Qualitative and quantitative inference to the best theory. reply to iikka Niiniluoto Kuipers, Theodorus

Similar documents
Scientific Progress, Verisimilitude, and Evidence

DISKURS. De plaats van geloofservaringen binnen de rationele handelingstheorie van Jürgen Habermas Ploeger, A.K.

Citation for published version (APA): Labuschagne, C. J. (2008). 16.Numerical Features of Third Isaiah (56-66). s.n.

Psillos s Defense of Scientific Realism

Logic is the study of the quality of arguments. An argument consists of a set of

Is the Existence of the Best Possible World Logically Impossible?

ON CAUSAL AND CONSTRUCTIVE MODELLING OF BELIEF CHANGE

In essence, Swinburne's argument is as follows:

Ethical Consistency and the Logic of Ought

Philosophy 5340 Epistemology Topic 4: Skepticism. Part 1: The Scope of Skepticism and Two Main Types of Skeptical Argument

BOOK REVIEWS. Duke University. The Philosophical Review, Vol. XCVII, No. 1 (January 1988)

University of Groningen. Dependent leaders Voorn, Bart

Comments on Truth at A World for Modal Propositions

Logic: inductive. Draft: April 29, Logic is the study of the quality of arguments. An argument consists of a set of premises P1,

Klein on the Unity of Cartesian and Contemporary Skepticism

5 A Modal Version of the

THE ROLE OF COHERENCE OF EVIDENCE IN THE NON- DYNAMIC MODEL OF CONFIRMATION TOMOJI SHOGENJI

Kripke on the distinctness of the mind from the body

Realism and instrumentalism

DEFEASIBLE A PRIORI JUSTIFICATION: A REPLY TO THUROW

ROBERT STALNAKER PRESUPPOSITIONS

Informalizing Formal Logic

Does Deduction really rest on a more secure epistemological footing than Induction?

Realism and the success of science argument. Leplin:

Instrumental reasoning* John Broome

Richard L. W. Clarke, Notes REASONING

Reliabilism: Holistic or Simple?

A Model of Decidable Introspective Reasoning with Quantifying-In

Resemblance Nominalism and counterparts

Boghossian & Harman on the analytic theory of the a priori

PHILOSOPHY OF LOGIC AND LANGUAGE OVERVIEW LOGICAL CONSTANTS WEEK 5: MODEL-THEORETIC CONSEQUENCE JONNY MCINTOSH

HANDBOOK (New or substantially modified material appears in boxes.)

Definite Descriptions and the Argument from Inference

THE SEMANTIC REALISM OF STROUD S RESPONSE TO AUSTIN S ARGUMENT AGAINST SCEPTICISM

Logic and Pragmatics: linear logic for inferential practice

Introduction Symbolic Logic

Quantificational logic and empty names

Jeffrey, Richard, Subjective Probability: The Real Thing, Cambridge University Press, 2004, 140 pp, $21.99 (pbk), ISBN

HAVE WE REASON TO DO AS RATIONALITY REQUIRES? A COMMENT ON RAZ

Between the Actual and the Trivial World

Naturalized Epistemology. 1. What is naturalized Epistemology? Quine PY4613

Analogy and Pursuitworthiness

Truth and Evidence in Validity Theory

A Scientific Realism-Based Probabilistic Approach to Popper's Problem of Confirmation

Lecture 3. I argued in the previous lecture for a relationist solution to Frege's puzzle, one which

SIMON BOSTOCK Internal Properties and Property Realism

Necessity. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Pp. i-ix, 379. ISBN $35.00.

Predicate logic. Miguel Palomino Dpto. Sistemas Informáticos y Computación (UCM) Madrid Spain

HANDBOOK (New or substantially modified material appears in boxes.)

Exercise Sets. KS Philosophical Logic: Modality, Conditionals Vagueness. Dirk Kindermann University of Graz July 2014

prohibition, moral commitment and other normative matters. Although often described as a branch

On The Logical Status of Dialectic (*) -Historical Development of the Argument in Japan- Shigeo Nagai Naoki Takato

The Role of Logic in Philosophy of Science

I. Scientific Realism: Introduction

THE MEANING OF OUGHT. Ralph Wedgwood. What does the word ought mean? Strictly speaking, this is an empirical question, about the

Pictures, Proofs, and Mathematical Practice : Reply to James Robert Brown

Mohammad Reza Vaez Shahrestani. University of Bonn

A Review of Neil Feit s Belief about the Self

SAVING RELATIVISM FROM ITS SAVIOUR

From Transcendental Logic to Transcendental Deduction

Detachment, Probability, and Maximum Likelihood

Modal Realism, Counterpart Theory, and Unactualized Possibilities

Philosophy 5340 Epistemology. Topic 6: Theories of Justification: Foundationalism versus Coherentism. Part 2: Susan Haack s Foundherentist Approach

TWO VERSIONS OF HUME S LAW

YFIA205 Basics of Research Methodology in Social Sciences Lecture 1. Science, Knowledge and Theory. Jyväskylä 3.11.

The Problem of Induction and Popper s Deductivism

1/12. The A Paralogisms

Sensitivity hasn t got a Heterogeneity Problem - a Reply to Melchior

The Development of Laws of Formal Logic of Aristotle

Progress as Approximation to the Truth: A Defence of the Verisimilitudinarian Approach

Tuukka Kaidesoja Précis of Naturalizing Critical Realist Social Ontology

Scientific errors should be controlled, not prevented. Daniel Eindhoven University of Technology

IS GOD "SIGNIFICANTLY FREE?''

Phil 1103 Review. Also: Scientific realism vs. anti-realism Can philosophers criticise science?

Van Inwagen's modal argument for incompatibilism

Direct Realism and the Brain-in-a-Vat Argument by Michael Huemer (2000)

Philosophy Epistemology. Topic 3 - Skepticism

The problems of induction in scientific inquiry: Challenges and solutions. Table of Contents 1.0 Introduction Defining induction...

Can A Priori Justified Belief Be Extended Through Deduction? It is often assumed that if one deduces some proposition p from some premises

Leibniz, Principles, and Truth 1

From Necessary Truth to Necessary Existence

Merricks on the existence of human organisms

OSSA Conference Archive OSSA 5

145 Philosophy of Science

Varieties of Apriority

Explanatory Indispensability and Deliberative Indispensability: Against Enoch s Analogy Alex Worsnip University of North Carolina at Chapel Hill

Millian responses to Frege s puzzle

Critical Thinking 5.7 Validity in inductive, conductive, and abductive arguments

Remarks on a Foundationalist Theory of Truth. Anil Gupta University of Pittsburgh

Believing Epistemic Contradictions

Skepticism and Internalism

UC Berkeley, Philosophy 142, Spring 2016

Evaluating Logical Pluralism

Van Fraassen: Arguments Concerning Scientific Realism

University of Groningen. Numerical Features of the Book of Haggai Labuschagne, Casper

SYSTEMATIC RESEARCH IN PHILOSOPHY. Contents

Levi and the Lottery. Olsson, Erik J. Published in: Knowledge and Inquiry: Essays on the Pragmatism of Isaac Levi. Link to publication

Timothy Williamson: Modal Logic as Metaphysics Oxford University Press 2013, 464 pages

Artificial Intelligence I

Critical Scientific Realism

Transcription:

University of Groningen Qualitative and quantitative inference to the best theory. reply to iikka Niiniluoto Kuipers, Theodorus Published in: EPRINTS-BOOK-TITLE IMPORTANT NOTE: You are advised to consult the publisher's version (publisher's PDF) if you wish to cite from it. Please check the document version below. Document Version Publisher's PDF, also known as Version of record Publication date: 2005 Link to publication in University of Groningen/UMCG research database Citation for published version (APA): Kuipers, T. A. F. (2005). Qualitative and quantitative inference to the best theory. reply to iikka Niiniluoto. In EPRINTS-BOOK-TITLE University of Groningen. Copyright Other than for strictly personal use, it is not permitted to download or to forward/distribute the text or part of it without the consent of the author(s) and/or copyright holder(s), unless the work is under an open content license (like Creative Commons). Take-down policy If you believe that this document breaches copyright please contact us providing details, and we will remove access to the work immediately and investigate your claim. Downloaded from the University of Groningen/UMCG research database (Pure): http://www.rug.nl/research/portal. For technical reasons the number of authors shown on this cover page is limited to 10 maximum. Download date: 11-02-2018

Theo A. F. Kuipers QUALITATIVE AND QUANTITATIVE INFERENCE TO THE BEST THEORY REPLY TO ILKKA NIINILUOTO Let me start with quoting from my Foreword to SiS: I like to mention Ilkka Niiniluoto s Critical Scientific Realism (1999) as, as far as I know, the most learned recent exposition of some of the main themes in the philosophy of science in the form of an advanced debate-book, that is, a critical exposition and assessment of the recent literature, including his own major contribution, viz. Truthlikeness of 1987. Despite our major differences regarding the topic of truth approximation, I like to express my affinity to, in particular, his rare type of constructive-critical attitude in the philosophy of science. In the debate between realists and instrumentalists, I share with Niiniluoto a nonessentialist version of realism, taking truth approximation, and hence false theories, seriously. Our first major difference is his emphasis on what I call actual truth approximation, whereas I focus on nomic truth approximation. To be sure, he can deal with both, as far as first order languages are concerned, by adding modal operators for nomic truth approximation. Our second major difference is that I seek to remain qualitative for as long as possible, whereas Niiniluoto does not hesitate to go quantitative, even though that makes arbitrary choices necessary. In this reply I will make some remarks on the first point, but focus on the second. Niiniluoto starts with a clear survey of Peirce s main view on abduction, concluding with the important distinction between singular and theoretical abduction or between individual and rule abduction to use Thagard s (1988) favorite terms or simply between individual and general abduction. Many expositions fail to make this distinction, but it is essential. In SiS (pp.75-6) I write [A]fter an explanation of an individual event by subsumption under a law the really important issue then is to explain this law. In my opinion the core of explanation lies in the explanation of observational laws by subsumption under a theory, in short, theoretical explanation of (observational) laws. After a successful theoretical explanation of a law, we get as an extra bonus a theoretical explanation of the individual events fitting into that law. In: R. Festa, A. Aliseda and J. Peijnenburg (eds.), Confirmation, Empirical Progress, and Truth Approximation (Pozna Studies in the Philosophy of the Sciences and the Humanities, vol. 83), pp. 276-280. Amsterdam/Atlanta, GA: Rodopi, 2005.

Reply to Ilkka Niiniluoto 277 Hence, theoretical or general abduction is the main kind of abduction in scientific research. This is not to say that individual abduction is nowhere important. On the contrary, in application contexts, e.g. when human experts or expert systems perform diagnostic reasoning, using a knowledge base, individual abduction is the primary form of abduction. The Why and When of a Qualitative Approach After surveying the three (probabilistic) ways in which abductive arguments can serve the justification of the relevant hypothesis, with (standard) inference to the best explanation (as true) (IBE) as the most far-reaching one, Niiniluoto turns his attention to IBE s functionality for truth approximation. He appreciates my turn to inference to the best theory (as the closest to the truth) (IBT), in particular for its symmetric character (unlike IBE, not only the premise but also the conclusion of IBT is comparative) and its basis in the Success Theorem, according to which more truthlikeness guarantees being at least as successful. His main objection is that my qualitative notion of more successfulness and more truthlikeness are not frequently applicable. He concludes Section 3 with the correct observation: in many cases there will be no single theory which is better than all the available alternatives, so that a rule like IBT is inapplicable (p. 264). However, instead of forcing the existence of a best theory by going quantitative, as Niiniluoto favors, even when the subject matter gives no plausible distances between the structures (or sentences) to be compared, I am interested in the clues given by my analysis when there is no best theory or, more generally, when two theories are incomparable. In SiS I have been more explicit in this than in ICR: Finally, it is important to stress that the strict [qualitative] strategy does not lead to void or almost void methodological principles. If there is divided success between theories, the Principle of Improvement amounts, more specifically, to the recommendation that we should try to apply the Principle of Dialectics: Aim at a success preserving synthesis of the two RSescaping theories [where RS refers to the Rule of Success, the purely methodological side of IBT]. Similarly, for truth approximation aims: if there is reason to suppose that two theories cannot be ordered in terms of more truthlikeness in the strict sense, the challenge is to construe a theory which is more truthlike than both. In sum, the restricted applicability of strict notions of comparative success and truthlikeness does not exclude the possibility of clear challenges being formulated in cases where they do not apply, on the contrary. (SiS, p. 250). Of course, when the subject matter suggests meaningful distances and probabilities, one may want to go further. Moreover, we should like to have as the quantitative variant of the (backward) Success Theorem, the expected success (ES) principle (ICR, p. 303, p. 310): the expected success increases with increasing closeness to the truth. Using Niiniluoto s plausible concept of

278 Theo A. F. Kuipers estimated truthlikeness as the probabilistic specification of (quantitative) success we get (ICR, p. 314): the expected value of the estimated truthlikeness increases with increasing closeness to the truth. This would justify the quantitative use of IBT, but other (non-) probabilistic specifications of success might be defensible as well. Be that as it may, Niiniluoto focuses on the forward version of a kind of ES principle, his principle (19), according to which estimated truthlikeness increases with being a better approximate explanation, which, assuming a quantitative specification of the latter, amounts to: estimated truthlikeness increases with increasing success. To be sure, this sounds like a justification of the quantitative use of IBT, but it has a circular feature: success and estimated truthlikeness are based on the same evidence. Hence, for a genuine justification of such a use of IBT what we would need, besides meaningful distances and probabilities, is an additional link between estimated truthlikeness and true or objective truthlikeness, that is, something like the ES principle. Monadic First-Order Languages In Section 5 Niiniluoto compares several qualitative and quantitative principles in the special case of a (non-modal) monadic first-order language. Whereas I have to concede that the Clifford distance measure (roughly, counting the number of elementary differences) is rather arbitrary in this case and that inductive probabilities have no objective basis, I would also like to remark, in contrast to what Niiniluoto seems to think, that non-modal monadic constituents are directly interesting from the nomic perspective, for they allow straightforward nomic illustrations. For example, theories classifying chemical elements, such as the periodic table, may not only be read as claims about actually existing elements, but also, or even preferably, as claims of nomically possible existing elements, whether or not they have already been produced by nature or artificially. Hence, although a modal formalization is certainly possible, this is not necessary in this case. Let me summarize the main results claimed by Niiniluoto. By (21) he specifies the Success Theorem for constituent-theories (and later informally for arbitrary theories and, in a restricted form, for theories with theoretical terms) and adds that only very few false constituents are comparable in my qualitative, settheoretic way. However, apart from the general relativization of incomparability given above, the question is: what is very few in this context? Given a certain constituent, and hence a certain symmetric difference relative to the true constituent, the number of constituents closer to the truth, and hence, the number of possible qualitative improvements, is equal to the number of subsets of that symmetric difference. Hence, in absolute terms, this number may be very high.

Reply to Ilkka Niiniluoto 279 The same holds for the number of possible worsenings. To be sure, relative to the number of qualitatively incomparable changes, both numbers are small, as a rule. Niiniluoto concedes that (22), that is, his favorite quantitative, generalized, version of the success theorem (21) is invalid. This is so because the antecedence of (22) allows evidence in which relatively many of the correct Q-predicates of a less truthlike constituent are instantiated. Later Niiniluoto argues that the generalization of (22) to arbitrary theories and to theories with theoretical terms is invalid for similar reasons. In sum, the lesson is that the success theorem (21) is only valid for the qualitative case, which is only applicable in relatively few cases. More generally, I think that expecting (21) to be valid in any deterministic quantitative sense, however restricted, is too much. It seems more plausible to think in terms of the (probabilistic) ES principle mentioned above, and I am puzzled why Niiniluoto does not pay attention to it. In correspondence Niiniluoto refers to a theorem in this direction in (Niiniluoto 1984, (12), p. 92 and (16), p. 170) in terms of true and fully informative (or non-misleading ) evidence. However, this is still of a very limited kind, for the theorem s condition amounts to the claim that the constituent corresponding to the evidence is the true one. The theorem says that under that condition the estimated truthlikeness of that constituent, that is, the true one, approaches the maximum value. The remaining challenge is to generalize this result to the comparative case: increasing closeness to the truth should lead to an increasing expected value of the estimated truthlikeness. Turning to the upward (or forward ) problem of abduction, and using Hintikka s system of inductive probabilities, Niiniluoto specifies (19) (estimated truthlikeness increases with increasing success) by (23) for monadic constituents and argues that a similar specification can be given of the non-symmetric variant of (19), viz. (20), and plausibly claims that both can be generalized to arbitrary theories and theories with theoretical terms. Since all these claims presuppose a context, such as a monadic first-order language, in which all relevant theories are available, including the true one, this is not yet realistic. For this reason, Niiniluoto finally surveys three different ways of dealing with theories sharing a false idealizing presupposition as developed in his (1987). Here only the first one may have a qualitative counterpart. More specifically, it would be interesting to investigate its relation to my treatment of truth approximation by concretization, based on refined qualitative truthlikeness, in ICR (pp. 268-71), including Niiniluoto s interesting suggestion of modifying. the basic idea of the Converse Consequence principle, according to which confirmation of a concretization of an idealized assumption entails (some kind of) confirmation of that assumption.

280 Theo A. F. Kuipers REFERENCES Niiniluoto, I. (1984), Is Science Progressive? Dordrecht: Reidel. Niiniluoto, I. (1987). Truthlikeness. Dordrecht: Reidel. Niiniluoto, I. (1999). Critical Scientific Realism. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Thagard, P. (1988) Computational Philosophy of Science. Cambridge MA: The MIT Press.