Response to Brian R. Clack. Accepted Author Manuscript. Sophia 54 (3): (2015), DOI: /s

Similar documents
WITTGENSTEIN, FRAZER AND RELIGION

General Editor: D.Z. Phillips, Professor of Philosophy, University College of Swansea

xiv Truth Without Objectivity

Swansea Studies in Philosophy

SEMESTER AT SEA COURSE SYLLABUS

사회학영문강독 제 12 강. 전광희교수

Review: The Objects of Thought, by Tim Crane. Guy Longworth University of Warwick

Twentieth-Century Analytic Philosophy by Avrum Stroll

Nature of Religion. Week 1: Why is defining religion a hopeless business, and why do we still have to carry on with it?

Wittgenstein and Buddhism

Violence and Social Justice

Explorations in Post-Secular Metaphysics

Critical Thinking: Present, Past and Future 5 April, 2015

Suggested Activities. revolution and evolution. criteria for revolutionary change. intellectual climate of the Middle Ages

PHILOSOPHY OF RELIGION A-Z

A History of Western Thought Why We Think the Way We Do. Summer 2016 Ross Arnold

Slavoj Žižek and Dialectical Materialism

Each copy of any part of a JSTOR transmission must contain the same copyright notice that appears on the screen or printed page of such transmission.

Access provided by National Taiwan University (10 Aug :00 GMT)

Lectures on S tmcture and Significance of Science

Mark Coeckelbergh: Growing Moral Relations. Critique of Moral Status Ascription

QUERIES: to be answered by AUTHOR

Citation Philosophy and Psychology (2009): 1.

Jeffrey, Richard, Subjective Probability: The Real Thing, Cambridge University Press, 2004, 140 pp, $21.99 (pbk), ISBN

Reason and Explanation: A Defense of Explanatory Coherentism. BY TED POSTON (Basingstoke,

Verificationism. PHIL September 27, 2011

H U M a N I M A L I A 3:1

Shanghai Jiao Tong University. PI900 Introduction to Western Philosophy

Marxism and the Leninist Revolutionary Model

The Advancement: A Book Review

Wittgenstein on forms of life: a short introduction

EUROPEAN POLITICAL THEORY: ROUSSEAU AND AFTER

Religion 101. Tools and Methods in the Study of Religion. Term: Spring 2015 Professor Babak Rahimi. Section ID: Location: Room: PCYNH 120

COURSES THOUGHT IN ENGLISH FALL TERM 2012

Intelligent Design. Kevin delaplante Dept. of Philosophy & Religious Studies

Philosophy 305 Introduction to Philosophy of Religion Fall 2016 (also listed as CTI 310, RS 305) 42270; 33770; WAG 302 MWF 2-3

McCLOSKEY ON RATIONAL ENDS: The Dilemma of Intuitionism

This page intentionally left blank

What the History of Science Cannot Teach Us Ioannis Votsis University of Bristol

Ayer on the criterion of verifiability

Death and Immortality (by D Z Phillips) Introductory Remarks

Evil and International Relations

Heidegger s Interpretation of Kant

Bridging Faith and Knowledge. through Wittgenstein s On Certainty

Intimacy, Transcendence, and Psychology

CLASSICAL SOCIOLOGICAL THEORY Sociology 475

Journal of Philosophy: A Cross-Disciplinary Inquiry, Winter 2011, Vol. 6, No. 14

THE MORAL FIXED POINTS: REPLY TO CUNEO AND SHAFER-LANDAU

RECOVERING RELIGIOUS CONCEPTS

Could There Have Been Nothing?

AUTHOR: Steven M. Cahn TITLE: Reason and Religions: Philosophy Looks at the World s Religious Beliefs

Literature, Philosophy, Nihilism

Human Nature & Human Diversity: Sex, Love & Parenting; Morality, Religion & Race. Course Description

A solution to the problem of hijacked experience

Reading and Writing Scripture in New Religious Movements

Honours Programme in Philosophy

Junior Seminar Syllabus REL3931, Sec 0207 Fall 2011 Course Description: Course Objectives:

Difficult Cases and the Epistemic Justification of Moral Belief Joshua Schechter (Brown University)

New Studies in the Philosophy of Religion

Why Counterpart Theory and Three-Dimensionalism are Incompatible. Suppose that God creates ex nihilo a bronze statue of a

III Knowledge is true belief based on argument. Plato, Theaetetus, 201 c-d Is Justified True Belief Knowledge? Edmund Gettier

Comments on Scott Soames, Philosophical Analysis in the Twentieth Century, volume I

An Introduction To Medieval Jewish Philosophy (International Library Of Historical Studies) [Paperback] By Daniel Rynhold

Metaphysical atomism and the attraction of materialism.

RELIGION DEPARTMENT FALL2008 COURSEOFFERINGS

Kevin Scharp, Replacing Truth, Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2013, At 300-some pages, with narrow margins and small print, the work

Course Website: Course materials and assignments are on D2L.

This page intentionally left blank

INTUITION AND CONSCIOUS REASONING

Are You A Religious Naturalist Without Knowing It? We humans are narrative beings. We are storytellers. Communication between beings

Templeton Fellowships at the NDIAS

PLEASESURE, DESIRE AND OPPOSITENESS

Annotated List of Ethical Theories

Theology and Marxism in Eagleton and Žižek

Ethics. PHIL 181 Spring 2018 SUMMARY OBJECTIVES

The New Wittgenstein, ed. Alice Crary and Rupert Read, London and New York, 2000, pp. v + 403, no price.

Kant s Practical Philosophy

Evolution and the Possibility of Moral Realism

Also by Nafsika Athanassoulis. Also by Samantha Vice

FLORIDA INTERNATIONAL UNIVERSITY Department of Religious Studies Capstone Seminar: Theories and Methods in Religious Studies REL 4030 Spring 2013

Pihlström, Sami Johannes.

Published by Palgrave Macmillan

3. Why is the RE Core syllabus Christian in content?

CHAPTER ONE What is Philosophy? What s In It For Me?

SOUTH AFRICAN ELITES AND CHRISTIAN ETmcs - PERSONAL ETmcs

Descartes: A Guide for the Perplexed

NOT SO PROMISING AFTER ALL: EVALUATOR-RELATIVE TELEOLOGY AND COMMON-SENSE MORALITY

Alternative Conceptual Schemes and a Non-Kantian Scheme-Content Dualism

TWO VERSIONS OF HUME S LAW

NON-COGNITIVISM AND THE PROBLEM OF MORAL-BASED EPISTEMIC REASONS: A SYMPATHETIC REPLY TO CIAN DORR

REASONS-RESPONSIVENESS AND TIME TRAVEL

JASMIN HASSEL University of Münster

QCAA Study of Religion 2019 v1.1 General Senior Syllabus

"",hi'" . -= ::-~,~-:::=- ...,.,.. ::;- -.--

Philosophical approaches to animal ethics

Academic argument does not mean conflict or competition; an argument is a set of reasons which support, or lead to, a conclusion.

Existentialism Philosophy 303 (CRN 12245) Fall 2013

Wittgenstein and the End of Philosophy

New Studies in the Philosophy of Religion. General Editor: W. D. Hudson, Reader In Moral Philosophy, University ofexeter

Locke s and Hume s Theories of Personhood: Similarities and Differences. In this paper I will deal with the theories of personhood formulated by

Transcription:

!1 Response to Brian R. Clack Accepted Author Manuscript Sophia 54 (3):381-383 (2015), DOI: 10.1007/s11841-015-0488-7 http://link.springer.com/article/10.1007/s11841-015-0488-7 Thomas D. Carroll Xing Wei College thomasdcarroll@gmail.com Brian Clack makes a number of criticisms of Wittgenstein within the Philosophy of Religion in his review for this journal. I would like to respond to two of these criticisms in order to address potential misunderstandings about what the book argues. I am grateful to the editor of this journal for the opportunity to respond in this fashion to the review. The first criticism concerns a sentence of mine that mentions Oswald Spengler on the history of cultures. The sentence in question reads: "Oswald Spengler, a thinker who influenced Wittgenstein s view of the history of cultures, espoused something of an evolutionary view of the history of cultures, and such a view was defended by thinkers now recognized as among the most influential theorists in the development of the academic study of religions (for example, Herbert Spencer, and E. B. Tylor). (Carroll, 16, qtd. on Clack, 108). Clack argues that in this sentence [s]omething has gone badly wrong because Spengler s conception of history as recurrent forms as the drama of a number of rising and declining cultures stands in radical opposition to the conception of one linear history embraced by Tylor and Frazer, and it is Wittgenstein s albeit qualified acceptance of Spengler that underlies some of his antipathy toward The Golden

!2 Bough. (Clack, 108) I agree that something would have gone badly wrong if the sentence in question conveyed what I take it Clack is concerned that it might: a conflation of the views of Spengler, Tylor, and Frazer; however, stating that Spengler's view of the history of cultures stands in radical opposition to the conception of one linear history embraces by Tylor and Frazer is not incompatible with the claim that the views of all three may be described in terms of evolution. Not all appeals to evolution in describing cultural change over time are the same (i.e. postulate one linear history ). I reject the view that use of the word evolution must entail one linear history; this may help illuminate another line from the book: Not that evolution would insure greater sophistication or value (say, as teleological versions of the evolution of culture and religion would have it). (Carroll, 16) In writing that Spengler espoused something of an evolutionary view of the history of cultures, I meant that there are a variety of possible views of the history of cultures that could be described as evolutionary (i.e. that employ the word evolution or its variants, or closely related ideas, in describing cultural change over time). Yet, the book does not provide support for my claim and I see now that a thorough genealogy of evolution (with respect to culture) is required to support what may otherwise appear to be a counter-intuitive claim about Spengler. The second criticism is that the final chapter reflects an enormous loss of confidence in comparison with the aims of the book. Clack writes, There is much that could be said here that might be new how Wittgenstein connects to Spengler, or to Freud and psychoanalysis but instead we find here discussions of D. Z. Phillips contemplative philosophy of religion and of the need for clarity and perspicuity in thinking about religious phenomena. None of that is

!3 especially new. (Clack, 108) The aim of the final chapter of the book is to explore entailments of the ethic of perspicuity reading of Wittgenstein for the philosophy of religion (i.e. to explore ethical considerations in doing philosophy of religion). Clarity about religious phenomena, however important, is only one entailment of the ethic of perspicuity for the philosophy of religion, and I agree that calling for this is nothing new. In this regard, John Clayton's work, which I discuss in the chapter, is particularly relevant. Aside from (1) being perspicuous about religious phenomena, other entailments of the ethic of perspicuity for philosophy of religion include: (2) being scrupulous in considering received interpretations of figures or movements in the history of philosophy of religion (including the concepts that are used in forming those received interpretations, such as fideism or religion/religious ); (3) being attentive to religions, in their diversities, as they are actually practiced; (4) being responsive to instances of confusion about religions one may encounter (e.g. in one's classroom, community, or scholarship); and (5) being aware of the situatedness of one's own philosophical activity (e.g. within a time, place, culture, language, community, institution, and so on). The entailments identified in the final chapter are not just statements of what a perspicuous philosophy of religion could do; they are a distillation of what has been performed in the previous chapters of the book interpreting Wittgenstein and the history of Wittgenstein s reception within the philosophy of religion. On the basis of these entailments, I argue that Wittgenstein s ethic of perspicuity is well-suited to the circumstances that some philosophers of religion may find themselves facing today (including, in particular, the book s author): a crowded, religiously and secularly diverse world that students may otherwise have difficulty understanding and negotiating their ways through. In this regard, I would certainly agree in word, if not in spirit, with H. H. Price in saying that clarity [about

!4 religious phenomena] is not enough. (Price, 1) Clack is certainly right that the book would benefit from a greater variety of voices, and this is all the more true in connection with the topic of perspicuous representations (something to which scholarship on Freud, Spengler, and Wittgenstein s writings on the two is relevant). I am thankful for Clack s criticisms and provocations and hope that future research will make good on the remarks I present here.

!5 References Carroll, T. D. 2014. Wittgenstein within the Philosophy of Religion. Basingstoke, Hampshire: Palgrave Macmillan. Clack, B. R. 2015. Review of Thomas D. Carroll, Wittgenstein within the Philosophy of Religion, Sophia, 54/1, pp. 107-09. Price, H. H. 1945. Clarity is Not Enough, Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, 19, 1 31.