Similar documents

Utilitarianism: For and Against (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1973), pp Reprinted in Moral Luck (CUP, 1981).


Citation for the original published paper (version of record):

A Case against Subjectivism: A Reply to Sobel

Practical Rationality and Ethics. Basic Terms and Positions

Buck-Passers Negative Thesis

The Rightness Error: An Evaluation of Normative Ethics in the Absence of Moral Realism

INTUITION AND CONSCIOUS REASONING

Mark Schroeder s Hypotheticalism: Agent-neutrality, Moral Epistemology, and Methodology

DANCY ON ACTING FOR THE RIGHT REASON

Luck, Rationality, and Explanation: A Reply to Elga s Lucky to Be Rational. Joshua Schechter. Brown University

AN ACTUAL-SEQUENCE THEORY OF PROMOTION

The Oxford Handbook of Epistemology

The stated objective of Gloria Origgi s paper Epistemic Injustice and Epistemic Trust is:

Each copy of any part of a JSTOR transmission must contain the same copyright notice that appears on the screen or printed page of such transmission.

Direct Realism and the Brain-in-a-Vat Argument by Michael Huemer (2000)

Why there is no such thing as a motivating reason


Philosophical Review.

PLEASESURE, DESIRE AND OPPOSITENESS

A Rational Solution to the Problem of Moral Error Theory? Benjamin Scott Harrison


Ethics is subjective.

HUME AND HIS CRITICS: Reid and Kames

Huemer s Problem of Memory Knowledge

On the alleged perversity of the evidential view of testimony

what makes reasons sufficient?

Reason and Explanation: A Defense of Explanatory Coherentism. BY TED POSTON (Basingstoke,

GS SCORE ETHICS - A - Z. Notes

Four Arguments that the Cognitive Psychology of Religion Undermines the Justification of Religious Belief

Oxford Scholarship Online Abstracts and Keywords

TWO ACCOUNTS OF THE NORMATIVITY OF RATIONALITY

A DEFENSE OF REASONS-INTERNALISM. Ryan Stringer A THESIS

Right-Making, Reference, and Reduction

On the Origins and Normative Status of the Impartial Spectator

Philosophy of Religion 21: (1987).,, 9 Nijhoff Publishers, Dordrecht - Printed in the Nethenanas

CRUCIAL TOPICS IN THE DEBATE ABOUT THE EXISTENCE OF EXTERNAL REASONS

ON PROMOTING THE DEAD CERTAIN: A REPLY TO BEHRENDS, DIPAOLO AND SHARADIN

CONSCIOUSNESS, INTENTIONALITY AND CONCEPTS: REPLY TO NELKIN

Attraction, Description, and the Desire-Satisfaction Theory of Welfare

Scanlon on Double Effect

David O Connor. Hume on Religion H. O. Mounce Hume Studies Volume XXVIII, Number 2 (November, 2002)

The unity of the normative

Utilitas / Volume 25 / Issue 03 / September 2013, pp DOI: /S , Published online: 08 July 2013

Many Faces of Virtue. University of Toronto. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research

KNOWLEDGE ON AFFECTIVE TRUST. Arnon Keren

Aboutness and Justification

SCHROEDER ON THE WRONG KIND OF


MULTI-PEER DISAGREEMENT AND THE PREFACE PARADOX. Kenneth Boyce and Allan Hazlett

Moral Relativism and Conceptual Analysis. David J. Chalmers

WHY THERE REALLY ARE NO IRREDUCIBLY NORMATIVE PROPERTIES

IN DEFENCE OF CLOSURE

Seth Mayer. Comments on Christopher McCammon s Is Liberal Legitimacy Utopian?

REASON AND PRACTICAL-REGRET. Nate Wahrenberger, College of William and Mary

Instrumental reasoning* John Broome

2014 THE BIBLIOGRAPHIA ISSN: Online First: 21 October 2014

knowledge is belief for sufficient (objective and subjective) reason

Skepticism and Internalism

ALTERNATIVE SELF-DEFEAT ARGUMENTS: A REPLY TO MIZRAHI

THE ROLE OF COHERENCE OF EVIDENCE IN THE NON- DYNAMIC MODEL OF CONFIRMATION TOMOJI SHOGENJI

Williamson on Knowledge, by Patrick Greenough and Duncan Pritchard (eds). Oxford and New

On the Nature of Intellectual Vice. Brent Madison, United Arab Emirates University, Al-Ain, UAE

Harman s Moral Relativism

Moral Twin Earth: The Intuitive Argument. Terence Horgan and Mark Timmons have recently published a series of articles where they

8 Internal and external reasons

Introduction to Cognitivism; Motivational Externalism; Naturalist Cognitivism

Reply to Kit Fine. Theodore Sider July 19, 2013

Gary Ebbs, Carnap, Quine, and Putnam on Methods of Inquiry, Cambridge. University Press, 2017, 278pp., $99.99 (hbk), ISBN

THINKING ANIMALS AND EPISTEMOLOGY

Skepticism is True. Abraham Meidan

Huemer s Clarkeanism

Of Skepticism with Regard to the Senses. David Hume

Are Humans Always Selfish? OR Is Altruism Possible?

The Philosophical Review, Vol. 100, No. 3. (Jul., 1991), pp

Interest-Relativity and Testimony Jeremy Fantl, University of Calgary

Philosophy Epistemology Topic 5 The Justification of Induction 1. Hume s Skeptical Challenge to Induction

The Philosophical Review, Vol. 110, No. 3. (Jul., 2001), pp

Varieties of Apriority

the negative reason existential fallacy

PH 1000 Introduction to Philosophy, or PH 1001 Practical Reasoning

Abstract: According to perspectivism about moral obligation, our obligations are affected by

Explanatory Indispensability and Deliberative Indispensability: Against Enoch s Analogy Alex Worsnip University of North Carolina at Chapel Hill

Is Truth the Primary Epistemic Goal? Joseph Barnes

SCHAFFER S DEMON NATHAN BALLANTYNE AND IAN EVANS

Are Practical Reasons Like Theoretical Reasons?

A Hobbist Tory: Johnson on Hume Paul Russell Hume Studies Volume XVI, Number 1 (April, 1990)

DOES CONSEQUENTIALISM DEMAND TOO MUCH?

Naturalism and is Opponents

Are There Reasons to Be Rational?

King and Kitchener Packet 3 King and Kitchener: The Reflective Judgment Model

From the Routledge Encyclopedia of Philosophy

Reliabilism: Holistic or Simple?

Objective Normative Reasons (Draft)

Judith Jarvis Thomson s Normativity

Knowledge and its Limits, by Timothy Williamson. Oxford: Oxford University

What Lurks Beneath the Integrity Objection. Bernard Williams s alienation and integrity arguments against consequentialism have

Commentary on Professor Tweyman's 'Hume on Evil' Pheroze S. Wadia Hume Studies Volume XIII, Number 1 (April, 1987)

Philosophy 2: Introduction to Philosophy Section 4170 Online Course El Camino College Spring, 2015

Transcription:

Mark Schroeder. Slaves of the Passions. Melissa Barry Hume Studies Volume 36, Number 2 (2010), 225-228. Your use of the HUME STUDIES archive indicates your acceptance of HUME STUDIES Terms and Conditions of Use, available at http://www.humesociety.org/hs/about/terms.html. HUME STUDIES Terms and Conditions of Use provides, in part, that unless you have obtained prior permission, you may not download an entire issue of a journal or multiple copies of articles, and you may use content in the HUME STUDIES archive only for your personal, non-commercial use. Each copy of any part of a HUME STUDIES transmission must contain the same copyright notice that appears on the screen or printed page of such transmission. For more information on HUME STUDIES contact humestudies-info@humesociety.org http://www.humesociety.org/hs/

Hume Studies Volume 36, Number 2, 2010, pp. 225 228 Book Reviews Mark Schroeder. Slaves of the Passions. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2007. Pp. ix + 224. ISBN 978-0-19-929950-8, Cloth, $75.00. ISBN 978-0-19-957572-5, Paper, $35.00. In Slaves of the Passions, Mark Schroeder provides a systematic, rigorously argued defense of a Humean theory of reasons for action, taking pains to respond to influential objections to the view. While inspired by Hume, Schroeder makes it clear that he aims to develop a Humean theory, not necessarily one that Hume himself embraced, and for this reason little is said about Hume in the book. One respect in which Schroeder takes himself to be departing from Hume is in developing a normative account. On his reading, Hume held that only beliefs could stand in the reason relation (187, n11), whereas Schroeder, like many contemporary Humeans, holds that actions can as well. He sets out to develop a theory of this relation. Of special interest, I think, is the extent to which Schroeder is willing to reject what are often regarded as central commitments of a Humean position, as I highlight below. His discussion provides an extremely helpful framework for thinking through the Humean view. It should be of great interest to participants in the reasons debate and to anyone who is dissatisfied with Hume s denial that actions can be reasonable or unreasonable and who wonders how his insights might be developed. A familiar argument for the Humean theory starts with the claim that reasons must be able to motivate, adds that desire is necessary for motivation, and Volume 36, Number 2, 2010

226 Book Reviews concludes that having a reason requires having a desire. Schroeder instead takes the primary rationale for the theory to be that it explains an agent s reasons, and differences among agents reasons, more plausibly than its rivals. In many cases, he claims, we should explain an agent s reasons by appealing to elements of his psychology (e.g., Ronnie s reason to go to the party is explained by the facts that he likes to dance and that there will be dancing there). The Humean thought is that if there is to be a unified explanation of why people have the reasons they do, and if reasons are sometimes explained by appealing to psychological features of agents, then they must always be explained in this way (2). The Humean theory as such does not identify which psychological feature is involved (e.g., desire, pleasure, valuing) or explain exactly how it gives rise to a reason, however. This is important, Schroeder argues, for influential recent criticisms of the theory rest upon assumptions about how the Humean explanation must work assumptions that a Humean can reject (5). It s often supposed, for example, that the psychological state involved is desire, that this desire must figure in the content of a reason, and that the weight of a reason is a function of the strength of desire together with how well an action promotes it. These assumptions lead to familiar objections to the Humean view, including the following: (1) it makes practical reasoning too self-regarding, focused on the agent s desires; (2) it gives the wrong answer to the question of why considerations are reason-giving, i.e., because they promote the agent s desires; (3) it neglects to defend its foundational claim that desires figure in the explanation of every reason; (4) it generates too many reasons, counting things as reason-giving that clearly are not; and (5) it generates too few reasons, failing, in particular, to yield agent-neutral moral reasons. A substantial part of Schroeder s defense of the Humean theory (chapters 2 7) consists in responding to these objections. The explanatory framework of his preferred version, which he calls Hypotheticalism, emerges through these arguments. In chapter 2, he argues that in a Humean view desire need only appear in the background conditions of a reason and not in its content, allowing the theory to escape objections (1) and (2). In chapters 3 and 4, he argues that the Humean theory can defend its foundational claim by offering the right kind of reductive analysis of what a reason is. In chapters 5 7, he argues that in a Humean view the weight of a reason needn t be a function of the strength of desire, and uses this to respond to objections (4) and (5). The remaining chapters fill in elements of Hypotheticalism. In chapter 8, Schroeder explains why he thinks desire, analyzed in phenomenologicalcum-dispositional terms, is the psychological state that underpins reasons, arguing that it can motivate rational action in the right way. In chapter 9, he explores the implications of the account for normative epistemology and motivation; in chapter 10, he addresses the concern that the Humean theory bars the rational assessment of desires; and in chapter 11, he examines the deep motivations for the Humean view. Hume Studies

Book Reviews 227 Each chapter of this excellent book rewards careful attention. In the limited space available here I shall focus on difficulties with two arguments Schroeder develops to defend Hypotheticalism against objections. In chapter 2, Schroeder distinguishes between a reason s background conditions, which explain why it is a reason, and its content, which states what the reason is, arguing that the Humean view should claim that desires figure only in the background conditions. This, he argues, allows the Humean to accept the Deliberative Constraint, which requires that a properly deliberating agent think directly in terms of her reasons, without having to concede that the agent s reasoning must focus on her desires and so be overly self-regarding (23). Likewise, it enables the Humean to avoid giving a counterintuitive answer to the why? question, for if desires are not part of the content of reasons, they need not figure in the answer (39). I am skeptical that this distinction between background conditions and content can satisfy the concerns behind these objections, however. Schroeder does not say why he thinks the Deliberative Constraint should be respected, but one reason to think so is that it seems, intuitively, that to act rationally an agent needs to understand the justification for her actions, including both the surface reason ( there will be dancing at the party ) and the explanation of why this is a reason ( I like to dance ). Background conditions that play an essential role in fixing normative content should be regarded as part of the justification and need to be available to the deliberating agent if she is to meet the Deliberative Constraint. Similarly, relegating desires to the background does not meaningfully change their role in answering the why? question since they remain an essential part of the justification. The second argument I want to examine appears in chapters 5 7. Schroeder denies that in a Humean account the weight of a reason must be a function of the strength of desire together with how well an action promotes desire. An agent has a reason to do an action, he argues, if the action promotes her desires to some degree (99). The reason s weight, however, and so ultimately what an agent ought to do, is determined by whether the right kind of reasons favor giving it weight (where the latter, in turn, are determined by the nature of the relevant activity) (135). This account of weight provides a reply to the too many reasons objection, Schroeder argues, for while Hypotheticalism makes reasons easy to come by, it can explain why many of these reasons are not weighty and so are irrelevant to deliberation (96). The account of weight also allows a reply to the too few reasons worry by suggesting a way to justify agent-neutral moral reasons. If for any agent with desires, moral action promotes at least some of these desires in some way, then every agent has at least some reason to act morally (115). Such reasons are weighty, even equally weighty for all agents, if the right kind of reasons for determining weight require this. The right kind of reasons here, Schroeder argues, are those that any Volume 36, Number 2, 2010

228 Book Reviews agent has simply in virtue of placing weight on reasons, i.e., deciding what to do, which every agent is engaged in. So the right kind of reasons are just the class of agent-neutral reasons (142). I have doubts about the details of each reply, but even if we grant their success, a larger worry remains about this account of weight. Schroeder claims that the primary rationale for the Humean theory is that its appeal to psychological features of agents enables it to explain better than its rivals both why particular agents have the reasons that they do and why agents reasons differ. However, in disregarding strength of desire when assessing the weight of both agent-neutral reasons of morality and agent-relative personal reasons for individual agents and giving normative priority to the verdict of the right kind of reasons, Schroeder drives a substantial wedge between reasons and the psychologies of individual agents. In his central examples, Ryan s reason to help Katie is judged weighty despite the weakness of Ryan s desire, while Aunt Margaret s reason to build a spaceship in the backyard is not, despite the strength of her desire (142 44). This strongly suggests that Hypotheticalism is not especially well positioned to explain why particular agents have the reasons they do, or why agents reasons differ. Furthermore, giving this kind of normative priority to the right kind of reasons seems unjustified in a Humean framework. Schroeder characterizes the right kind of reasons for an activity as those that the people involved in that activity have, because they are engaged in that activity (135). This suggests that an analysis of the nature of activities can identify standards that anyone engaging in them has reason to follow. However, even if an agent is already engaged in an activity, she may have her own view about how to carry it out; unless she aims to perform the activity exactly as it is characterized in the analysis, there seems to be nothing in a Humean account to give the right reasons normative force for her. Despite these objections, I think there is a great deal to be learned from this very fine book. Schroeder s insightful examination of how explanations of normative reasons work nicely clarifies the dispute between Humeans and their critics, while his able defense of the Humean view shows that it has greater resources than critics have recognized. Indeed, as developed, it may even be a view that Hume would have found attractive. MELISSA BARRY Department of Philosophy Williams College 24 Hopkins Hall Drive Williamstown, MA 01267, USA mbarry@williams.edu Hume Studies