Boghossian, Bellarmine, and Bayes

Similar documents
In Epistemic Relativism, Mark Kalderon defends a view that has become

In Defense of Radical Empiricism. Joseph Benjamin Riegel. Chapel Hill 2006

A Priori Bootstrapping

Direct Realism and the Brain-in-a-Vat Argument by Michael Huemer (2000)

Philosophy Epistemology. Topic 3 - Skepticism

Varieties of Apriority

Can A Priori Justified Belief Be Extended Through Deduction? It is often assumed that if one deduces some proposition p from some premises

Received: 30 August 2007 / Accepted: 16 November 2007 / Published online: 28 December 2007 # Springer Science + Business Media B.V.

Explanatory Indispensability and Deliberative Indispensability: Against Enoch s Analogy Alex Worsnip University of North Carolina at Chapel Hill

PHL340 Handout 8: Evaluating Dogmatism

Does Deduction really rest on a more secure epistemological footing than Induction?

Philosophy 5340 Epistemology Topic 4: Skepticism. Part 1: The Scope of Skepticism and Two Main Types of Skeptical Argument

The Problem of Induction and Popper s Deductivism

Boghossian & Harman on the analytic theory of the a priori

Self-Evidence and A Priori Moral Knowledge

Mohammad Reza Vaez Shahrestani. University of Bonn

The Skeptic and the Dogmatist

Interest-Relativity and Testimony Jeremy Fantl, University of Calgary

ON EPISTEMIC ENTITLEMENT. by Crispin Wright and Martin Davies. II Martin Davies

Testimony and Moral Understanding Anthony T. Flood, Ph.D. Introduction

ALTERNATIVE SELF-DEFEAT ARGUMENTS: A REPLY TO MIZRAHI

Philosophical Perspectives, 16, Language and Mind, 2002 THE AIM OF BELIEF 1. Ralph Wedgwood Merton College, Oxford

Scientific Method and Research Ethics

Epistemological Externalism and the Project of Traditional Epistemology. Contemporary philosophers still haven't come to terms with the project of

THE MORAL ARGUMENT. Peter van Inwagen. Introduction, James Petrik

Robert Audi, The Architecture of Reason: The Structure and. Substance of Rationality. Oxford: Oxford University Press, Pp. xvi, 286.

Skepticism and Internalism

Deontological Perspectivism: A Reply to Lockie Hamid Vahid, Institute for Research in Fundamental Sciences, Tehran

SUPPOSITIONAL REASONING AND PERCEPTUAL JUSTIFICATION

PHILOSOPHY 5340 EPISTEMOLOGY

what makes reasons sufficient?

Wright on response-dependence and self-knowledge

THE CASE OF THE MINERS

STEWART COHEN AND THE CONTEXTUALIST THEORY OF JUSTIFICATION

UNDERSTANDING, JUSTIFICATION AND THE A PRIORI

Evidential arguments from evil

THE TWO-DIMENSIONAL ARGUMENT AGAINST MATERIALISM AND ITS SEMANTIC PREMISE

Is there a good epistemological argument against platonism? DAVID LIGGINS

World without Design: The Ontological Consequences of Natural- ism , by Michael C. Rea.

x is justified x is warranted x is supported by the evidence x is known.

DEFEASIBLE A PRIORI JUSTIFICATION: A REPLY TO THUROW

Is the Existence of the Best Possible World Logically Impossible?

Theories of epistemic justification can be divided into two groups: internalist and

Choosing Rationally and Choosing Correctly *

Justified Inference. Ralph Wedgwood

A solution to the problem of hijacked experience

I assume some of our justification is immediate. (Plausible examples: That is experienced, I am aware of something, 2 > 0, There is light ahead.

Moral Relativism and Conceptual Analysis. David J. Chalmers

Learning is a Risky Business. Wayne C. Myrvold Department of Philosophy The University of Western Ontario

Disintegrating Galileo: A Commentary on Pablé David Spurrett, University of KwaZulu-Natal, South Africa

Dogmatism and Moorean Reasoning. Markos Valaris University of New South Wales. 1. Introduction

DOES RORTY S PRAGMATISM UNDERMINE ITSELF?

On Some Alleged Consequences Of The Hartle-Hawking Cosmology. In [3], Quentin Smith claims that the Hartle-Hawking cosmology is inconsistent with

From Necessary Truth to Necessary Existence

Luck, Rationality, and Explanation: A Reply to Elga s Lucky to Be Rational. Joshua Schechter. Brown University

Nested Testimony, Nested Probability, and a Defense of Testimonial Reductionism Benjamin Bayer September 2, 2011

Philosophy Of Science On The Moral Neutrality Of Scientific Acceptance

Does the Skeptic Win? A Defense of Moore. I. Moorean Methodology. In A Proof of the External World, Moore argues as follows:

Rationalism of a moderate variety has recently enjoyed the renewed interest of

Klein on the Unity of Cartesian and Contemporary Skepticism

Philosophy Epistemology Topic 5 The Justification of Induction 1. Hume s Skeptical Challenge to Induction

NICHOLAS J.J. SMITH. Let s begin with the storage hypothesis, which is introduced as follows: 1

Philosophy 5340 Epistemology. Topic 6: Theories of Justification: Foundationalism versus Coherentism. Part 2: Susan Haack s Foundherentist Approach

Against Coherence: Truth, Probability, and Justification. Erik J. Olsson. Oxford: Oxford University Press, Pp. xiii, 232.

5 A Modal Version of the

Scientific Progress, Verisimilitude, and Evidence

The Rightness Error: An Evaluation of Normative Ethics in the Absence of Moral Realism

A Defense of the Significance of the A Priori A Posteriori Distinction. Albert Casullo. University of Nebraska-Lincoln

Psillos s Defense of Scientific Realism

A Solution to the Gettier Problem Keota Fields. the three traditional conditions for knowledge, have been discussed extensively in the

AUTHOR S PREPRINT. Deficiency Arguments Against Empiricism. and the Question of Empirical Indefeasibility

- We might, now, wonder whether the resulting concept of justification is sufficiently strong. According to BonJour, apparent rational insight is

Is Truth the Primary Epistemic Goal? Joseph Barnes

Comments on Lasersohn

Do we have knowledge of the external world?

Evidence and Normativity: Reply to Leite

What God Could Have Made

Relativism. We re both right.

Epistemological Foundations for Koons Cosmological Argument?

Against Phenomenal Conservatism

TWO VERSIONS OF HUME S LAW

Plantinga, Pluralism and Justified Religious Belief

Physicalism and Conceptual Analysis * Esa Díaz-León.

Rational Self-Doubt and the Failure of Closure *

PHILOSOPHY OF LOGIC AND LANGUAGE OVERVIEW FREGE JONNY MCINTOSH 1. FREGE'S CONCEPTION OF LOGIC

Naturalized Epistemology. 1. What is naturalized Epistemology? Quine PY4613

INTUITION AND CONSCIOUS REASONING

On Searle on Human Rights, Again! J. Angelo Corlett, San Diego State University

McDowell and the New Evil Genius

Does Rorty s Pragmatism Undermine Itself?

What is Relative Confirmation? * It is commonly acknowledged that, in order to test a theoretical hypothesis, one must, in

Understanding Truth Scott Soames Précis Philosophy and Phenomenological Research Volume LXV, No. 2, 2002

COPYRIGHT 2009ASSOCIAZIONE PRAGMA

The purpose of this paper is to introduce the problem of skepticism as the

RESPECTING THE EVIDENCE. Richard Feldman University of Rochester

2 FREE CHOICE The heretical thesis of Hobbes is the orthodox position today. So much is this the case that most of the contemporary literature

DISCUSSION PRACTICAL POLITICS AND PHILOSOPHICAL INQUIRY: A NOTE

Is there a distinction between a priori and a posteriori

TWO ACCOUNTS OF THE NORMATIVITY OF RATIONALITY

Transmission Failure Failure Final Version in Philosophical Studies (2005), 126: Nicholas Silins

Transcription:

Boghossian, Bellarmine, and Bayes John MacFarlane As Paul Boghossian sees it, postmodernist relativists and constructivists are paralyzed by a fear of knowledge. For example, they lack the courage to say, in the face of the Lakotas claim that their ancestors came from inside the earth, that it is a matter of known fact that their ancestors came across the Bering Strait. To avoid this, they accept the nonconfrontational view Boghossian calls (Equal Validity) There are many radically different, yet equally valid ways of knowing the world, with science being just one of them (2). 1 Boghossian suggests two sources for the continuing appeal of this view. The first is a postcolonial unwillingness to criticize cultures as inferior. Here, he notes, Equal Validity is a two-edged sword: for if the powerful can t criticize the oppressed, because the central epistemological categories are inexorably tied to particular perspectives, it also follows that the oppressed can t criticize the powerful (130). But in addition to its political appeal, Boghossian observes, Equal Validity has a philosophical appeal an appeal he aims to show is merely skin-deep. Boghossian concedes that if one thinks hard about fundamental epistemic disagreements in which two parties draw incompatible conclusions from the same evidence because they accept different justificatory frameworks Equal Validity can seem a natural and even inevitable conclusion. In such disputes, neither party can justify his own framework without presupposing its correctness. So, if there is a fact of the matter as to which framework is correct, it is hard to see how either party could know it. Faced with an unpalatable choice between skepticism, on the one hand, and the chauvinism of assuming that our own framework is correct just because it is our own, on the other, we might be led to the view that there are no absolute facts about justification, but only system-relative facts. In the central chapters of Fear of Knowledge, Boghossian fleshes out this line of thought with considerable sympathy, only to tear it down again. This is not Boghossian s only strategy against the relativist he 1 Except as noted, all page references are to Paul Boghossian, Fear of Knowledge: Against Relativism and Constructivism (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2006). 1

also calls in question the very intelligibility of the relativist s position but it is an effective and important one. In fleshing out the case for epistemic relativism, Boghossian focuses on a concrete example, ripped from the pages of history (and from Richard Rorty s discussion in Philosophy and the Mirror of Nature). The two disputing parties are Galileo, who has just revealed thousands of previously unseen stars, the phases of Venus, and the moons of Jupiter in his telescope, and Cardinal Bellarmine, who warns Galileo not to promote the Copernican theory. Boghossian repeats the apocryphal story that Cardinal Bellarmine refused to look through Galileo s telescope, saying that he had a far better source of evidence about the make-up of the heavens, namely the Holy Scripture itself (60). This claim is belied by Boghossian s own source. 2 But if Bellarmine did look through the telescope, the story is even better for Boghossian s purposes. For although Bellarmine and Galileo had access to exactly the same evidence, they drew different conclusions. Bellarmine put a great deal of evidential weight on certain passages from scripture, including Solomon s claim that the sun also riseth and the sun goeth down, and hasteneth to the place where he ariseth, and concluded that although the Copernican theory correctly predicted celestial movements, it should not be accepted as literal truth on the strength of the evidence Galileo had given. Galileo, by contrast, put a great deal of weight on the testimony of his senses (and his views about the operation of the telescope), dismissing the scriptural interpretations as non-evidential. About this case, Rorty asks: What determines that Scripture is not an excellent source of evidence for the way the heavens are set up? 3 Of course, the scientific standpoint we have inherited from Galileo recommends distinguishing sharply between properly scientific evidence and religious matters. But, Rorty says,...to proclaim our loyalty to these distinctions is not to say that there are objective and rational standards for adopting them. Galileo, so to speak, won the argument, and we all stand on the common ground of the grid of relevance and irrelevance which modern philosophy developed as a consequence of that victory. But what could show that the Bellarmine-Galileo 2 Giorgio de Santillana, The Crime of Galileo (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1955), 28. 3 Philosophy and the Mirror of Nature (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1981), 328 9. 2

issue differs in kind from the issue between, say, Kerensky and Lenin, or that between the Royal Academy (circa 1910) and Bloomsbury? 4 What makes Rorty s claim hard to resist, Boghossian suggests, is that the only justification we can provide for our own epistemic framework is a normcircular one. Galileo (like us) employs the following fundamental epistemic principles: (Observation) For any observational proposition p, if it visually seems to S that p and circumstantial conditions D obtain, then S is prima facie justified in believing p. (64) (Deduction) If S is justified in believing p and p fairly obviously entails q, then S is justified in believing q. (66) (Induction) If S has often enough observed that an event of type A has been followed by an event of type B, then S is justified in believing that all events of type A will be followed by events of type B. (67) Bellarmine, by contrast, employs (Revelation) For certain propositions p, including propositions about the heavens, believing p is prima facie justified if p is the revealed word of God as claimed by the Bible. (69) Suppose Galileo calls on Bellarmine to justify Relevalation. Bellarmine could not do so except by invoking Revelation itself: the Bible claims its own reliability as a guide to truth. Galileo would be right, it seems, to reject this blatantly circular justification as no justification at all. But can Galileo do any better in justifying his own fundamental principles? It is a Philosophy 101 commonplace that one cannot justify Deduction without deducing, or Observation without invoking the deliverances of the senses, or Induction without making inductive inferences. So (it seems natural to conclude) neither Galileo nor Bellarmine has any non-circular argument for the objective correctness of his own fundamental epistemic principles: If the point is to decide which of the two practices is better than the other, self-certification is not going to help. Each side will be able to provide a norm-circular justification of its own practice; neither side will be able to 4 Ibid., 331. 3

provide anything more. With what right, then, could either party claim to have a superior conception of rational or justified belief? We seem left with no choice but to say, as Wittgenstein does in his Philosophical Investigations: If I have exhausted the justifications I have reached bedrock, and my spade is turned. Then I am inclined to say: This is simply what I do. (79 80) If this is right, then it seems we can persist in thinking that there is an objective fact of the matter as to whose epistemic principles are correct only at the price of acknowledging that neither party is in a position (even on further reflection) to come to know this fact. 5 This flies in the face of the intuitive assumption (which Boghossian apparently endorses) that fundamental facts about justification, if there are any, should be knowable through a priori reflection (76). The alternative is to drop the assumption that there are absolute, objective facts about what counts as a justification, and take all justification judgements to be implicitly framework-relative. To take this second option is, in effect, to endorse Equal Validity. So where does this apparently plausible argument go wrong? Boghossian observes that if an argument like this is to support Equal Validity, it must start from a real confrontation between genuinely alternative epistemic systems. In the absence of a legitimate challenge, the fact that we cannot offer non-circular justifications of basic epistemic principles does not undermine our entitlement to believe them. We can be justified in accepting them by default. If we could not be, Boghossian points out, the path to skepticism would be short indeed. What must an alternative epistemic system look like in order to count as a legitimate challenge to our own? Boghossian argues that it must be coherent, in the sense of not giving incompatible verdicts about justification, and that it must have a sufficiently impressive track record in the actual world. (Science-fiction scenarios about technologically advanced aliens who reject modus ponens do not count.) Finally, it must be a genuine alternative to our own a system with different fundamental epistemic principles, not just different derived principles. In assessing the argument for Equal Validity, then, we must ask whether Bellarmine s epistemic system really constitutes a genuine alternative to our own 5 Boghossian assumes, at least for purposes of this book, that knowledge requires justification (15). 4

(Galileo s), and if so whether it is a coherent system. Boghossian argues that if Bellarmine s system is coherent, then it cannot be a genuine alternative to our own. For Bellarmine can hardly reject the fundamental principles Galileo employs Observation, Deduction, and Induction: Yes, the Cardinal consults his Bible to find out what to believe about the heavens, rather than using the telescope; but he doesn t divine what the Bible itself contains, but rather reads it using his eyes. Nor does he check it every hour to make sure that it still says the same, but rather relies on induction to predict that it will say the same tomorrow as it does today. And, finally, he uses deductive logic to deduce what it implies about the make-up of the heavens. (103) Given this, Boghossian argues, If Bellarmine s Vatican were to be a genuine example of a coherent fundamentally different epistemic system, he would have to hold that whereas ordinary epistemic principles apply to propositions about objects in his immediate vicinity, Revelation applies to propositions about the heavens. (104) But of course Bellarmine applies the other epistemic principles to objects in the heavens, too (using his eyes to see that constellations are visible, for example). 6 On pain of attributing to Bellarmine an incoherent epistemic system, then, we had better regard his system as differing from ours only in some derived sense, attributing to him the view that there is evidence, of a perfectly ordinary sort, that the Holy Scripture is the revealed word of the Creator of the Universe. (104) In other words: if Bellarmine accepts Observation, Deduction, and Induction, then he cannot coherently accept Revelation as a fundamental epistemic principle (one that cannot be justified on the basis of the others). So either Bellarmine s epistemic system is not a genuine alternative to ours or it is not coherent, and in neither case do we have reason to doubt that our own epistemic system is objectively correct. But why should we agree with Boghossian that an epistemic system containing Revelation as a fundamental principle alongside Observation, Deduction, and Induction can be coherent only if the verdicts of Revelation are confined 6 Boghossian might also have pointed out that Revelation is also supposed to justify beliefs about things on earth. 5

to a special domain (say, heavenly goings-on) about which the other three principles have nothing to say? Boghossian seems to think that if the principles comprising an epistemic system can have divergent verdicts about the same domain, the resulting epistemic system is incoherent. But if that were so, we could show that Induction is not a fundamental epistemic principle. After all, its verdicts depart from, and sometimes even conflict with, those of Observation and Deduction alone. The mistake Boghossian is making here is to suppose that the principles that make up an epistemic system operate in complete isolation from each other. Notice, first, how wide a gap there is between the principles and any definite verdicts about justification. Applying the principles requires making delicate judgement calls about what circumstances count as defeating conditions for perceptual judgements, what entailments are fairly obvious, how many inductive instances are enough to support the conclusion which might be sensitive to the other principles one accepts. One who accepts Revelation, for example, might require many more instances to confirm inductive generalizations that appear to contradict the Bible, and might recognize new conditions under which visual appearances are to be mistrusted. Second, and crucially, the principles yield only prima facie claims of justification. This is explicit in Boghossian s formulations of Observation and Revelation, and it is hard to see how the verdicts of Induction could be anything other than prima facie. (If my inductions contradict what I can see with my own eyes, must my eyes always defer to them?) Even Deduction, if applied stupidly, can take us from justified beliefs to non-justified ones. (My belief of any one ticket that it will not win the lottery may be very well justified on probabilistic grounds, but through simple deductions from many such beliefs, I can arrive at the completely unjustified belief that no ticket will win.) The unqualified justificatory verdicts of a system of such principles are the result of a balancing of competing prima facie verdicts, and will therefore depend on the precise mix of principles making up the system. An epistemic system is incoherent only if its unqualified verdicts about justification are incompatible; the fact that its constituent principles yield incompatible prima facie verdicts is not enough to make it incoherent. When Induction is in play, the prima facie deliverances of Observation are sometimes dismissed as illusory. Conversely, prima facie compelling inductive arguments may be dismissed in the face of strong observational evidence against their conclusions. We should expect similar negotiations in a system containing 6

Revelation. When Revelation is in play, the other principles may be applied differently, and a belief the other principles count as prima facie justified may not be justified all things considered. We have seen no good reason, then, to deny that an epistemic system containing Revelation, Observation, Deduction, and Induction as fundamental epistemic principles could be coherent. Boghossian has not shown that the only real question between Galileo and Bellarmine is whether there is evidence of a perfectly ordinary sort for the divine status of the Bible, and Rorty s diagnosis of the situation as a clash between two different grids of inquiry has not been refuted. 7 These reflections point to a more serious problem with the way Boghossian has set things up in particular, with his notion of a fundamental epistemic principle. Boghossian assumes that fundamental epistemic principles will be knowable a priori: Whenever we confidently judge that some belief is justified on the basis of a given piece of information, we are tacitly assuming that such facts [about justification] are not only knowable but that they are known. And in doing epistemology, we not only assume that they are knowable, we assume that they are knowable a priori. (76) 8 He also assumes that these principles (working together as a system) will give us definite verdicts about which beliefs are justified on the basis of what 7 Of course, even if we have here a case of real conflict between genuinely incompatible epistemic frameworks, we could still resist Equal Validity and plump for skepticism instead, claiming that there is an objective fact about which framework is correct one that we are not in a position to know. Boghossian tries briefly to persuade us that such skepticism is palatable if it is due to some contingent condition, like our recognition of a sufficiently impressive and coherent epistemic framework that competes with our own: While it is very plausible to claim that, if there are absolutely correct epistemic principles, they ought to be accessible in principle, it is much less plausible to claim that if there are such principles, we must know what they are here and now, in the actual world, (102). One might worry, however, that skepticism about fundamental epistemic principles would quickly ramify into universal skepticism. Even if being justified in believing that p does not require knowing the principles that make this belief justified, genuine doubts about what counts as a justification might lead one to suspend first-order belief. I lack the space to pursue this issue further here. 8 Though the assumption that fundamental epistemic principles must be known is later questioned see note 7, above their in-principle a priori knowability is not. 7

evidence. For he understands two epistemic systems to conflict just in case they give different such verdicts. But it is quite implausible that there are any systems of fundamental epistemic principles that meet both these conditions. Principles that give definite verdicts about justification are generally not knowable a priori, and principles that are knowable a priori are generally too schematic to yield definite verdicts. Consider again Boghossian s principle (Observation) For any observational proposition p, if it visually seems to S that p and circumstantial conditions D obtain, then S is prima facie justified in believing p. This is knowable a priori only if we can know a priori that visual perception is reliable when conditions D hold. But surely that is an empirical matter. (Anyone familiar with recent work on change-blindness knows how surprising empirical findings about perceptual unreliability can be.) Moreover, Observation gives us only prima facie verdicts about justification. To convert these into unqualified verdicts, we need to know how to balance them against the prima facie verdicts of other principles. Do we know a priori how to do that? The problems are especially clear in the case of (Induction) If S has often enough observed that an event of type A has been followed by an event of type B, then S is justified in believing that all events of type A will be followed by events of type B. Clearly, how many times are often enough to justify the inductive inference depends heavily on one s background beliefs, including empirical beliefs. Sometimes one or two instances will suffice, when one can be confident in the uniformity of the sample. On the other hand, no matter how many grue emeralds you show me, I ll refuse to accept the inference to all emeralds are grue. That the lines we must draw here cannot be drawn on the basis of reflection alone is brought out clearly by I. J. Good s demonstration that there are situations in which the observation of a black raven would disconfirm the hypothesis that all ravens are black. 9 Knowing how many is enough requires knowing something about the world; it is broadly empirical knowledge. 9 The White Shoe is a Red Herring, British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 17 (1967), 322. 8

I hope these examples are enough to show that epistemic principles capable of yielding definite verdicts about when particular beliefs are justified are not, in general, going to be knowable a priori. We can make them knowable a priori only by draining them of determinate content to the point where they could be shared by two parties who applied them in very different ways, yielding incompatible verdicts about justification. If this is right, then we have two options. One is to embrace a strong kind of externalism about justification, according to which the fundamental principles governing justification are not discoverable simply by a priori reflection. As I have mentioned, there are indications that Boghossian would not be happy with this option. At any rate, no one who is happy with it would be gripped for even a second by the argument for epistemic relativism that Boghossian presents as having some prima facie appeal. The other option is to accept a kind of relativism about justification, saying that whether someone is justified in believing p in light of evidence E depends crucially on their background beliefs or credences. This is, of course, exactly what subjective Bayesians say. Since Bellarmine presumably assigns a very high prior probability to the literal truth of the Bible, and to the correctness of a certain construal of its words, a Bayesian updating norm will require him to have stronger evidence than Galileo would need to be justified in giving up his belief in an earth-centered cosmos. And this is so whether his high credence in an interpretation of the Bible is the result of induction from historical evidence or an article of faith. In this way a Bayesian can accept a form of Equal Validity claim: Bellarmine is no less justified, given his starting points, than Galileo is given his. I am not sure whether this kind of view, which accepts only a very formal kind of objective epistemic norm, falls within Boghossian s target area in Fear of Knowledge. In a footnote (94 n. 5), he says that he is not concerned with views on which the only sorts of absolute epistemic truths there are, are ones which advert to the thinker s starting point, but only with a view that attempts to evade commitment to any absolute epistemic truths of any kind. But why write about the latter when the former seems equally capable of funding a version of the Equal Validity claim Boghossian is so concerned to reject? Isn t the former just as serious a threat to what he calls Objectivism about Justification, the view that Facts of the form information E justifies belief B are society-independent facts (22)? In defense of his choice of focus, Boghossian writes: 9

It is easy to see what might motivate someone to take seriously the idea that there are no absolute epistemic truths of any kind; it is much harder to see what would motivate the moderate view that, while there are some absolute epistemic truths, there are many fewer than we had been inclined to suppose, or that they make essential references to such parameters as a thinker s starting point. (94) To the contrary it is easy to motivate the moderate view. All one has to do is to write down some candidate epistemic principles, as Boghossian has done, and then reflect (as we have just done) on what would be required to fill in their escape clauses and adjudicate between the various prima facie claims to which they give rise. If you don t know where to start, start with Induction. 10