REVIEW DISCUSSION. A. Drummond: Law, Politics and Power: Sallust and the Execution of the Catilinarian Conspirators. Pp Steiner, DM 64.

Similar documents
hij Teacher Resource Bank A-level Classical Civilisation Exemplar Answers CIV1F

Instructor: Fred K. Drogula, Ascension 323 (PBX 5436), home: Office Hours: T TH 11:30-1:30pm, W 2:30-4:00pm, and by appointment

This document consists of 10 printed pages.

DISCUSSION PRACTICAL POLITICS AND PHILOSOPHICAL INQUIRY: A NOTE

PITTSBURGH. Issued: March 1993 Revised: October 2002 Updated: August 2003 Updated: August 2006 Updated: March 2008 Updated: April 2014

Templates for Research Paper

EXECUTION AND INVENTION: DEATH PENALTY DISCOURSE IN EARLY RABBINIC. Press Pp $ ISBN:

Templates for Writing about Ideas and Research

Sentence Starters from They Say, I Say

JULIUS CAESAR SHINE Assessment

Commentary on Sample Test (May 2005)

Index of Templates from They Say, I Say by Gerald Graff and Cathy Birkenstein. Introducing What They Say. Introducing Standard Views

Changes and Questions by 121BCE

LAW04. Law and Morals. The Concepts of Law

U.S. Bishops Revise Part Six of the Ethical and Religious Directives An Initial Analysis by CHA Ethicists 1

Each copy of any part of a JSTOR transmission must contain the same copyright notice that appears on the screen or printed page of such transmission.

Faculty of Classics: Guidance on Commentaries and Gobbets

If Everyone Does It, Then You Can Too Charlie Melman

William Shakespeare s Julius Caesar

ACADEMIC SKILLS PROGRAM STUDENT SERVICES AND DEVELOPMENT

b. Use of logic in reasoning; c. Development of cross examination skills; d. Emphasis on reasoning and understanding; e. Moderate rate of delivery;

A Contractualist Reply

Jesus: The Centerpiece of the Bible

How a Republic Falls Political Science (upper-level seminar)

CONVENTIONALISM AND NORMATIVITY

Writing Module Three: Five Essential Parts of Argument Cain Project (2008)

Does Deduction really rest on a more secure epistemological footing than Induction?

-- The search text of this PDF is generated from uncorrected OCR text.

by William Shakespeare Essential Question: How does the quest for power and/or fame lead us to act with honor or shame?

The First Conspiracy of Catiline. Sarah Barnett

Julius Caesar By: William Shakespeare

1. Tiberius Gracchus: Gaius Gracchus: Civil War: Spartacan Revolt: Cataline First Triumvirate:

Compromise and Toleration: Some Reflections I. Introduction

Two Kinds of Ends in Themselves in Kant s Moral Theory

An Introduction to the People and the Power of. Beginning August 28, 2005 On

Introduction to Philosophy: Socrates, Horses & Corruption Dr. Michael C. LaBossiere Revised: 4/26/2013

PROFESSOR HARTS CONCEPT OF LAW SUBAS H. MAHTO LEGAL THEORY F.Y.LLM

PROSPECTS FOR A JAMESIAN EXPRESSIVISM 1 JEFF KASSER

Pilate's Extended Dialogues in the Gospel of John: Did the Evangelist alter a written source?

The majority. This is democracy. In almost any society, the majority can look after itself. - Lord Bingham

Parallel Lives. Mark Antony BCE

Louisiana Law Review. Cheney C. Joseph Jr. Louisiana State University Law Center. Volume 35 Number 5 Special Issue Repository Citation

BASIC SENTENCE PATTERNS

Is there a good epistemological argument against platonism? DAVID LIGGINS

Study Guide: Julius Caesar. Act I Scene ii

Jean Jacques Rousseau The Social Contract, or Principles of Political Right (1762)

BE IT THEREFORE RESOLVED by the Bishop Clergy and Laity of the Diocese of Perth in Synod assembled

CLASSICAL STUDIES HIGHER LEVEL

This review first appeared in Heythrop Journal 41 (2000), pp and is

Templates for Introducing Standard Views (what everybody thinks) Templates for Making what they say something you Say

1 Ted Kirnbauer Galatians 2: /25/14

SANDEL ON RELIGION IN THE PUBLIC SQUARE

Eschatology and Soteriology. A Review of Hawley s Articles By Marty Cauley 8/8/2012

2. Public Forum Debate seeks to encourage the development of the following skills in the debaters: d. Reasonable demeanor and style of presentation

Section 8 - The Clergy Discipline Measure

WEST POTOMAC HIGH SCHOOL HONOR CODE

New Men Dying Republic

Law and Authority. An unjust law is not a law

MANUAL ON MINISTRY. Commissioned Ministry. United Church of Christ. Section 6 of 10

Colossians 1:1-8 Thursday 2/05/13

THE MOST IMPORTANT QUESTION IN THE WORLD

Commonwealth of Kentucky Court of Appeals

RES PUBLICA ROMAE 509/510 BCE 27 BCE

M.A. Martins (May-June 23) (June 24-August 24) May Dear English 12/L1 student:

AMERICAN CENTER FOR LAW AND JUSTICE S MEMORANDUM OF LAW REGARDING THE CRIMINAL TRIAL OF ABDUL RAHMAN FOR CONVERTING FROM ISLAM TO CHRISTIANITY

WEST POTOMAC HIGH SCHOOL HONOR CODE

The Church s Neglected Priorities

Take Home Exam #2. PHI 1700: Global Ethics Prof. Lauren R. Alpert

BCO AMENDMENTS SENT DOWN TO PRESBYTERIES BY THE 46 th GENERAL ASSEMBLY FOR VOTING, and for ADVICE AND CONSENT

JUDICIAL COUNCIL OF THE UNITED METHODIST CHURCH DECISION 1315

2.3. Failed proofs and counterexamples

General Certificate of Education Advanced Subsidiary Examination June 2011

IN DEFENCE OF CLOSURE

Evaluating the New Perspectives on Paul (7)

Genre Guide for Argumentative Essays in Social Science

421 (planning to ambush and kill him on the way). Verse 4. But Festus replied that Paul was at Caesarea and he himself would be returning there soon.

FRANK JACKSON AND ROBERT PARGETTER A MODIFIED DUTCH BOOK ARGUMENT. (Received 14 May, 1975)

Study Guide: Academic Writing

Theory of Knowledge. 5. That which can be asserted without evidence can be dismissed without evidence. (Christopher Hitchens). Do you agree?

Insider and Outsider Scholarship in Bahá í Studies

Bishop s Report To The Judicial Council Of The United Methodist Church

ASSEMBLIES OF THE LORD JESUS CHRIST

A R G U M E N T S I N A C T I O N

Israel Kirzner is a name familiar to all readers of the Review of

In this article we will consider further the case

Guide Unit 4 Rome: Augustus. S 3/28 RFC 3-6 Frivolous Inspirations (I - 15:30-28:30) RFC 6-8 An Innocent Face (I - 28:30-37:15)

Attfield, Robin, and Barry Wilkins, "Sustainability." Environmental Values 3, no. 2, (1994):

Civil War Marius and Sulla

OSSA Conference Archive OSSA 8

Explanatory Indispensability and Deliberative Indispensability: Against Enoch s Analogy Alex Worsnip University of North Carolina at Chapel Hill

Choosing Rationally and Choosing Correctly *

AS RELIGIOUS STUDIES. Component 1: Philosophy of religion and ethics Report on the Examination June Version: 1.0

In Epistemic Relativism, Mark Kalderon defends a view that has become

PLANTINGA ON THE FREE WILL DEFENSE. Hugh LAFoLLETTE East Tennessee State University

GOD'S SOLUTION: A MERCIFUL HIGH PRIEST

Comparing Republics. Rome Powers America. Consuls EXECUTIVE President. *Senate *Centuriate Assembly *Tribal Assembly. *House of Representatives

A Case against Subjectivism: A Reply to Sobel

DORE CLEMENT DO THEISTS NEED TO SOLVE THE PROBLEM OF EVIL?

Reid s dilemma and the uses of pragmatism

Reading/Study Guide: Rorty and his Critics. Richard Rorty s Universality and Truth. I. The Political Context: Truth and Democratic Politics (1-4)

Transcription:

Histos 1 (1997) 199-204 REVIEW DISCUSSION A. Drummond: Law, Politics and Power: Sallust and the Execution of the Catilinarian Conspirators. Pp. 136. Steiner, 1995. DM 64. The issues which D. expresses his intention of addressing are the interaction of law and politics and the protection of individual liberties. This involves him in seeking answers to a number of questions concerning the nature and purpose of S. s account, most of them centred on the relevance (or not) of the scu. Was there debate about the legality of the executions under the scu and/or under normal law? Was Caesar s speech directed against the scu in general or in this particular case, did Cato claim that the scu legitimated the executions, or was the scu irrelevant to the debate? What is the purpose of the syncrisis of Caesar and Cato? D. first examines the setting for the debate. The account of Cicero s vacillations in BC 46.2 is unflattering, but its accuracy is confirmed by Plut. Cic. 19.5-20.3. D. rightly says (11ff.) that for Cicero to bring the issue of the punishment of the guilty to the senate so soon after the revelation of the conspiracy was at the very least to invite a vote for execution. But S. is here not primarily concerned with the nature or justification of any punishment His point is more basic: that the imposition of any penalty, regardless of its nature, the procedures adopted and their legality, would bring inuidia upon Cicero. (In passing D. makes a good case against identifying the absentee of Cic. Cat. 4.10 with Crassus; either Nepos or Bestia is to be preferred.) S. s account (BC 46.3-47.4) of the senate meeting of 3/12 strikingly omits any reference to the scepticism of many senators towards Cicero s revelations. Everything is presented as undisputed fact; it is therefore impossible even to enquire what was alleged, much less what was proved, on that day. In discussing (18f.) the consequences of the meeting (BC 48.1-49.4) D. rightly stresses that the most important factor was the immediate revulsion of popular feeling against the conspiracy. But his argument that even earlier popular support had been less than is sometimes assumed is not wholly convincing. He makes a better case (20f.) for his claim that all the attempts to implicate Caesar postdate his stance in the senate on 5/12. Turning to the immediate context of the debate of 5/12 (BC 50.1-3) D. argues that the possibility of an attempt to rescue the conspirators was never a serious consideration. S. s account proceeds logically, in a manner consistent with his position in 46.3ff.: the reference to the decree that the conspirators had acted contra rem publicam again implies that the senate had already judged them guilty and that the only question still to be decided was the penalty. D. then jumps from this point, with the silence of Cic. Cat. 4.5 as his Copyright 1997 Robin Seager

200 Robin Seager springboard, to the suggestion that S. invented the decree. That is possible, but hardly certain. The senate was alarmed and no doubt somewhat confused; its actions may not have been dictated by strict logic or a concern for the convenience of future historians. On the preliminaries to Caesar s speech (BC 50.3-5) D. first confronts the question of Nero s motive (24). He argues strongly in favour of the view that Nero was urging only a brief delay, not the postponement of proceedings until after the defeat of Catiline (as App. BC 2.5). This, as he says, is plausible, but as a response to Caesar s speech, not where S. places it. But S., to give added force to the clash between Caesar and Cato, completely ignores the course of the debate between their respective contributions. D. rightly prefers S. s version of Silanus second thoughts to that of Plutarch and Suetonius. He then turns (28ff.) to Caesar s refutation of Silanus (BC 51.1-24). Caesar claims that security is irrelevant, but does not make a good case, for his argument neglects the situation outside Rome. His essential point is that the law always offers exile as an alternative to execution, but he never denies the conspirators guilt and makes no attack on the legality of execution without trial, whether in the name of prouocatio or of the lex Sempronia. D. concludes (32) that Caesar is concerned chiefly or wholly with the historical modification of judicial penalties. But his point may perhaps have been rather simpler: since Silanus was prepared to ignore one set of laws, why not the lex Porcia as well? Caesar s reflections on the dangers of a nouom exemplum (BC 51.25-36) involve some special pleading concerning indemnati. He cites the execution of indemnati by the Thirty, but does not bring out this aspect of the Sullan proscriptions. The distinction lies in the fact that at Athens execution after trial was commonplace. That Caesar should nevertheless pair the Thirty and Sulla suggests, as D. argues, that he was more concerned with the abuse of the ruling power s right to execute than with its victims right to trial. D. also makes a strong case (33f.) against identifying the decree of BC 51.36 with the scu; it must rather be something comparable with the present proposal of Silanus. His disparaging remarks on the imprecision of the alleged parallels with the actions of Octavian in 43 are also cogent, and his point that these words are relevant rather to the general situation in 63 is correspondingly well taken. It might have been worth mentioning here the accusations of falsifying the record brought against Cicero by Torquatus (Cic. Sull.40ff.) The continuing stress throughout the account of Caesar s own proposal (BC 51.37-43) on the perils of a nouom consilium refers again, as D. rightly contends, to the possibility of a new form of penalty, not to the possibly extralegal circumstances of its application. Caesar himself is proposing a penalty, not just a remand in custody, but legality is central to his argument (37). This

Review of Drummond, Law, Politics and Power 201 is undoubtedly true, but it comes as something of a surprise to see it firmly stated here, given the thrust of D. s argument so far. So much for S. s account of Caesar s speech and proposal. D. next attempts to assess its historicity. He suggests that transcripts may have been taken on 5/12, as they had been two days before, but that these were perhaps intended chiefly for Cicero s personal archive. This is a surprising suggestion; those taken on 3/12 were on Cicero s own account intended for the widest circulation (Cic. Sull. 42). However, his conclusion (39f.), from the standard rhetorical flavour of the speech, the Sallustian character of its themes (true also of the speech of S. s Cato) and the weakness of its arguments, that it is a free composition can hardly be challenged. D. then goes beyond his self-imposed brief of merely interpreting S. by wondering if there is any possibility of coming close to what Caesar actually said. He examines the fourth Catilinarian, delivered between the speeches of Caesar and Cato and probably not the subject of drastic rewriting between delivery and publication. His conclusion (43f.) is pessimistic but prudent: S. may have used Cicero, but there is no proof that Cicero used Caesar. (He is perhaps, however, wrong to suggest that the argument that the conspirators had made themselves hostes by their actions did not outlive its author; a form of it recurs at Amm. 29.5.23 adjacent to an appeal to the authority of Cicero.) On Cato s speech and its call to action (BC 52.2-35) D. notes the parallels with the Mytilene debate in Thucydides, with Caesar as Diodotus and Cato as Cleon, but he rightly emphasises (52f.) that there are also significant differences. The crucial claims are pragmatic: the very existence of the res publica is at stake, and the execution of the conspirators is essential to ensure the defeat of Catiline in the field. Cato s proposal too (BC 52.36) seems tailored to justify the execution itself; it does not appear concerned with the issue of execution without trial. D. argues (60ff.) against the idea that manifesti and confessi were regularly punished without trial. The argument in the case of manifesti is relatively simple and convincing. In civil law confession did bring matters to a conclusion, provided it was made in proper legal form and unconditional. But in criminal cases the tendency was rather to abandon the case or keep silent. Cato seems to be claiming that confessi should be executed like manifesti, but he may not be telling the truth. Certainly, as D. remarks (72), a justificatory analogy was highly desirable given the dubious nature of the conspirators alleged confessions, on which he makes pertinent observations (75). Like Caesar s, Cato s speech must be dismissed as largely unhistorical, composed with an eye to future popularis criticism and exhibiting the speaker s own future persona. The wording of the motion is also Sallustian. D. then rejects the conventional view that Cato emerges superior from the

202 Robin Seager debate and subsequent syncrisis. His argument (77) is that both speakers achieve significant success, because Cato makes a concession over the four absentees. But it is hard to see this as anything more than a consolation goal for Caesar at the end of a crushing defeat. D. now turns to the scu, beginning with S. s account of it. The general assumption, as he says, is that S. regarded the judgement and execution of the conspirators as legitimised by the scu and that his account of the debate of 5/12 rests on this view. D. admits that this is possible, though S. would in that case have been wrong, but prefers an alternative interpretation, for which he presents a cogent case: namely that the scu should be seen as the culmination of what has gone before, rather than as the formal justification of what follows. Its significance as a turning-point is thus limited. Up to that point Cicero has been acting alone; thereafter, he at least has the senate s support. But S. cannot be absolved of misrepresentation. He attempts to present as specific constitutional prerogatives powers that were in fact entirely contingent on political consensus in an individual situation. D. bolsters this conclusion with pertinent observations on the relative importance at Rome of inherited practice as against formal statute, though inherited practice was always liable to change and adaptation. In passing he delivers himself of sound views (84f.) on the nature of Labienus case against Rabirius and Cicero s attempt to distort it. (To the instances cited at 85 n. 37 of Cicero s practice of claiming for an event a wider political significance than it in fact possessed might be added Rosc. Am. 7, 11, 14 from the outset of his forensic career and Deiot. 3, 30 from its twilight.) He is also good (85ff.) on the reasons why individual court cases did not play a major role in modifying constitutional norms, while rightly insisting that the successful assertion of a constitutional norm itself depended on the achievement of a consensus. D. moves further from S. to consider other aspects of the scu. It did not indicate what powers magistrates might use. Nor, he claims, did it name those whose actions threatened the res publica. This is uncertain. Cic. Cat. 1.3 may well be regarded with suspicion, but Sall. Hist. 1.77.22M (the proposal of the scu by L. Marcius Philippus) does specify Lepidus and his activities as the ground for the decree. Its very generality made it attractive, but also laid it open to challenge. Hence the desire of those who had recourse to it to demonstrate the endorsement of their course of action by the more reputable elements of society. The public interest or the wishes of the senate could always be cited in court as possible good grounds for ignoring the letter of the law, but they might not be deemed sufficient or binding for the future, and the scu did not change that. For instance the acquittal of Opimius in 120 did not establish the right of future consuls armed with the scu to ignore prouocatio.

Review of Drummond, Law, Politics and Power 203 Thus in the present case the real questions to be asked are whether prior practice justified Cicero s assumption that the scu entitled him to inflict the death penalty and whether that view won general acceptance. The answers, as D. says, are clearly no and no. There was no valid precedent for Cicero s action. The characters concerned were upper class, guilty of no open violence, and the scu had been passed a considerable time before - well before, one might add, the alleged activities of Lentulus and company were known about. Indeed the scu seems to have played little part in discussion at the time or later. Cicero s argument that the conspirators had made themselves hostes is not linked to the scu; it clearly does not rest on any theory that the scu could somehow cause automatic forfeiture of citizen rights. The doctrine, for what it is worth, is more likely to derive from the spate of hostis declarations that began in 88. (D. draws a maliciously apt parallel with Ti. Gracchus claim that Octavius deserved deposition for betraying the function of the tribunate, while stressing that this claim had required confirmation by the people.) A parallel can justly be drawn (99) between Cicero s conduct here and his later advocacy of flagrant disregard of the laws whenever his own conception of the interests of the res publica demanded it. But neither now nor later did Cicero s arguments have any chance of winning acceptance; D. rightly cites the senate s resistance to his efforts to have Antony declared a hostis, likewise the attitude of Brutus. D. emphasises that the scu did not provide the justification that Cicero wanted and needed. It conspicuously left to the consuls the choice of the methods to be employed in saving the state from harm, whereas Cicero wanted to present himself as the instrument of the senate s will. This would protect him against accusations of personal vendetta, cruelty and tyranny by giving political authority to his decision. He knew that he could not evade responsibility; indeed, he sometimes claims the credit for a triumph in the cause of senatus auctoritas and concordia ordinum. Had he been brought to trial, there were various lines of argument he might have pursued, in which both the scu and the senate s vote of 5/12 might have figured. But again D. does well to highlight the fact that there was no legal position in any simple sense.

204 Robin Seager Valuable though D. s treatment of S. is, he is at his best when the exegesis of his author inexorably leads him on to wider issues. Whatever disagreements of detail his views may provoke, his approach is always fundamentally sound, for it never loses sight of the essential fact that what men did and said was dictated by their perception of what was politically possible in a specific but not necessarily stable situation, not by abstract theories of constitutional law. University of Liverpool ROBIN SEAGER