The Richness of Things Themselves

Similar documents
The Theory of Reality: A Critical & Philosophical Elaboration

MY PURPOSE IN THIS BOOK IS TO PRESENT A

A Major Matter: Minoring in Philosophy. Southeastern Louisiana University. The unexamined life is not worth living. Socrates, B.C.E.

The Greatest Mistake: A Case for the Failure of Hegel s Idealism

Kant and the Problem of Metaphysics 1. By Tom Cumming

Development of Soul Through Contemplation and Action Seen from the Viewpoint of lslamic Philosophers and Gnostics

Aspects of Western Philosophy Dr. Sreekumar Nellickappilly Department of Humanities and Social Sciences Indian Institute of Technology, Madras

Robert Kiely Office Hours: Monday 4:15 6:00; Wednesday 1-3; Thursday 2-3

MODELS CLARIFIED: RESPONDING TO LANGDON GILKEY. by David E. Klemm and William H. Klink

Qué es la filosofía? What is philosophy? Philosophy

A History of Western Thought Why We Think the Way We Do. Summer 2016 Ross Arnold

Book Review: Prince of Networks: Bruno Latour and Metaphysics By Graham Harman

24.01 Classics of Western Philosophy

Philosophy Courses-1

Philosophy in Review XXXIII (2013), no. 5

Chapter Summaries: Introduction to Christian Philosophy by Clark, Chapter 1

BENJAMIN R. BARBER. Radical Excess & Post-Modernism Presentation By Benedetta Barnabo Cachola

Philosophy Courses-1

William Meehan Essay on Spinoza s psychology.

PHILOSOPHICAL RAMIFICATIONS: THEORY, EXPERIMENT, & EMPIRICAL TRUTH

DEPARTMENT OF PHILOSOPHY UNIVERSITY OF CALIFORNIA, RIVERSIDE. Graduate course and seminars for Fall Quarter

WHAT IS HUME S FORK? Certainty does not exist in science.

Course Text. Course Description. Course Objectives. StraighterLine Introduction to Philosophy

Has Logical Positivism Eliminated Metaphysics?

EXAM PREP (Semester 2: 2018) Jules Khomo. Linguistic analysis is concerned with the following question:

The Supplement of Copula

Ibuanyidanda (Complementary Reflection), African Philosophy and General Issues in Philosophy

1/12. The A Paralogisms

FIRST STUDY. The Existential Dialectical Basic Assumption of Kierkegaard s Analysis of Despair

The Middle Path: A Case for the Philosophical Theologian. Leo Strauss roots the vitality of Western civilization in the ongoing conflict between

A BEGINNER'S GUIDE TO PHILOSOPHY BY DOMINIQUE JANICAUD DOWNLOAD EBOOK : A BEGINNER'S GUIDE TO PHILOSOPHY BY DOMINIQUE JANICAUD PDF

Ontological Justification: From Appearance to Reality Anna-Sofia Maurin (PhD 2002)

Reading Questions for Phil , Fall 2016 (Daniel)

Thought is Being or Thought and Being? Feuerbach and his Criticism of Hegel's Absolute Idealism by Martin Jenkins

Templeton Fellowships at the NDIAS

Response to The Problem of the Question About Animal Ethics by Michal Piekarski

Journal Of Contemporary Trends In Business And Information Technology (JCTBIT) Vol.5, pp.1-6, December Existentialist s Model of Professionalism

Philosophy Catalog. REQUIREMENTS FOR A MAJOR IN PHILOSOPHY: 9 courses (36 credits)

Philosophy 125 Day 13: Overview

Lonergan on General Transcendent Knowledge. In General Transcendent Knowledge, Chapter 19 of Insight, Lonergan does several things:

CONSTRUCTIVE ENGAGEMENT DIALOGUE SEARLE AND BUDDHISM ON THE NON-SELF SORAJ HONGLADAROM

A History of Western Thought Why We Think the Way We Do. Summer 2016 Ross Arnold

Rule-Following and the Ontology of the Mind Abstract The problem of rule-following

THE STUDY OF UNKNOWN AND UNKNOWABILITY IN KANT S PHILOSOPHY

DEPARTMENT OF PHILOSOPHY FALL 2013 COURSE DESCRIPTIONS

Philosophy 203 History of Modern Western Philosophy. Russell Marcus Hamilton College Spring 2014

An Interview with Alain Badiou Universal Truths and the Question of Religion Adam S. Miller Journal of Philosophy and Scripture

Stengers on Whitehead: A Short Introduction to the Bifurcation of Nature. Adam Robbert

Why I Am Not a Property Dualist By John R. Searle

The Leibniz Review, Vol. 11,

Kant and his Successors

POLI 343 Introduction to Political Research

Immanuel Kant, Analytic and Synthetic. Prolegomena to Any Future Metaphysics Preface and Preamble

Process Thought and Bridge Building: A Response to Stephen K. White. Kevin Schilbrack

In Defense of Pure Reason: A Rationalist Account of A Priori Justification, by Laurence BonJour. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press,

Rationalism. A. He, like others at the time, was obsessed with questions of truth and doubt

The CopernicanRevolution

Philosophy Epistemology Topic 5 The Justification of Induction 1. Hume s Skeptical Challenge to Induction

Review of The Monk and the Philosopher

The Ontological Argument for the existence of God. Pedro M. Guimarães Ferreira S.J. PUC-Rio Boston College, July 13th. 2011

V3301 Twentieth-Century Philosophy PHIL V TR 2:40pm-3:55pm- 516 Hamilton Hall - Fall Professor D. Sidorsky

Ayer s linguistic theory of the a priori

INTRODUCTION TO THINKING AT THE EDGE. By Eugene T. Gendlin, Ph.D.

Moral Objectivism. RUSSELL CORNETT University of Calgary

PHILOSOPHY AND THE SOCIAL SCIENCES

Intro. The need for a philosophical vocabulary

Introduction to Deductive and Inductive Thinking 2017

Jeu-Jenq Yuann Professor of Philosophy Department of Philosophy, National Taiwan University,

Reflections on sociology's unspoken weakness: Bringing epistemology back in

Under contract with Oxford University Press Karen Bennett Cornell University

Discussion of McCool, From Unity to Pluralism

In Epistemic Relativism, Mark Kalderon defends a view that has become

Introduction to SUNY Series in Constructive Postmodern Thought 1

PHILOSOPHY (PHIL) Philosophy (PHIL) 1

Moral Argumentation from a Rhetorical Point of View

Phil 3121: Modern Philosophy Fall 2016 T, Th 3:40 5:20 pm

Think by Simon Blackburn. Chapter 4b Free Will/Self

The Philosophical Review, Vol. 110, No. 3. (Jul., 2001), pp

Some Notes Toward a Genealogy of Existential Philosophy Robert Burch

Aspects of Western Philosophy Dr. Sreekumar Nellickappilly Department of Humanities and Social Sciences Indian Institute of Technology, Madras

Philip D. Miller Denison University I

Teachur Philosophy Degree 2018

Book Review: From Plato to Jesus By C. Marvin Pate. Submitted by: Brian A. Schulz. A paper. submitted in partial fulfillment

PHILOSOPHY 4360/5360 METAPHYSICS. Methods that Metaphysicians Use

1/8. Reid on Common Sense

Anaphoric Deflationism: Truth and Reference

DOMINICAN UNIVERSITY COLLEGE

The British Empiricism

New people and a new type of communication Lyudmila A. Markova, Russian Academy of Sciences

Meaning of the Paradox

The title of this collection of essays is a question that I expect many professional philosophers have

MEANING AND TRUTH IN THEOLOGY

BOOK REVIEWS. The arguments of the Parmenides, though they do not refute the Theory of Forms, do expose certain problems, ambiguities and

3 Supplement. Robert Bernasconi

A History of Western Thought Why We Think the Way We Do. Summer 2016 Ross Arnold

TEILHARD DE CHARDIN, A. N. WHITEHEAD AND A METAPHYSICS OF INTERSUBJECTIVITY

Neo-Confucianism: Metaphysics, Mind, and Morality

Saving the Substratum: Interpreting Kant s First Analogy

T.M. Luhrmann. When God Talks Back: Understanding the American Evangelical Relationship

- We might, now, wonder whether the resulting concept of justification is sufficiently strong. According to BonJour, apparent rational insight is

Transcription:

The Richness of Things Themselves Steven Shaviro Criticism, Volume 52, Number 1, Winter 2010, pp. 129-133 (Article) Published by Wayne State University Press For additional information about this article http://muse.jhu.edu/journals/crt/summary/v052/52.1.shaviro.html Access Provided by Wayne State University at 01/15/11 9:14PM GMT

The Richness of Things Themselves Steven Shaviro Prince of Networks: Bruno Latour and Metaphysics by Graham Harman. Anamnesis series. Melbourne, Australia: re.press, 2009. Pp. 258. $25.00 paper. Graham Harman s Prince of Networks is really two books in one. The first part is a lucid exposition of the metaphysics of Bruno Latour; the second part presents Harman s own metaphysical speculations, which are deeply indebted to those of Latour, but which also strike out in new and different directions. Bruno Latour is well known in the United States, but he is not usually thought of as a philosopher or a metaphysician. Latour is, rather, most familiar as one of the leading figures in science studies: the interdisciplinary field that looks at the actual practices of scientists and scientific institutions, and the cultural implications of these practices. Science studies involves the work of sociologists, anthropologists, and historians, as well as of cultural theorists and rhetoricians, who are often to be found in literature departments. Latour is also frequently cited as one of the developers of actor-network theory, which has had a significant impact in the social sciences and in cultural studies but which has little in common with the concerns of the philosophy of science as it was practiced in the last century under the influence of such figures as Karl Popper and Thomas Kuhn. It s surprising, therefore (at least for English-language readers, though not necessarily for Frenchlanguage ones) to see Latour presented, as he is by Harman, as a Criticism, Winter 2010, Vol. 52, No. 1, pp. 129 133. ISSN: 0011-1589. 129 2010 Wayne State University Press, Detroit, MI 48201-1309.

130 STeven Shaviro metaphysician, in the company of such figures as Leibniz, Hume, Kant, and Whitehead. Indeed, Harman suggests that Latour compares favorably with such figures as Derrida, Foucault, Deleuze, Lacan, and Badiou, those theorists who have entranced American academia over the last several decades. One of the great merits of Prince of Networks is that it not only argues for the importance of Latour s thought, but also places Latour himself in an entirely new light. In the first part of Prince of Networks, Harman outlines Latour s metaphysics through a close reading of four of Latour s texts: Irreductions (from The Pasteurization of France, 1984), Science in Action (1987), We Have Never Been Modern (1991), and Pandora s Hope (1999). Harman discovers a cluster of four metaphysical axioms that define Latour s philosophy (14 16). In the first place, the world is made up of actors or actants, discrete and separate individuals. Human beings are actors, but so are bacteria, chairs, grapes, and grains of sand. In the second place, all these actors are irreducible. No actor can be entirely explained in the terms of, or by reference to, another. You cannot fully account for the being and doing of a chair, for instance, by referring either to the atoms out of which it is ultimately made or to its use by the person who sits in it. In the third place, any encounter, any interaction between actors, involves a process of translation. Each actor mediates (and thereby transforms) other actors and is in its own turn mediated (and thereby transformed) by still other actors: There is never an immediate visibility of the fact, but only a series of mediations.... Truth is nothing but a chain of translation without resemblance from one actor to the next (76). And finally, in the fourth place, change happens as a result of negotiations or battles among actors; and the outcome of these negotiations or battles depends upon the alliances that actors are able to make with one another: For Latour, an object is neither a substance nor an essence, but an actor trying to adjust or inflict its forces, not unlike Nietzsche s cosmic vision of the will to power (15). After stating these axioms concisely, Harman proceeds to elaborate and develop them, and to explore their ramifications and consequences. The result is to reveal that Latour is actually grappling with many of the major concerns of Western philosophy and offering his own innovative suggestions for resolving them. In the second part of Prince of Networks, Harman steps back from this close reading, in order to offer some criticisms of Latour s metaphysics and to propose his own metaphysical speculations as an alternative. Above all, Harman criticizes Latour for his relationalism: his notion that actors are defined entirely by their relations and alli-

on harman s Prince of networks 131 ances. For Latour, actors must be fully relational in character, with no distinction between object and accident, object and relation, or object and quality... to change one s relations is to change one s reality (104). Harman objects that this dimension of Latour s thought (which he shares with Whitehead) risks dissolving actors into a sort of primordial indistinction and effacing their concrete individuality. Radical relationalism makes it difficult to understand how an actor can change over time. It also risks undermining the very actuality of actors that Latour otherwise wishes to affirm, by not allowing [an actor] to be real outside the alliances that articulate it (129). Harman therefore suggests that contrary to Latour s specific assertions, but in tune with his basic intuitions actors must be accorded a reality beyond all relationality ; each actor (or object) must be in and of itself actual apart from any relations (187). Latour s own insistence upon the actuality and efficacy of actors, nonhuman as well as human, implies that each of these actors is necessarily self-contained (144). Harman s own philosophy elaborates upon, and expands, this basic insight. In the second part of Prince of Networks, Harman further develops, with the help of Latour, ideas that he had earlier formulated in his previous books, Tool-Being (2002) and Guerrilla Metaphysics (2005). Among other things, Harman remarkably revives, and gives new life to, two old philosophical doctrines that, for most of the last century, have been regarded as old-fashioned, when not forgotten entirely. The first of these doctrines is substantialism: the claim that every object is a substance, which is to say that it is something more than the mere sum of its qualities. The second of these forgotten doctrines is occasionalism: the claim that objects cannot influence one another directly as in conventional notions of cause and effect but require some external mediation in order to do so. Harman suggests that substantialism is the missing term that could resolve many of the problems that remain in Latour s metaphysics. And he credits Latour with the prodigious discovery, for the first time in the history of philosophy, of a secular occasionalism: a thought that considers seriously the problem of mediation in any relationship among entities without falling back upon God as the ultimate mediator (102, 115, 228). Ever since Descartes, Western philosophy has called upon God as the ultimate guarantor of the world s coherence; Latour is the first thinker to envision this coherence in entirely immanent and secular terms. What unites both parts of Prince of Networks is Harman s quest, following Latour, to develop what he calls an object-oriented philosophy. This is a view of the world

132 STeven Shaviro that in contrast to nearly all Western philosophy since Kant, or indeed since Descartes is not centered upon questions of consciousness, subjectivity, and the epistemological problem of human access to an external world. Rather, object-oriented philosophy affirms a marvelous plurality of concrete objects (156), each with its own integrity and its own mysterious depths. The universe of things is not a harmonious whole, but a wild anarchy of innumerable objects both withdrawing from and reaching out to one another. And these objects cannot be contained within the fixed categories that we would seek to impose upon them. Object-oriented philosophy is therefore equally opposed to scientific naturalism and to so-called social constructionism. Against the former, it insists that no object is reducible to, or fully explicable in terms of, its ultimate subatomic constituents. Against the latter, it insists that the world is not made by us and for us. Cats, brown dwarf stars, internal combustion engines, and lava flows all have their own stubborn autonomy and inherent activity. Latour has often been viewed, in the United States at least, as a social constructionist, but Harman demonstrates convincingly that this characterization is wrong. Far from reducing the physical world to a human projection, Latour s philosophy orients us, as never before, toward the richness of things themselves in all their multifariousness (119). Prince of Networks marks something of a turning point, I think, in contemporary intellectual discourse. For Harman s reconstruction of Latour s metaphysics, and his presentation of his own metaphysics, both exemplify an important development in recent years: the revival of metaphysical speculation. For most of the twentieth century, metaphysics was taboo, or under quarantine. It was generally seen as something bad, something we had to get away from. The goal of overcoming metaphysics was shared by thinkers as otherwise antagonistic to one another as Carnap and Heidegger. And despite the vast differences among them, Wittgenstein, Rorty, and Derrida were united at least by their incessant efforts to undo the bewitchment of metaphysics, even if they all conceded that we would never be able to escape this bewitchment entirely. But it seems that this sort of attitude might finally be giving way. In the twentyfirst century, it might be possible, once again, to do metaphysics without a bad conscience. Harman suggests as much, both through his own bold speculations and through what might be thought of as his outing of Latour as an unabashed metaphysician. The case of Latour is especially significant in this respect because it demonstrates that full-fledged metaphysical specula-

on harman s Prince of networks 133 tion is not incompatible with the most careful, and hardheadedly empirical, examination of local, particular facts in minute detail. Metaphysics, no less than scientific examination, is a way of embracing the richness of things themselves. It is high time for us to have done with the asceticism and superciliousness of the last century s intellectual climate. Metaphysical speculation, at its best, is a stimulus to thought; Prince of Networks is profoundly engaging and challenging even if one does not accept (as I do not) all of its arguments. In concluding, I should mention that Prince of Networks is not just intellectually stimulating, but also a delight to read. Philosophy has never been a matter of mere logical propositions. It has always involved the elucidation of a basic stance towards the world, which means that it has always also involved a kind of literary style. A manner of writing is not just an adornment to the underlying ideas; it is rather the case that ideas themselves can emerge only when they are given the proper form of expression. Even the philosophers who are most painful and obnoxious to read one might mention Kant, Hegel, and (for me at least) Heidegger have written the way they did because they realized that a new sort of language was required in order to convey their new insights about reality. This is all the more so, in the case of thinkers who can also be credited as great writers: think of Plato, Hume, Nietzsche, and William James. Graham Harman is, similarly, a philosopher who writes well. His prose style is as seductive as his ideas, and indeed it is impossible to separate the two. Prince of Networks is a great adventure of ideas (to use a phrase from Alfred North Whitehead); it is one of those rare books that, in style as in substance, truly invites us to think. Steven Shaviro is the DeRoy Professor of English at Wayne State University. He is the author of Connected, or What It Means to Live in the Network Society (University of Minnesota Press, 2003), Without Criteria: Kant, Whitehead, Deleuze, and Aesthetics (MIT Press, 2009), and Post-Cinematic Affect (forthcoming).