philippine studies Ateneo de Manila University Loyola Heights, Quezon City 1108 Philippines Philippine Studies vol. 13, no.

Similar documents
Universal Features: Doubts, Questions, Residual Problems DM VI 7

by Br. Dunstan Robidoux OSB

Essays in Systematic Theology 45: The Structure of Systematic Theology 1

QUESTION 87. How Our Intellect Has Cognition of Itself and of What Exists Within It

REVIEW. St. Thomas Aquinas. By RALPH MCINERNY. The University of Notre Dame Press 1982 (reprint of Twayne Publishers 1977). Pp $5.95.

PHILOSOPHY OF NATURE LET THOMAS AQUINAS TEACH IT. Joseph Kenny, O.P. St. Thomas Aquinas Priory Ibadan, Nigeria

QUESTION 34. The Goodness and Badness of Pleasures

philippine studies Ateneo de Manila University Loyola Heights, Quezon City 1108 Philippines

Lonergan on General Transcendent Knowledge. In General Transcendent Knowledge, Chapter 19 of Insight, Lonergan does several things:

QUESTION 44. The Procession of Creatures from God, and the First Cause of All Beings

general development of both renaissance and post renaissance philosophy up till today. It would

William Hasker s discussion of the Thomistic doctrine of the soul

270 Now that we have settled these issues, we should answer the first question [n.

Questions on Book III of the De anima 1

PART TWO EXISTENCE AND THE EXISTENT. D. The Existent

QUESTION 65. The Work of Creating Corporeal Creatures

Anthony P. Andres. The Place of Conversion in Aristotelian Logic. Anthony P. Andres

QUESTION 28. The Divine Relations

QUESTION 90. The Initial Production of Man with respect to His Soul

The Greatest Mistake: A Case for the Failure of Hegel s Idealism

QUESTION 55. The Medium of Angelic Cognition

QUESTION 34. The Person of the Son: The Name Word

QUESTION 26. Love. Article 1. Does love exist in the concupiscible power?

WHAT ARISTOTLE TAUGHT

QUESTION 56. An Angel s Cognition of Immaterial Things

THE RELATIONSHIP BETWEEN SCIENCE, RELIGION AND ARISTOTELIAN THEOLOGY TODAY

philippine studies Ateneo de Manila University Loyola Heights, Quezon City 1108 Philippines Philippine Studies vol. 19, no.

Henry of Ghent on Divine Illumination

Duns Scotus on Divine Illumination

Knowledge according to Bavinck and Aquinas

The Trinity, The Dogma, The Contradictions Part 2

QUESTION 11. Enjoying as an Act of the Will

Essays in Systematic Theology 17: Shorter Version of System Seeking Method: Reconciling System and History

Francisco Suárez, S. J. DE SCIENTIA DEI FUTURORUM CONTINGENTIUM 1.8 1

Wisdom in Aristotle and Aquinas From Metaphysics to Mysticism Edmond Eh University of Saint Joseph, Macau

God and Creation, Job 38:1-15

QUESTION 59. An Angel s Will

Peter L.P. Simpson January, 2015

Vol 2 Bk 7 Outline p 486 BOOK VII. Substance, Essence and Definition CONTENTS. Book VII

QUESTION 54. An Angel s Cognition

QUESTION 67. The Duration of the Virtues after this Life

The question is concerning truth and it is inquired first what truth is. Now

Rationalism. A. He, like others at the time, was obsessed with questions of truth and doubt

A Man to Be Wrestled With

Introduction. I. Proof of the Minor Premise ( All reality is completely intelligible )

QUESTION 3. God s Simplicity

QUESTION 86. What Our Intellect Has Cognition of in Material Things

QUESTION 10. The Modality with Which the Will is Moved

Thomas Aquinas The Treatise on the Divine Nature

Aquinas, Hylomorphism and the Human Soul

Freedom as Morality. UWM Digital Commons. University of Wisconsin Milwaukee. Hao Liang University of Wisconsin-Milwaukee. Theses and Dissertations

THE PHILOSOPHY OF NATURE. jennifer ROSATO

Unit VI: Davidson and the interpretational approach to thought and language

REFLECTIONS ON THE RELATION BETWEEN PHILOSOPHY AND THEOLOGY GERALD VAN ACKEREN, S.J.

24.01 Classics of Western Philosophy

WHY IS GOD GOOD? EUTYPHRO, TIMAEUS AND THE DIVINE COMMAND THEORY

The Evangelical Turn of John Paul II and Veritatis Splendor

Testimony and Moral Understanding Anthony T. Flood, Ph.D. Introduction

John Duns Scotus. 1. His Life and Works. Handout 24. called The Subtle Doctor. born in 1265 (or 1266) in Scotland; died in Cologne in 1308

philippine studies Ateneo de Manila University Loyola Heights, Quezon City 1108 Philippines Philippine Studies vol. 22, no. 3-4 (1974)

On Being and Essence (DE ENTE Et ESSENTIA)

Thomas Aquinas on the World s Duration. Summa Theologiae Ia Q46: The Beginning of the Duration of Created Things

philippine studies Ateneo de Manila University Loyola Heights, Quezon City 1108 Philippines Philippine Studies vol. 44, no.

Summary of Kant s Groundwork of the Metaphysics of Morals

The Middle Path: A Case for the Philosophical Theologian. Leo Strauss roots the vitality of Western civilization in the ongoing conflict between

Kant s Fundamental Principles of the Metaphysic of Morals

You may not start to read the questions printed on the subsequent pages of this question paper until instructed that you may do so by the Invigilator

NOT CLASSICAL, COVENANTAL

What We Are: Our Metaphysical Nature & Moral Implications

A Review of Norm Geisler's Prolegomena

The Divine Nature. from Summa Theologiae (Part I, Questions 3-11) by Thomas Aquinas (~1265 AD) translated by Brian J.

AQUINAS S FOURTH WAY: FROM GRADATIONS OF BEING

Faith and Reason Thomas Aquinas

First Treatise <Chapter 1. On the Eternity of Things>

QUESTION 47. The Diversity among Things in General

Phil Aristotle. Instructor: Jason Sheley

The Unbearable Lightness of Theory of Knowledge:

Have you ever sought God? Do you have any idea of God? Do you believe that God exist?

1/12. The A Paralogisms

Aquinas on Spiritual Change. In "Is an Aristotelian Philosophy of Mind Still Credible? (A draft)," Myles

philippine studies Ateneo de Manila University Loyola Heights, Quezon City 1108 Philippines

c:=} up over the question of a "Christian philosophy." Since it

QUESTION 53. The Corruption and Diminution of Habits. Article 1. Can a habit be corrupted?

QUESTION 65. The Connectedness of the Virtues

THE ORDINATIO OF BLESSED JOHN DUNS SCOTUS. Book Two. First Distinction (page 16)

QUESTION 55. The Essence of a Virtue

- 1 - Outline of NICOMACHEAN ETHICS, Book I Book I--Dialectical discussion leading to Aristotle's definition of happiness: activity in accordance

INTRODUCTION THEOLOGY

On the Relation of Philosophy to the Theology Conference Seward 11/24/98

Aquinas' Third Way Modalized

What Part of the Soul Does Justice Perfect? Shane Drefcinski Department of Humanities/Philosophy University of Wisconsin Platteville

QUESTION 8. The Objects of the Will

QUESTION 4. The Virtue Itself of Faith

WHAT IS THE USE OF USUS IN AQUINAS' PSYCHOLOGY OF ACTION? Stephen L. Brock

QUESTION 58. The Mode of an Angel s Cognition

Essays in Systematic Theology 34: What Is the Gift of the Holy Spirit? 1

QUESTION 36. The Causes of Sadness or Pain. Article 1. Is it a lost good that is a cause of pain rather than a conjoined evil?

FUNDAMENTAL PRINCIPLES OF THE METAPHYSIC OF MORALS. by Immanuel Kant

Alexander of Hales, The Sum of Theology 1 (translated by Oleg Bychkov) Introduction, Question One On the discipline of theology

CHAPTER THREE ON SEEING GOD THROUGH HIS IMAGE IMPRINTED IN OUR NATURAL POWERS

Transcription:

philippine studies Ateneo de Manila University Loyola Heights, Quezon City 1108 Philippines V. Subject and Soul Bernard J. F. Lonergan Philippine Studies vol. 13, no. 3 (1965): 576 585 Copyright Ateneo de Manila University Philippine Studies is published by the Ateneo de Manila University. Contents may not be copied or sent via email or other means to multiple sites and posted to a listserv without the copyright holder s written permission. Users may download and print articles for individual, noncommercial use only. However, unless prior permission has been obtained, you may not download an entire issue of a journal, or download multiple copies of articles. Please contact the publisher for any further use of this work at philstudies@admu.edu.ph. http://www.philippinestudies.net Fri June 30 13:30:20 2008

Subject and Soul BERNARD.i. F. LONERZKNN,S~J. VER fifteen years ago I completed a series of articles in Theological Studies with the title, "The Concept of Verbum in the Writings of St. Thomas Aquinas." The present essay originally was written as an introduction to a re-issue of the articles in book form, but the question it raises is, perhaps, significant and timely enough to merit inclusion in Philippine Studies. As the reader will recall, the novelty of the uerbum articles was their effort to show that the Thomist analysis of intellect was not merely metaphysical but also psychological, that it was concerned not only with the intellect as a power of the human soul but also with the intelligence of conscious human subjects. The purpose of these pages will be to return to this basic point. For Thomist thought on verbum is metaphysical by its insertion in an Aristotelian framework, and it is psychological in virtue of its derivation from Augustinian trinitarian theory. We shall touch on each of these themes in turn to conclude with an account of the structure of the already mentioned articles on verbum in Aquinas. The Aristotelian framework was impressive. First, it was a general theory of being, a metaphysics. Secondly, it was a general theory of movement, a physics in that now antiquated sense. Thirdly, it was a general theory of life, a biology. Fourthly, it was a general theory of sensitivity and intelligence, a psychology.

LONERGAN: SUBJECT AND SOUL 577 In this framework, since the prior components are comprehensive, the later are not pure but cumulative. Because movements exist, physical statements are not just physical; they are determinations added to metaphysical statements. Because living things move, biological statements are not just biological; they are determinations added to metaphysical and physical statements. Because sentient and intelligent beings are alive, psychological statements are not purely psychological; they presuppose and employ and determine what already has been settled in metaphysics, physics, and biology. The use of such a framework gave Aristotelian thought its majestic coherence and comprehensiveness. The interlocking of each part with all the others precluded the possibility of merely patchwork revisions. As Prof. Butterfield has observed, to correct Aristotle effectively, one must go beyond him; and to go beyond him is to set up a system equal in comprehensiveness and more successful in inner coherence and in conformity with fad.' Still such attempts have been made and, indeed, in two quite different manners. There have been open repudiations of Aristotle, as in modern science and in much modern philosophy. There also has been the more delicate procedure of sublation that developed and transformed Aristotelian positions to the point where the incorporation of further and profounder doctrines became possible. Such was the method of Aquinas, and our immediate concern is to find in Aristotle the point of insertion for Augustinian thought. It is not difficult to discern. I distinguished above four components in the Aristotelian framework. I must hasten to add that, in a sense, the distinction between the third and fourth, between biology and psychology, is not as clear, as sharp, as fully developed, as may be desired. For Aristotle's De anima is at once biological and psychological. It does not confuse plants, animals, and men. At the same time it fails to bring out effectively the essential difference between an investigation of plant life and an investigation of the human *The point is made repeatedly by Herbert Butterfield, The Origin of Modern Science, 1300-1800, New York 1960.

mind; much less, does it work out the methodological implications of that essential difference. The De anima is about soul. If the Platonic nauta in navz is suggestive of the subject, the Aristotelian soul is not. It is an inner principle constituent of life. It is defined as the first act of an organic body."t is found in all organic bodies, in plants no less than in animals and men. Moreover, a single method is worked out for determining the differences of souls and so for investigating each species of the genus. Souls are differentiated by their potencies; potencies are known by their acts; acts are specified by their objecks But what is meant by an object? That is the decisive question. For the meaning given the term, object, will settle the specification given acts; the specification of ads will settle the distinction between potencies; and the distinction between potencies will settle the essential differences between the souls of plants, animals, and men. A modern reader is apt to take it for granted that by an object Aristotle must mean the intentional term of a conscious act. But quite evidently Aquinas was of a different opinion. In his Commentary he defines objects in terms, not of intentionality, but of causality: an object is either the efficient or the final cause of the occurence of an act of a potency.' Nor is it easy to disagree with Aquinas. He goes beyond what is explicit in the text. But as the book of definitions in the Metaphysics5 reveals, Aristotle used his word for object, antikeirnenon, in a great variety of meanings. In the immediate context in the De anima he illustrates objects not only by the sensible and the intelligible, which are the intentional terms of conscious acts, but also by nutriment, which in the case of plants has not an intentional but only a causal relation to acts. It is at this point that there comes to light the problem to which I have already alluded. No one will complain that 2 De iinirna 11, 1, 412b 4 ff. Slbid. 11, 4, 41% 14-20. In II de An., lect. 6 sec. 305. 5 Met. D, 10.

LONERGAN: SUBJECT AND SOUL Aristotle did not employ introspective techniques in his study of plant life. But one could well complain if a method, suitable for the study of plants, were alone employed in the study of human sensitivity and human intelligence. If the objects of vegetative activity are causal, it remains that the objects of sensitive and intellectual activity are also intentional. If vegetative acts are not accessible to introspection, sensitive and intellectual acts are among the immediate data of consciousness; they can be reached, not only by deduction from their objects, but also in themselves as given in consciousnes. Finally, when conscious acts are studied by introspection, one discovers not only the acts and their intentional terms but also the intending subject, and there arises the problem of the relation of subject to soul, of the Augustinian mens or animus to the Aristotelian anim. If in Scholastic circles such a Problematik is contemporary and indeed, for many, still novel, it is plain that neither Aristotle nor Aquinas handled the matter in a triumphantly definitive fashion. This is not to say, of course, that they anticipated positivists and behaviourists by systematically avoiding any use of introspection or any appeal to the data of consciousness. As we shall see, Aquinas explicitly appealed to inner experience and, I submit, Aristotle's account of intelligence, of insight into phantasm, and of the fact that intellect knows itself, not by a species of itself, but by a species of its object, has too uncanny an accuracy to be possible without the greatest introspective skill. But if Aristotle and Aquinas used introspection and did so brilliantly, it remains that they did not thematize their use, did not elevate it into a reflectively elaborated technique, did not work out a proper method for psychology and thereby lay the groundwork for the contemporary distinctions between nature and spirit and between the natural and the human sciences. It is time to turn to Augustine: a convert from nature to spirit; a person that, by God's grace, made himself what he was; a subject that may be studied but, most of all, must be encountered in the outpouring of his self-revelation and selfcommunication. The context of his thought on vmbum was

trinitarian, and its underlying preoccupation was anti-arb. It followed that the prologue to the Fourth Gospel had to be freed from any Arian implication. To achieve this end Augustine did not employ our contemporary techniques of linguistic and literary history. He did not attempt a fresh translation of the Greek word, Idgm, but retained the traditional verbum. Church tradition, perhaps, precluded any appeal to the Stoic distinction between verbum prolatum and verbrnn insitum6 In any case he cut between these Stoic terms to discover a third verbum that was neither the verbum prolatum of human speech nor the verbum insitum of man's native rationality but an intermediate verbum intw prolatum. Naturally enough, ;IS Augustine's discovery was part and parcel of his own mind's Itnowledge of itself, so he begged his readers to look within themselves and there to discover the speech of spirit within spirit, an inner verbum prior to any use of language yet distinct both from the mind itself and from its memory or its present apprehension of objects. Though I cannot attempt here to do justice to the wealth of Augustine's thought or to the variety of its expression,' at least it will serve to illustrate my meaning if, however, arbitrarily, I select and briefly comment on a single passage. Haec igitur omnia, et quae per se ipsum, et quae per sensus sui corporis, et quae testimoniis alionun percepta scit animus humanus, thesauro memoriae condita tenet, ex quibus gignitur verbum ante omnem sonurn, ante omnem wgitationem soni. Tune enim est verbum simillimum rei notae, de qua gignitur, et imago eius, quoniam de visione scientiae visio cogitationis exoritur, quod est verbum linguae nullius, verbum venun de re Vera, nihil de suo habens, sed totum de illa scientia de qua nascitur. Nec interest quando id didicerit, qui quod scit loquitur; aliquando enim statim ut discit, hoc dicit; durn tamen verbum sit venun, id est, de notis rebus exortum.8. - a On the distinction, G. Kittel, TWPIITT IV, 84, 12 ff. (Kleinknwht) ; M. Schmaus, Die psyclrologische Trinitatslehre des hl. Augustinus, Munster 1927, p. 33 n. 11. On the tradition, cf. St. Ambrose, De fide ad Gratianum, IV, vii, 72, ML 16, 631; also DS 140 can. 8. 1 would like in this connection to dmw attention to a forthcoming work in the series, Anulecta Gregoriana: S. Biolo, La coecienza nel "De Trinit~te" di S. Agostim. 8 De trinitate XV, xii, 22; ML 42, 1075.

LONERGAN: SUBJECT AND SOUL In this passage, then, the Augustinian uerbum is a nonlinguistic utterance of truth. It differs from expression in any language, for it is lingwe nullius. It is not primitive but derived: gignitur, exoritur, nuscitur. Its dependence is total: nihil de suo habens, sed totum de iua scientia de qua nascitur. This total dependence is, not blind or automatic, but conscious and cognitive: quod scimus loquimur; de visione scientiue visio cogitatwnis exoritur; qui quod scit loquitur. Finally, this total dependence as conscious and known is the essential point. It makes no difference whether the verbum has its ground in memory or in recently acquired knowledge. What counts is its truth, its correspondence with things as known: verbum simillimum rei notae; imago eius; verbum velum de re vera, nihd de suo habens, sed totum de illa scientia de qua mscitur; durn tumen verbum sit verum, id est, de notis rebus exortum. Such, at least, in one passage, is what Augustine had to say about verbum. Many more passages might be cited and they would reveal him saying different Zhings or the same things in a different; manner. But sooner or later it would be necessary to advance from the simpler question of what he said to the more difficult question of what he meant. Since 1 am writing not a study of Augustine but an introduction to i1 study of Aquinas, I must leap at once to the more difficult question, though not to answer it in detail, but only to indicate the source from which the answer must proceed. A blind man may listen to a disquisition on colour, but he is bound to find it obscure. A person who is deaf may read a book on music, but he will have a hard time deciding whether the author is talking sense or nonsense. In similar fashion it is only by introspection that one can discover what an introspective psychologist is talking about. If what Augustine had to say about verbum was true, then it corresponded exactly to what Augustine knew went on in his own mind. If what Augustine had to say about verbum was universally true, then it corresponds exactly to what Augustine knew goes on in any human mind. If one supposes Augustine to be right and, at the same time, entertains an admiration for Newman, one is going to ask whether the Augustinian couplet of memoria and

582 PHZLIPPZNE STUDZES verbum is parallel to Newman's couplet of illative sense and unconditional assent. But if one desires to get beyond words and suppositions to meanings and facts, then one has to explore one's own mind and find out for oneself what there is to be meant; and until one does so, one is in the unhappy position of the blind man hearing about colours and the deaf man reading about counterpoint. About such matters Auystine was explicit. Unde enzm mens aliquam mentem novit, si se non novit? Neque enim ut oculus corporis videt alios oculos et se non videt...mew ergo ipsa sicut corporearum rerum notitius per sensus corporis colligit, sic incorporearum per semetipsam. Ergo et semetipsam per se ipsam novit... Moreover, for Augustine, the mind's self-knowledge was basic; it was the rock of certitude on which shattered Academic doubt; it provided the ground from which one could argue to the validity both of the senses of one's own body and, with the mediation of testimony, of the senses of the bodies of others. So the passage we have quoted and explained begins with this threefold enumeration: quae per se ipsum, et qme per sensus slti corporis, et qme testimoniis aliorum percepta sctt animus humanus. The enumeration merely summarizes what had been set forth at greater length in the immediately preceding paragraph;1 and that paragraph, of course, only resumes a theme that is recurrent from Augustiie's earliest writings on. Clearly enough, it was neither per sensus sui corporis nor by auenorum corporum semus that Augustine knew of a verbum that was neither Latin nor Greek, neither sound nor even the thought of sound. The Augustinian affirmation of verbum was itself a verbum. For it to be true, on Augustine's own showing, it had to be totally dependent on what Augustine's mind knew through itself about itself. On the existence and - ------ De trinitate IX, iii, 3; ML 42, 962 f. '0 Zbid. XV, xii, 21; 1073-75.

LONERGAN: SUBJECT AND SOUL 583 nature of such knowledge Augustine had a great deal to say, and there is no need for us to attempt to repeat it here. Though it cannot be claimed that Augustine elevated introspection into a scientific technique, it cannot be doubted that he purported to report in his literary language what his own mind knew immediately about itself. So we come to Aquinas. Because he conceived theology as in some sense a science, he needed Aristotle who, more than anyone, had worked out and applied the implications of the Greek ideal of science. Because his theology was essentially the expression of a traditional faith, he needed Augustine, the Father of the West, whose trinitarian thought was the high-water mark in Christian attempts to reach an understanding of faith. Because Aquinas-himself was a genius, he experienced no great difficulty either in adapting Aristotle to his purpose or in reaching a refinement in his account of rational process-the emanatio intelligibilis that made explicit what Augustine could only suggest. Because, finally, Aquinas was a man of his time, he had to leave to a la&r age the task of acknowledging the discontinuity of natural and of human science and of working out its methological implications. For performance must precede refledion on performance, and met.hod is the fruit of this reflection. Aquinas had to be content to perform. My study of that performance is divided into five articles, and the division is dictated by the quite different systematic contexts in which Thomist statements about verbum are involved. Already I have noted the cumulative character of Aristotelian categories, in which psychological statements presuppose biological, biological presuppose physical, and physical presuppose metaphysical. In a somewhat similar fashion Thomist statements about verbum will be theological in their primary intent; they will involve technical terms drawn from physics and metaphysics; their meaning will turn on metaphysical explanations of gnoseological possibility; and embedded in this structural complexity there will be a core of psychoiogica1 fact. To reach even an approximation to what

Aquinas meant, it is necessary to explore separately the several hermeneutical circles that, in cumulative fashion, are relevant to an interpretation. The first two articles are concerned with the core of psychological fact. Aquinas identified verbum with the immanent terminal object of intellectual operation; he distinguished two intellectual operations, a first in answer to the question, quid sit, and a second in answer to the question, an sit. So we have a first article on verbum as definition, and second on verbum as compositio vel divisio. Throughout the first two articles the reader will be troubled by the recurrence of technical terms of a metaphysical or physical origin. Quite apart from any intrinsic difficulty they may offer, the determination of their meaning is enormously complicated, first, by Aristotle's efforts to adapt the Greek language to his own technical purposes, secondly, by the imperfect coincidence of the earlier Latin equivalents, mediated by Arabic culture, and the later fruits of direct translation from the Greek, and thirdly, for those who approach Aquinas through manuals and commentaries quite innocent of the methods of literary and historical research, by such interpreters' proclivity to smooth out linguistic oddities by giving free reign to their talent for speculative invention. The third article is an effort to cut through this jungle. The fourth article deals with matters intermediate between metaphysics and psychology. Such is the doctrine of abstraction from matter. Such also are the re!ations between immateriality and knowledge. Finally, St. Thomas's thought on verbum occurs, for ;the most part, in a trinitarian context. If Thomist philosophers, quite comprehensibly, are reluctant to venture into his field, it remains that a historian must do so. St. Thomas was a theologian. His thought on verbum was, in the main, a statement for his technically minded age of the psychological analogy of the trinitarian processions. Its simplicity, its profundity, and its brilliance have long been obscured by in-

LONERGAN: SUBJECT AND SOUL 585 ferpreters unaware of the relevant psychological facts and unequal to the task of handling merely linguistic problems." So it is that the final article deals with the trinitarian meaning of imago Dei, and there, I hope, the many levels of our study come together. " This may appear harsh. but I find no other explanation for the startling discrepancies that exist. In his account of intellectual procession no less eminent a theologian than L. Billot could write: Et simile cxnnino est in imaginatione (De Weo Uno et Trino, Roma 1910, p. 335). But St. Thomas explicitly restricted the trinitarian analogy to the minds of rational creatures. Sum. theol. I, q. 93, a. 6 c: nec in ~psa rationali creatura invenitur Dei imago nisi secundum mentem. Cf. In I Sent., d. 3, q. 3, a. 1; De Ver., q. 10, aa. 1 sec. 7; De Pot., (1 9, a. 9 ad /in.; C. Gent., IV, 11.