Crane s general response to this pattern of difficulties is the following. His claim is not that when someone thinks that there is a largest prime, and so thinks about the largest prime, there is a largest prime that they are thinking about. Rather, his claim is that when someone thinks that there is a largest prime, so thinks about the largest prime, there is something perhaps a thing that they are thinking about. And in making that claim he needn t be, and isn t, committed to the further claim that what they are thinking about is a largest prime. But if the thing they are thinking about is not the largest prime, what is it? Crane s proposal is that just like the things that exist the things we think about that don t exist have distinctive properties. So, the truths about the things we think about that don t exist go beyond undiscriminating truths like the truth that they don t exist. However, Crane doesn t accept that everything that we think about such things is true of those things. For example, the thing we think about when we think that the largest prime exists is not a largest prime, let alone an existent largest prime. Crane disagrees with those who take a more equitable view about the things we think about the non-existent. He disagrees with those who hold that many, or all, of the things we think about the non-existent are true for example, those who hold that Pegasus is a winged horse. And he disagrees with those who hold that more or less all of the things that we think about the nonexistent are not true (as on negative free logics) for example, those who hold that it s not true that Pegasus is a mythical winged horse. (Chapter 3.) Crane s attempt to take an inequitable view must deal with the following difficulty. Consider the following two sentences.

(1) Pegasus is a horse. (2) Pegasus is a mythical winged horse. Crane seems to endorse the following: A. In (1) and (2), is a horse and is a mythical winged horse work in the same way, to attribute properties to Pegasus: the properties of being a horse and of being a mythical winged horse, respectively. (pp.18 23, p.67) B. (1) is false. (p.55) C. (2) is true. (p.23) A is not perspicuous as it stands. However, it would be natural, if not mandatory, to understand it as implying that the predication in (2) functions in the same way as the predication in (3). (3) Pegasus is a brindle horse. The obvious difficulty is that (3) entails (1). So, the natural understanding of A seems to deliver D: D. (2) entails (1). And now, we need only an application of a natural generalisation about entailment to deliver E: E. If sentence (2) entails sentence (1), then if sentence (2) is true, then sentence (1) is not false. So, we can t accept all of A E. Now it might seem natural to blame A. However, it s not entirely clear how to reject A consistently with a face-value treatment of the embedded predication, and consistently with retaining the claim that (2) attributes a property to Pegasus. It may be that this difficulty figures in explaining the fact that many theorists in this area adopt an equitable view of (1) and (2), so rejecting either B or C. Crane recognises the need to speak to this difficulty, writing: Being a mythological horse is not, of course, being a kind of horse. (p.136. See also p.68, p.135.) But the question raised by the difficulty is, how is this to be explained? Crucially, it must be explained in a way that sustains Crane s claim that being a mythological horse is a property possessed by things. One natural analogy would be with toys. For just as Crane wants to hold that a mythical winged horse need not be a winged horse, it would be natural to hold that a toy winged horse need not be a winged horse. However, it also seems natural to allow that toys are things, and that, for example, a toy winged horse has the property of being a toy in much the same way that a horse has the property of

being a horse. The difficulty, however, is not removed, but only generalized. For if we take this route, we now require a unified account of what is it to be a toy F and what it is to be a mythical F. Furthermore, we would have to face up to the problem that being a toy is existence entailing (pp.59 64, 119 20), for its being true that there is a toy F entails that a toy F exists. Obviously, there is more to be said here. I don t want to suggest that there is no way of defending Crane s collection of commitments. However, I do want to suggest that further work would be required before we are in a position properly to assess the prospects of that collection. Moreover, even if Crane were able to supply a principled way of blocking the problematic transition from (2) to (1), the question would naturally arise: why not seek to impose the blockade at an earlier stage, by providing a means of denying that it follows from the fact that someone is thinking that there is a winged horse that there is some thing about which they are thinking? Suppose the difficulty overcome. We now require an explanation for why the things we think about that don t exist have the specific range of properties they have. And Crane seeks to provide this explanation under the constraint that such an explanation must be given only by appeal to what exists (and properties of what exists). (pp.18 23) Crane proposes what he calls a reductive explanation: a piecemeal explanation of the obtaining of truths about the non-existent on the basis of truths of other kinds. Specifically, Crane aims to explain the truths about the non-existent by appeal to truths about the intentional states, episodes, and processes of existent thinkers. That is, in Crane s terms, aside from certain special cases of properties, like non-existence and self-identity, non-existent things have only representation-dependent properties. (pp.68 71.) One worry here is the following. Suppose that individual thinkers, rather than pluralities of thinkers, are the locus of representation. In that case, one might wonder what makes it so that when you think about Sherlock Holmes, and I think about Sherlock Holmes, there is a single non-existent thing that both of us think about. Crane (pp.162 167) seems to want to deny that there is a single thing, because he denies that such identity claims about non-existents make sense. For him, then, it seems that no one thing has the property of being a famous fictional detective. The most fundamental concern I have about Crane s project is somewhat amorphous. The concern is that the project was motivated by appeal to the fact that our ground level characterisations of people s intentional psychologies make play with embedded commitments to things that don t exist: my belief that there is a largest prime; Eliza s desire for a unicorn; Flo s fear of ghosts. We re tempted to move from those facts to a generalisation, to the effect that in each such case, people think about things that don t exist. And from there, we re tempted to the claim that there are things that don t exist but about which people nonetheless think. The latter claims, then, seem to raise distinctive puzzles, insofar as we take them to carry commitments beyond those carried by the ground level claims that

they systematise. Crane s response is that the latter claims don t really go beyond the ground level claims: their truth is exhaustively explained by appeal to the truth of the ground level claims. But now it s hard to see what explanatory work the claims about things that don t exist are doing and, so, why we should be especially puzzled by those claims. One might think that the deepest puzzles in this area concern the ground level claims themselves, rather than the claims about things that, at best, systematise those ground level claims. That is, the deepest puzzles here concern our capacity to think, for example, that Pegasus flies or that the largest prime is greater than a million, given that neither Pegasus nor the largest prime exist, and not our propensity to characterise such thinking as being about things that don t exist. And it seems to me that it takes us little distance towards resolving those puzzles to be told that such thought in effect creates its own subject matter, albeit without bestowing existence on that subject matter. (Crane briefly considers some of the ground level claims in chapter 6, and the circularity worry in his Concluding Remarks.) Although I m sceptical about the project undertaken in the book, it represents an admirable attempt to clarify various issues surrounding thought about the nonexistent. Whether or not one agrees that there are things that don t exist, or that such thought is about those things, there is much to learn from Crane s discussion, not merely about its central target, but about intentional phenomena more generally. I recommend it highly to those interested not only in the specific matters with which it deals, but also to philosophers of mind more generally.