The Tractatus for Future Poets: Dialectic of the Ladder by B. Ware

Similar documents
Wittgenstein on The Realm of Ineffable

Book Reviews 427. University of Manchester Oxford Rd., M13 9PL, UK. doi: /mind/fzl424

The New Wittgenstein, ed. Alice Crary and Rupert Read, London and New York, 2000, pp. v + 403, no price.

Philosophy Courses-1

Philosophy Courses-1

HAVE WE REASON TO DO AS RATIONALITY REQUIRES? A COMMENT ON RAZ

1 Discuss the contribution made by the early Greek thinkers (the Presocratics) to the beginning of Philosophy.

(Routledge: London and New York, 1974). 1 This unpublished essay was written in 2004, in partial fulfilment of the requirements for the MPhil

Theories of the mind have been celebrating their new-found freedom to study

Foundations of Analytic Philosophy

Who or what is God?, asks John Hick (Hick 2009). A theist might answer: God is an infinite person, or at least an

Reading a Philosophy Text Philosophy 22 Fall, 2019

Department of Philosophy

Tractatus Logico-Philosophicus (abridged version) Ludwig Wittgenstein

The Representation of Logical Form: A Dilemma

On the Rationality of Metaphysical Commitments in Immature Science

Class #3 - Meinong and Mill

Verificationism. PHIL September 27, 2011

In Defense of Pure Reason: A Rationalist Account of A Priori Justification, by Laurence BonJour. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press,

Matters of Fact and Relations of Ideas

Eric Schliesser Philosophy and Moral Sciences, Ghent University ª 2011, Eric Schliesser

Faculty of Philosophy. Double Degree with Philosophy

ON NONSENSE IN THE TRACTATUS LOGICO-PHILOSOPHICUS: A DEFENSE OF THE AUSTERE CONCEPTION

A Major Matter: Minoring in Philosophy. Southeastern Louisiana University. The unexamined life is not worth living. Socrates, B.C.E.

UC Berkeley UC Berkeley Previously Published Works

Conceivability and Possibility Studies in Frege and Kripke. M.A. Thesis Proposal. Department of Philosophy, CSULB. 25 May 2006

Index. Cantor, Georg, 17, 178, , 248n18, 249n25 Capek, Karel, ,

The Philosophy of Physics. Physics versus Metaphysics

UC Davis Philosophy Department Expanded Course Descriptions Fall, 2009

Shanghai Jiao Tong University. PI900 Introduction to Western Philosophy

Proposal for: The Possibility of Philosophical Understanding: Essays for Barry Stroud

Denis Seron. Review of: K. Mulligan, Wittgenstein et la philosophie austro-allemande (Paris: Vrin, 2012). Dialectica

Death and Immortality (by D Z Phillips) Introductory Remarks

Wittgenstein and Moore s Paradox

Holtzman Spring Philosophy and the Integration of Knowledge

Mysticism and Nonsense in the Tractatus

Todays programme. Background of the TLP. Some problems in TLP. Frege Russell. Saying and showing. Sense and nonsense Logic The limits of language

Edmund Dain. and Wittgenstein s opposition or hostility to that tradition. My aim will be to argue that

WITTGENSTEIN S TRACTATUS

John Haugeland. Dasein Disclosed: John Haugeland s Heidegger. Edited by Joseph Rouse. Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 2013.

PH 463/663 Philosophy of Language, Spring 2019 Professor Juliet Floyd, Boston University

Ayer s linguistic theory of the a priori

Epistemology Naturalized

1 Hans Jonas, The Imperative of Responsibility: In Search of an Ethics for the Technological Age (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1984), 1-10.

Bertrand Russell Proper Names, Adjectives and Verbs 1

Phil 3121: Modern Philosophy Fall 2016 T, Th 3:40 5:20 pm

On Searle on Human Rights, Again! J. Angelo Corlett, San Diego State University

Honours Programme in Philosophy

Negative Facts. Negative Facts Kyle Spoor

Self-Evidence and A Priori Moral Knowledge

LODGE VEGAS # 32 ON EDUCATION

If we can t assert this, we undermine the truth of the scientific arguments too. So, Kanterian says: A full

Ayer on the criterion of verifiability

Existentialism. Course number PHIL 291 section A1 Fall 2014 Tu-Th 9:30-10:50am ED 377

Tools for Logical Analysis. Roger Bishop Jones

The Language Revolution Russell Marcus Fall 2014

Review of Who Rules in Science?, by James Robert Brown

Philosophy Faculty Reading List and Course Outline PART II PAPER 09: WITTGENSTEIN READING LIST

DEPARTMENT OF PHILOSOPHY FALL 2013 COURSE DESCRIPTIONS

G. H. von Wright (1916 )

Fundamentals of Metaphysics

COURSE GOALS: PROFESSOR: Chris Latiolais Philosophy Department Kalamazoo College Humphrey House #202 Telephone # Offices Hours:

Action in Special Contexts

Masters in Logic and Metaphysics

Peter L.P. Simpson January, 2015

Choosing Rationally and Choosing Correctly *

Philosophy of Economics and Politics

Philosophy in Review XXXIII (2013), no. 1

Unit 2. WoK 1 - Perception. Tuesday, October 7, 14

Philosophy A465: Introduction to Analytic Philosophy Loyola University of New Orleans Ben Bayer Spring 2011

UNIVERSITY OF MALTA THE MATRICULATION EXAMINATION ADVANCED LEVEL

Kant and the Problem of Metaphysics 1. By Tom Cumming

Aspects of Western Philosophy Dr. Sreekumar Nellickappilly Department of Humanities and Social Sciences Indian Institute of Technology, Madras

To the first questions the answers may be obtained by employing the process of going and seeing, and catching and counting, respectively.

ISSA Proceedings 1998 Wilson On Circular Arguments

The Resolute Reading and Its Critics: An Introduction to the Literature 1

Self-Evidence in Finnis Natural Law Theory: A Reply to Sayers

Twentieth-Century Analytic Philosophy by Avrum Stroll

Kevin MacNeil, Culver Academies

What Is Existentialism? COPYRIGHTED MATERIAL. Chapter 1. In This Chapter

Supplementary Section 6S.7

DEPARTMENT OF PHILOSOPHY FALL 2014 COURSE DESCRIPTIONS

Introduction to Technical Communications 21W.732 Section 2 Ethics in Science and Technology Formal Paper #2

Rejecting Jackson s Knowledge Argument with an Account of a priori Physicalism

Metaphysical atomism and the attraction of materialism.

It doesn t take long in reading the Critique before we are faced with interpretive challenges. Consider the very first sentence in the A edition:

Primitive Thisness and Primitive Identity by Robert Merrihew Adams (1979)

FIL217 / FIL317 - Wittgenstein studies. 1st lecture : - Nachlass & work(s) - Problems of the Tractatus

PHILOSOPHY. Minor in Philosophy. Philosophy, B.A. Ethical theory: One course required. History: Two courses required.

THE AIM OF THIS PAPER IS TO PROVIDE AN OVERVIEW OF ONE ASPECT OF

Pihlström, Sami Johannes.

EXAMINERS REPORT AM PHILOSOPHY

Contemporary Theology I: Hegel to Death of God Theologies

Correspondence. From Charles Fried Harvard Law School

Resemblance Nominalism and counterparts

Revolution and Reaction: Political Thought From Kant to Nietzsche

UNITY OF KNOWLEDGE (IN TRANSDISCIPLINARY RESEARCH FOR SUSTAINABILITY) Vol. I - Philosophical Holism M.Esfeld

Review of Constructive Empiricism: Epistemology and the Philosophy of Science

THE NATURE OF NORMATIVITY IN KANT S PHILOSOPHY OF LOGIC REBECCA V. MILLSOP S

The Oxford Handbook of Epistemology

Transcription:

The Tractatus for Future Poets: Dialectic of the Ladder by B. Ware Kevin Cahill Ben Ware, Dialectic of the Ladder: Wittgenstein, the Tractatus and Modernism. London: Bloomsbury, 2015, xix+212 pp. On a flight to Oslo in the summer of 2016, one of two young men sitting to my left asked me in unmistakable American English if I were an electrical engineer. I answered No, but why do you ask? to which one of them responded Because of the book you are reading. The book I was reading, or more particularly, the chapter of the book I was reading, was on electricity and electrical circuits. The book itself was a standard introductory physics textbook used in Norway. I was on my way to Oslo for the weekend to help my middle stepdaughter cram for her physics exam. As it turned out, both young men were recent graduates from U.C. Berkeley, my alma mater. One had studied computer science, the other chemical engineering. They were taking some time off of work to see a bit of Europe. We got to talking about the two different undergraduate physics series traditionally offered at Berkeley. I assumed, rightly, that they took the same series as I had taken (although in my day it was the Physics 5 series, now it s Physics 7). This was the series described as Physics for Scientists and Engineers. Basically, this was the physics series one ought to take if one studied physics, chemistry, or engineering. It made relatively extensive use of mathematics. The other physics series, Physics 8, was intended for premed students and those in the life sciences (whom I suppose were not being counted as scientists, oddly enough.) Anyway, Physics 8 made rather less use of mathematics. As a biochemistry major, I could take whichever of the two I pleased. Out of stupid pride, I took Physics 5, which resulted in a string of mediocre grades. And then there was Physics 10. This was a course offered to non-science majors to satisfy a so-called breadth requirement. It was an entirely 139

Book Reviews CC-BY conceptual presentation of the main ideas of physics without any math (or hardly any math). I now think such courses have an important role to play at universities and would never denigrate them at all. Still, in my day we used to refer to Physics 10 as Physics for Poets. Before leaving the plane, I asked my two fellow alumnae if Physics for Poets was offered when they were still students. One of them responded Oh sure. But now they call it Physics for Future Presidents. In The Dialectic of the Ladder: Wittgenstein, the Tractatus, and Modernism Ben Ware attempts to shed light on some of the more puzzling aspects of Wittgenstein s first book by examining it through the prism of literary modernism. Though it goes against the mainstream of traditional Tractatus interpretation, according to which the book is usually treated as an idiosyncratic work of philosophical logic, such an approach is not unmotivated, especially as Wittgenstein himself wrote to a potential publisher that the book is strictly philosophical and literary at the same time. This suggests that any just treatment of the book must address its literary character as internal to its philosophical ambitions, whatever they may be. Suffice it to say, for most of its interpretative history the literary character of the Tractatus has been given rather short shrift. This began to change substantially about 30 years ago, in particular with the work of Cora Diamond, the founder of what has come to be known as resolute approaches to reading the book. While Diamond s writings on the Tractatus kept such logical topics as the nature of the proposition, inference, the nature of a Begriffsschrift, and definite descriptions at the forefront of her treatment, she also paid much more serious attention than other scholars previously had to perplexing features of the work such as Wittgenstein s calling his Sätze nonsense at the book s second-tolast remark, 6.54, and, to Wittgenstein s comment in the same letter to the potential editor already mentioned, where he describes the aim of the book as an ethical one. One of Diamond s most controversial claims, perhaps the first pillar in resolute readings, is that when Wittgenstein tells the reader at 6.54 that the person who understands him must recognize his Sätze as nonsense and so throw these Sätze away, he really means it. Ware wishes to draw our attention away from what I above called logical topics and to the book s strictly literary character while doing justice to what he takes to be the overall correctness of a resolute approach to reading the book. It is with this goal in mind that he thinks treating the Tractatus as a work of literary high modernism is fruitful. Such an approach has promise, but given that Wittgenstein chose to pursue his ethical aim largely by employing the tropes of Frege s and Russell s work on logic, any attempt at clarifying the Tractatus that so substantially eschews these themes as does Ware s had better get almost 222

everything else just right. Given the fact that the blurbs for the book suggest that finally someone has given us a way really to read the Tractatus the way in which it was supposed to be read I think Ware s book comes up short in some significant ways. Chapter One provides some of the cultural and intellectual backdrop to the Tractatus. I didn t find anything exactly wrong with this chapter, but neither did I find anything particularly new. Much of it can be found in Janik and Toulmin s 1973 Wittgenstein s Vienna, granted without the particular modernist take Ware s narrative provides. One thing I wished this chapter had had more of was an in depth philosophical and historical treatment of the problems that modernism was meant to respond to. I think, for example, that it would have been worthwhile to explore Stanley Cavell s idea that connects the advent of modernism (and the modern more generally) to difficulties that arise when, for various reasons, philosophical, aesthetic, and moral traditions become increasingly difficult to inherit. 1 Chapter 2 is a reasonably clear and accurate retelling of the state of Tractatus scholarship that is relevant for Ware s overall project. But again, it doesn t contain much that is new for those who have followed the 1 Several of the essays in Cavell s (Harvard, 1969) Must We Mean What We Say touch on this issue. See especially A Matter of Meaning It. relevant debates. It does, unfortunately, repeat a now tired falsehood however, viz. that Frank Ramsey s quip But what we can t say we can t say can t say, and we can t whistle it either was directed at what Ramsey took to be Wittgenstein s attempt to show ineffable truths by the use of what P.M.S. Hacker calls illuminating nonsense. This should have been laid to rest some time ago. 2 I was also struck by Ware s claim (p. 65) that In the Tractatus, the poetic quality of the writing is evident not only in the epigrammatic style of the sentences themselves, but also, and more importantly, in the way in which every word makes a vital contribution to the whole. The writing, as it stands, is perfectly complete in it nothing is superfluous nor is there anything missing. This seems a bit much, given Wittgenstein s own concession in the preface regarding the slightness of his powers. Chapter 3 deals with (mostly middle and later) Wittgenstein s 2 See Cora Diamond (2011), We Can t Whistle it Either, European Journal of Philosophy, 19: 335-356. The original remark by Ramsey can be found at F.P. Ramsey, General Propositions and Causality (1931), in The Foundations of Mathematics and other Logical Essays, edited by R.B. Braithewaite, 238. London: Routledge and Kegan Paul. 223

Book Reviews CC-BY views about culture, modernity, politics, and scientific progress. Ware claims, correctly I think, that Wittgenstein s overall views on these matters were largely continuous throughout his life, although most of his discussion here concerns not how these views infuse the early work but concern influences such as Spengler whom Wittgenstein picked up somewhat later. Most of what is said is fine as far as it goes; but it doesn t go beyond by what has been said elsewhere. There is one point that must be mentioned where Ware s book goes completely off of the rails. This is in his discussion of some of the political implications of Wittgenstein s philosophical quietism. In particular, PI 124 (a remark that never ceases to send certain members of the political left into paroxysms) in which Wittgenstein writes that Philosophy may in no way interfere with the actual use of language; it can in the end only describe it. For it cannot give it any foundation either. It leaves everything as it is is connected to what Ware (94) calls Wittgenstein s hollowed out political perspective. This, we hear, is a product of among other things Wittgenstein s failure to grasp the working class as the collective agent of social (and intellectual) change We are then treated to a serious misreading of a discussion about philosophy with Rush Rhees, followed by the implication that Wittgenstein s calling Ramsey a bourgeois thinker is perhaps a bit hypocritical as the discussion with Rhees shows his own bourgeois attachment to the ideal of the autonomous, free-thinking intellectual If by philosophy Wittgenstein meant something like intelligent, well-reasoned discussion of important topics like politics, religion, morals, and art, then perhaps Ware s accusation could get some traction. But Wittgenstein doesn t mean this; he means almost always two things (in sometimes seamless alteration): metaphysics and the critique of metaphysics. Any critique Wittgenstein might have voiced against Marxism (or any other political philosophy) would have been directed at its metaphysically foundationalist ambitions, the seeking of which he would have regarded as a diversion from the quest for a better society. 3 I thought Chapter 4 on the question of the limits of language was the best chapter in the book. It situates the Tractatus as a kind of modernist Trojan horse among other modernist works, undermining from within as it were strains of ineffabilism about the limits of language within modernist literature itself. Chapter 5 is a reading of Kafka s story Der Bau in terms of the Tractatus relation to modernism. Since literature is not my field, I can only say that even if I thought the 3 As for his calling Ramsey a bourgeois thinker, I suspect that he meant to say something to the effect that Ramsey was a practitioner of the philosophical equivalent of what Kuhn calls normal science. 224

motivation behind this chapter appealing, there were some problems with the execution. The interpretive function and placement of the biographical references to Wittgenstein s work as a designer seemed unclear to me, even if on the surface one could understand the temptation to connect just these facts to an interpretation of precisely this Kafka story. Finally, the use of Heidegger s concept of anxiety seemed a bit simplistic to me. Overall, Ware s book is wellwritten and very accessible. It is a worthwhile effort at delineating the contours of an important and too often neglected topic. But as I have stated above, a bit too much of the book rehashes already available literature and there are a few serious problems with some important details. University of Bergen, Norway kevin.cahill @ uib.no 225