The Theory/Experiment Interface of the Observation of Black Holes

Similar documents
Phil 1103 Review. Also: Scientific realism vs. anti-realism Can philosophers criticise science?

Sydenham College of Commerce & Economics. * Dr. Sunil S. Shete. * Associate Professor

UNITY OF KNOWLEDGE (IN TRANSDISCIPLINARY RESEARCH FOR SUSTAINABILITY) Vol. I - Philosophical Holism M.Esfeld

HPS 1653 / PHIL 1610 Revision Guide (all topics)

Realism and the success of science argument. Leplin:

Jeu-Jenq Yuann Professor of Philosophy Department of Philosophy, National Taiwan University,

World without Design: The Ontological Consequences of Natural- ism , by Michael C. Rea.

I. Scientific Realism: Introduction

CLASS #17: CHALLENGES TO POSITIVISM/BEHAVIORAL APPROACH

The problems of induction in scientific inquiry: Challenges and solutions. Table of Contents 1.0 Introduction Defining induction...

Overview. Is there a priori knowledge? No: Mill, Quine. Is there synthetic a priori knowledge? Yes: faculty of a priori intuition (Rationalism, Kant)

In Defense of Radical Empiricism. Joseph Benjamin Riegel. Chapel Hill 2006

Phil/Ling 375: Meaning and Mind [Handout #10]

Ayer on the criterion of verifiability

Verificationism. PHIL September 27, 2011

PHI2391: Logical Empiricism I 8.0

Scientific Method and Research Ethics Questions, Answers, and Evidence. Dr. C. D. McCoy

The Problem of Induction and Popper s Deductivism

Naturalized Epistemology. 1. What is naturalized Epistemology? Quine PY4613

Class 6 - Scientific Method

145 Philosophy of Science

FINAL EXAM REVIEW SHEET. objectivity intersubjectivity ways the peer review system is supposed to improve objectivity

Philosophy of Science. Ross Arnold, Summer 2014 Lakeside institute of Theology

MY PURPOSE IN THIS BOOK IS TO PRESENT A

THE HYPOTHETICAL-DEDUCTIVE METHOD OR THE INFERENCE TO THE BEST EXPLANATION: THE CASE OF THE THEORY OF EVOLUTION BY NATURAL SELECTION

From the Routledge Encyclopedia of Philosophy

- We might, now, wonder whether the resulting concept of justification is sufficiently strong. According to BonJour, apparent rational insight is

In Defense of Pure Reason: A Rationalist Account of A Priori Justification, by Laurence BonJour. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press,

Philosophy Epistemology Topic 5 The Justification of Induction 1. Hume s Skeptical Challenge to Induction

What is a counterexample?

Logic is the study of the quality of arguments. An argument consists of a set of

Philosophy 5340 Epistemology Topic 4: Skepticism. Part 1: The Scope of Skepticism and Two Main Types of Skeptical Argument

Business Research: Principles and Processes MGMT6791 Workshop 1A: The Nature of Research & Scientific Method

The Positive Argument for Constructive Empiricism and Inference to the Best

Reflective Equilibrium. Hassan Masoud Jan. 30, 2012

Ch V: The Vienna Circle (Moritz Schlick, Rudolf Carnap, and Otto Neurath)[title crossed out?]

LENT 2018 THEORY OF MEANING DR MAARTEN STEENHAGEN

UNIVERSITY OF ALBERTA MATHEMATICS AS MAKE-BELIEVE: A CONSTRUCTIVE EMPIRICIST ACCOUNT SARAH HOFFMAN

Analyticity, Reductionism, and Semantic Holism. The verification theory is an empirical theory of meaning which asserts that the meaning of a

PHILOSOPHY 4360/5360 METAPHYSICS. Methods that Metaphysicians Use

Van Fraassen: Arguments Concerning Scientific Realism

An Empiricist Theory of Knowledge Bruce Aune

The Philosophy of Physics. Physics versus Metaphysics

NOTES ON A PRIORI KNOWLEDGE 10/6/03

Are Scientific Theories True?

Final Paper. May 13, 2015

PH 1000 Introduction to Philosophy, or PH 1001 Practical Reasoning

Scientific realism and anti-realism

A Defense for Scientific Realism:

PHILOSOPHICAL RAMIFICATIONS: THEORY, EXPERIMENT, & EMPIRICAL TRUTH

Epistemic Utility and Theory-Choice in Science: Comments on Hempel

Class 4 - The Myth of the Given

INDUCTIVE AND DEDUCTIVE

Logic: inductive. Draft: April 29, Logic is the study of the quality of arguments. An argument consists of a set of premises P1,

Quine on Holism and Underdetermination

PHILOSOPHY OF LANGUAGE

Philosophy 5340 Epistemology. Topic 6: Theories of Justification: Foundationalism versus Coherentism. Part 2: Susan Haack s Foundherentist Approach

Key definitions Action Ad hominem argument Analytic A priori Axiom Bayes s theorem

Quine and the a priori

Karl Popper & The Philosophy of Science. What Makes a Theory Scientific?

REVIEW THE DOOR TO SELLARS

Chapter One. Constructive Empiricism and the Case. Against Scientific Realism

THE SEMANTIC REALISM OF STROUD S RESPONSE TO AUSTIN S ARGUMENT AGAINST SCEPTICISM

Argumentation Module: Philosophy Lesson 7 What do we mean by argument? (Two meanings for the word.) A quarrel or a dispute, expressing a difference

Rethinking Knowledge: The Heuristic View

Logic, Truth & Epistemology. Ross Arnold, Summer 2014 Lakeside institute of Theology

Intro. The need for a philosophical vocabulary

Do we have knowledge of the external world?

The linguistic-cultural nature of scientific truth 1

PHILOSOPHY 5340 EPISTEMOLOGY

Philosophy 427 Intuitions and Philosophy. Russell Marcus Hamilton College Fall 2011

Does Deduction really rest on a more secure epistemological footing than Induction?

Cory Juhl, Eric Loomis, Analyticity (New York: Routledge, 2010).

INDUCTIVE KNOWLEDGE. (For Routledge Companion to Epistemology) Alexander Bird

How Do We Know Anything about Mathematics? - A Defence of Platonism

Constructing the World

Junior Research Fellow and Lecturer in Philosophy Worcester College, University of Oxford Walton Street Oxford OX1 2HB Great Britain

Gary Ebbs, Carnap, Quine, and Putnam on Methods of Inquiry, Cambridge. University Press, 2017, 278pp., $99.99 (hbk), ISBN

Unit. Science and Hypothesis. Downloaded from Downloaded from Why Hypothesis? What is a Hypothesis?

An Introduction to Language Faculty Science Some Quotations plus alpha

Oxford Scholarship Online Abstracts and Keywords

What is rationality? (Paper presented by Tim Harding at Mordi Skeptics meetup, 1 February 2011)

Psillos s Defense of Scientific Realism

Remarks on the philosophy of mathematics (1969) Paul Bernays

ON QUINE, ANALYTICITY, AND MEANING Wylie Breckenridge

Ultimate Naturalistic Causal Explanations

Semantic Foundations for Deductive Methods

Direct Realism and the Brain-in-a-Vat Argument by Michael Huemer (2000)

Empiricism, Natural Regularity, and Necessity

Falsification or Confirmation: From Logic to Psychology

Ayer s linguistic theory of the a priori

Lectures and laboratories activities on the nature of Physics and concepts and models in optic: 1. Scientific sentences

Lecture 9. A summary of scientific methods Realism and Anti-realism

Review of David J. Chalmers Constructing the World (OUP 2012) David Chalmers burst onto the philosophical scene in the mid-1990s with his work on

Tuomas E. Tahko (University of Helsinki)

Understanding Truth Scott Soames Précis Philosophy and Phenomenological Research Volume LXV, No. 2, 2002

SCIENTIFIC REALISM AND EPISTEMOLOGY

The University of Strathclyde 16 Richmond St, Glasgow G1 1XQ

Varieties of Apriority

MARK KAPLAN AND LAWRENCE SKLAR. Received 2 February, 1976) Surely an aim of science is the discovery of the truth. Truth may not be the

Transcription:

Manfred Stöckler Institut für Philosophie Universität Bremen The Theory/Experiment Interface of the Observation of Black Holes Manfred Stöckler stoeckl@uni-bremen.de Bad Honnef 17/04/27 1

Introduction Do Black Holes Exist? # mathematical descriptions # physical properties # empirical consequences # measurements of consequences 2

Introduction The Problem When do results of a measurement give good reasons that we have found a special physical object? Special case: When do results of measurements of stellar orbits, special X-ray emissions, and near infrared emissions from the location of the radio source Sagittarius A* give good reasons that we have found a supermassive black hole? 3

Introduction Good empirical reasons for the existence of Black Holes? What scientist do: Eckart, A., Kiefer, C., Britzen, S., et al. The Milky Way s Supermassive Black Hole: How good a case is it? Foundations of Physics 47 (2017) 553-624 What philosophers think about it: Can philosophy of science supply some general criteria for an answer? There is no concluding answer, but a variety of proposals for solving similar problems 4

What philosophers think about it: Introduction Typical problem: When does some evidence confirm a general theory? Philosophy of science has its own tradition. Starting with Logical Positivism (empiricism & modern logic) elementary applications of logic to scientific sentences later on: studying more realistic case studies 5

Overview Overwiew 1. Theories and facts in logical empiricism 2. Deductive and inductive approaches to a theory of confirmation 3. A more complex picture of the theory/experiment interface 4. A new methodological interest in experiments 5. Arguing for the existence of physical objects 6. Proposals for partial solutions 7. Philosophy of science and reflective equilibrium 6

1. Theories and facts in logical empiricism Logical Empriricism Movement of philosophers in 1920s, 1930s (Vienna, Berlin) England, later on USA # linguistic turn # modern logic # empiricism Meaningful propositions must either be analytic or empirically verifiable mathematics: analytic truth sciences: based on logical inferences from simple protocol sentences grounded on observable facts (empirical and theoretical language) metaphysics: not meaningful 7

Generalized sentences can not be verified: Logical Empriricism Two components: (1) Basic propositions (directly and strictly verifiable, incorrigible). (2) All other propositions can indirectly verified by reference to the empirical basis (1). empiristic tradition in epistemology fundamentalism or coherentism (empiristic or rationalistic) R. Carnap: confirmation (inductive logic) Justifying general propositions (laws) by special instances. Questions of existence of special physical objects are similar to questions of justification of general theories. 8

Theories of confirmation 2. Deductive and Inductive Approaches to a Theory of Confirmation General propositions ( All ravens are black. ) can not be proven by a finite number of observations. We need more tools than plain logical entailment. Reasoning from evidence is necessarily fallible. General idea: Evidence (observations, data, reports of the result of experiments (premises)) can affect the credibility of hypotheses. 9

Confirmation by instances Hypothetico-deductivism Theories of confirmation Evidence e confirms a hypothesis h in case the latter is able to entail e (with the help of suitable auxiliary hypotheses and assumptions). Problems: varying degrees of credibility Popper: Falsificationism Sceptical position: Theories can not be confirmed, but they can be falsified (evolutionary process: surviving theories are nearer to the truth ). 10

Underdetermination Theories of confirmation Given any theory about unobservables which fits observable facts there will be other incompatible theories which fit the same fact. Duhem-Quine-Problem: (h & a) e We should be able to say more about the degree to which a given body of evidence supports a given theory. Instead of purely logical relations: degrees of belief, credibility of proposition subjective (epistemic) probabilities 11

Bayesian confirmation theory # formal apparatus for inductive logic Theories of confirmation # laws of probability are coherence constraints on rational degrees of belief (degrees of confidence) # part of a general conception for belief, inference and behaviour Unconditional probabilities P(b) as primitives Conditional probabilities: P(b a) = P(b&a)/P(a) Start with P i (h) ( prior ) P f (h) = P i (h e) P f (h) = (P i (e h) (P i (h)) / P i (e) Bayes Theorem 12

Bayesian confirmation theory P f (h) = ( P i (e h) (P i (h) ) / P i (e) Bayes Theorem Theories of confirmation Dynamics of belief revision Example: Confirmation effect of surprising evidence e is much more expected if it were known that h were true 13

3. A More Complex Picture of the Theory/ Experiment Interface Logical empiricism: just experimental reports More complex picture Mario Bunge, Philosophy of Physics, Dordrecht 1973, chpt. 10 data are anything but given: they are produced and interpreted with the help of theories. most theories do not concern observations and measurements, let alone acts of perception, but things or rather idealised models of them. testable propositions seldom if ever follow from the assumptions of a single theory but, rather, are usually entailed by the theory in conjunction with additional assumptions and with bits of information other than those serving to check the theory. 14

. Mario Bunge, Philosophy of Physics History of science: More complex picture the history of science abounds in examples of theories that have been upheld in the face of adverse empirical evidence - and rightly so, for the data proved wrong in the end. Nonempirical tests: The theory must be well built, it must not go against the grain of justified scientific beliefs, and it must not postulate items that are either metaphysically objectionable (such as an electron s ability to make decisions) Consistency, coherence 15

Mario Bunge: Philosophy of Physics Observation: More complex picture Scientific observation, unlike the observations of babies and empiricist philosophy, is permeated by hypotheses and expectations, some explicit, most tacit. (even ordinary observation is determined jointly by sensation and ideation) Empirical evidence is neither purely empirical nor conclusive. Duhem-Quine 16

New interest in experiments 4. A New Methodological interest in experiments Logical empiricism: Experimental process was set aside, only the final product has been considered: experimental reports. New interest in experiments: Franklin, Galison, Hacking (1983) Experiments provide us with knowledge of the physical world, experiments provide the evidence. # describing experiments in detail # emphasizing human action and causal interaction 17

New interest in experiments Allan Franklin: What makes a good experiment? Pittsburgh 2016 (Pittsburgh University Press) Experiments can be good in many ways: conceptually good, methodologically, technically, pedagogically important There is no simple set of criteria for ranking or evaluating good experiments. Part III: Evidence for entities (neutrino, Higgs boson) 18

Existence of physical objects 5. Arguing for the Existence of Physical Objects When we are justified in believing in the existence of a special type of physical objects? W. Sellars (1962): to have good reasons for holding a theory is ipso facto to have good reasons for holding that the entities postulated by the theory exist objects as necessary parts of theories (Quine) (fields in electromagnetism)? special entities, that might exist (additional planet) (space-time singularity: limit of the domain of applicability of general relativity?) 19

Existence of physical objects W.V.O. Quine There is no special (philosophical) way to ontology: Ontological questions are on par with questions of natural science We do not learn first what to talk about an then what to say about it. Context of theories: Direct experience is not necessary. We posit molecules, and eventually electrons, even though these are not given to direct experience, merely because they contribute to an overall system which is simpler as whole than its known alternatives. 20

W.V.O. Quine Existence of physical objects Ontic decisions : similar criteria as for theories: Simplicity, scope (unification), fruitfulness How do we decide, apropos of the real world, what things there are? Ultimately, I think, by considerations of simplicity plus pragmatic guess as to how the overall system will continue to work in connection with experience. Holism 21

W.V.O. Quine Existence of physical objects The empirical relevance of the notion of molecules and electrons is indirect, and exists only by the virtue of the links with experience which exist at other points of the system. Actually I expect that gables and sheep are, in the last analysis, on much the same footing as molecules and electrons. In whatever sense the molecules in my desk are unreal and a figment of the imagination of the scientist, in that sense the desk itself is unreal and a figment of the imagination of the race. Continuum in epistemic access to objects, but not in the meaning of existence. 22

Existence of physical objects W. Sellars (1962): to have good reasons for holding a theory is ipso facto to have good reasons for holding that the entities postulated by the theory exist Cartwright (1983)/ Hacking (1983): manipulability of an entity as criterion for belief in existence trouble with astrophysics In contrast Franklin ( Experiment in physics, Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, Appendix 7) I will argue that experimenting on entities and measuring their properties can also provide ground for belief in their existence. Status of laws? 23

Existence of physical objects J.J. Thomson and the electrons: As the cathode rays carry a charge of negative electricity, are deflected by an electrostatic force as if they were negatively electrified, and are acted on by magnetic force in just the way in which this force would act on a negatively electrified body moving along the path of these rays, I can see no escape from the conclusion that they are charges of negative electricity carried by particle of matter. (1862) 24

6. Proposals for Partial Solutions Proposals for partial solutions 6.1 Abduction/ Inference to the best explanation Underdetermination A number of given hypotheses are empirically equivalent, any evidence is unable to favour one of them over the other. Additional criteria: Special status to explanatory considerations Type of inference often employed both in everyday life and in scientific reasoning. 25

Proposals for partial solutions Inference from explanatory power to truth : Given evidence e and candidate hypotheses h 1, h 2, h n h i explains e better than the other hypotheses Therefore: h i is (probably) true e 1, e 2,, e n are observations h explains e 1, e 2, e n better than all other alternative hypotheses. Therefore: h is (probably) true presupposition: a given set of hypotheses 26

Examples: Proposals for partial solutions Winston Churchill on the beach Orbit of Uranus Conclusion goes beyond what is logically contained in the premises. Widespread in everyday life and in science, but there is much discussion in philosophy of science about the justification. Abduction versus Bayesian Conformation Theory: compatible, supplement? 27

6.2 Further Intuitive Rules # new predictions # confirmation effect of surprising evidence # diverse evidence # coherence Proposals for partial solutions entities: (Franklin, p. 145): if we can reasonably infer that if the endproducts are observed, and there are no other competing processes that could produce those same products in sufficient numbers, than inverse β decay has been observed. holism Sherlock Holmes Strategy 28

6.3 Again: Bayesian Confirmation Theory Unifying conception Proposals for partial solutions Bayesian nets: account for more complex inferential structure in the theory/ experiment interface confirmation effect of surprising evidence, diverse evidence non-empirical confirmation constraint: theory of rationality problem of priors, metaphysical context 29

Conclusion: Role of Philosophy of Science 7. Philosophy of Science and Reflective Equilibrium When do results of a measurement give good reasons that we have found a special physical object? No ultimate consensus: Can science reveal the truth about unobservable objects? Can scientific reasoning be justified at all? Statements are justified by being a part of a coherent system. In addition: causal contact to the external world. Philosophy of science: Description or normative rules? 30

Method: reflective equilibrium Conclusion: Role of Philosophy of Science introduced by Nelson Goodman (1955): justification for the principles of inductive logic term coined by John Rawls: A Theory of Justice (1971) endpoint of a deliberative process: reflecting and revising our beliefs General rules are provided by what we believe to be good or by what is considered as an good example of inferential reasoning. These intuitions are systemized. Best account for a broad range of acceptable inferences. Working back and forth, avoiding inconsistencies Reflective equilibrium: State of balance arrived at by mutual adjustment among general principles and particular judgments. 31

Do Black Holes Exist? Yes or No? What does it mean, how do you know? What are the criteria? Philosophy and physics (in reflective equilibrium) Conclusion: Role of Philosophy of Science How good are the reasons for accepting the existence of black holes? The (subjective) probability/ credibility of the existence of BH is x (near to 1) What is the evidence? Physics 32

Conclusion: Role of Philosophy of Science What philosophy of science is good for? Clearing concepts and arguments Methodology # making rules of scientific reasoning explicit, finding patterns # evaluating disputed methods analogue gravity no alternative arguments Philosophy of Physics # metaphysics of spacetime # interpretations of quantum mechanics What philosophy of science is good for? Philosophy of science is about as useful to scientists as ornithology is to birds Attributed to Richard Feynman, is he right? 33