Article: Heath, M. (1989) Dionysius of Halicarnassus On Imitation. Hermes, 117. pp ISSN

Similar documents
Article: Heath, M. (1990) Thucydides' political judgement. Liverpool Classical Monthly, 15. pp ISSN

Article: Steward, H (2013) Responses. Inquiry: an interdisciplinary journal of philosophy, 56 (6) ISSN X

2016 Philosophy. Higher. Finalised Marking Instructions

This document consists of 10 printed pages.

Thomas Hobbes, Leviathan, ed. by Noel Malcolm, Clarendon Edition of the Works of Thomas Hobbes, 3 vols., Oxford: Clarendon Press, 2012

Dave Elder-Vass Of Babies and Bathwater. A Review of Tuukka Kaidesoja Naturalizing Critical Realist Social Ontology

Academic History of Suzie Ling

HAVE WE REASON TO DO AS RATIONALITY REQUIRES? A COMMENT ON RAZ

DEFEASIBLE A PRIORI JUSTIFICATION: A REPLY TO THUROW


Moral Argument. Jonathan Bennett. from: Mind 69 (1960), pp

Phenomenal Consciousness and Intentionality<1>

Self-Knowledge for Humans. By QUASSIM CASSAM. (Oxford: OUP, Pp. xiii +

WHY IS GOD GOOD? EUTYPHRO, TIMAEUS AND THE DIVINE COMMAND THEORY

Investigating Worldviews with Protégé Bro Wormslev Jakobsen, Thomas; Jakobsen, David; Øhrstrøm, Peter

COMPARING CONTEXTUALISM AND INVARIANTISM ON THE CORRECTNESS OF CONTEXTUALIST INTUITIONS. Jessica BROWN University of Bristol

INTUITION AND CONSCIOUS REASONING

How Subjective Fact Ties Language to Reality

HANDBOOK (New or substantially modified material appears in boxes.)

From: Michael Huemer, Ethical Intuitionism (2005)

Philosophy Pathways Issue nd October

Constructing A Biblical Message

In defence of the Simplicity Argument E. J. Lowe a a

Pihlström, Sami Johannes.

BOOK REVIEW. Thomas R. Schreiner, Interpreting the Pauline Epistles (Grand Rapids: Baker Academic, 2nd edn, 2011). xv pp. Pbk. US$13.78.

REVIEW THE MORALS OF HISTORIOGRAPHY

Eubulus fr. 123 Kassel-Austin = fr. 126 Hunter is incompletely preserved in the epitome of

COPYRIGHT NOTICE Bareau/The Buddhist Schools of the Small Vehicle

Anthony P. Andres. The Place of Conversion in Aristotelian Logic. Anthony P. Andres

An Alternate Possibility for the Compatibility of Divine. Foreknowledge and Free Will. Alex Cavender. Ringstad Paper Junior/Senior Division

ON QUINE, ANALYTICITY, AND MEANING Wylie Breckenridge

Citation for the original published paper (version of record):

Prentice Hall United States History Survey Edition 2013

HANDBOOK. IV. Argument Construction Determine the Ultimate Conclusion Construct the Chain of Reasoning Communicate the Argument 13

MULTI-PEER DISAGREEMENT AND THE PREFACE PARADOX. Kenneth Boyce and Allan Hazlett

Moral requirements are still not rational requirements

Buzzard writes about Titus 2:13, also supposedly an example of the Granville Sharp rule:

National Quali cations

This is a repository copy of Making Modal Distinctions: Kant on the possible, the actual, and the intuitive intellect..

Bowring, B. Review: Malcolm D. Evans Manual on the Wearing of Religious Symbols in Public Areas."

Is there a good epistemological argument against platonism? DAVID LIGGINS

Three short notes on RIB 955 = CLE 1597

Note: This is the penultimate draft of an article the final and definitive version of which is

38 SEVENTEENTH-CENTURY NEWS

Prentice Hall U.S. History Modern America 2013

How Not to Defend Metaphysical Realism (Southwestern Philosophical Review, Vol , 19-27)

GCE Religious Studies Unit A (RSS01) Religion and Ethics 1 June 2009 Examination Candidate Exemplar Work: Candidate B

HANDBOOK (New or substantially modified material appears in boxes.)

Of Cause and Effect David Hume

5 A Modal Version of the

CONSCIOUSNESS, INTENTIONALITY AND CONCEPTS: REPLY TO NELKIN

2. Refutations can be stronger or weaker.

Lawrence Brian Lombard a a Wayne State University. To link to this article:

The Mawer Report on Sheffield. Address at the 2017 National Assembly of Forward in Faith. by the Revd Paul Benfield SSC

A. Reading Read the text carefully.

TWO VERSIONS OF HUME S LAW

The Problem of Major Premise in Buddhist Logic

The Development of Laws of Formal Logic of Aristotle

REVIEW DISCUSSION. [Note: Tables of Contents appear at the end of the review]

DISCUSSION NOTES A RESOLUTION OF A PARADOX OF PROMISING WALTER SINNOTT-ARMSTRONG

Introduction to Technical Communications 21W.732 Section 2 Ethics in Science and Technology Formal Paper #2


2.3. Failed proofs and counterexamples

acting on principle onora o neill has written extensively on ethics and political philosophy

Magic, semantics, and Putnam s vat brains

Yuval Dolev, Time and Realism, MIT Press, 2007

II RESEMBLANCE NOMINALISM, CONJUNCTIONS

Religious Studies Paper 9 An Introduction to Philosophy of Religion

Portfolio Project. Phil 251A Logic Fall Due: Friday, December 7

Policy on Religious Education

NICHOLAS J.J. SMITH. Let s begin with the storage hypothesis, which is introduced as follows: 1

Universal Features: Doubts, Questions, Residual Problems DM VI 7

Remarks on a Foundationalist Theory of Truth. Anil Gupta University of Pittsburgh

INTERPRETATION AND FIRST-PERSON AUTHORITY: DAVIDSON ON SELF-KNOWLEDGE. David Beisecker University of Nevada, Las Vegas

HSC EXAMINATION REPORT. Studies of Religion

Kears, M. (2011) Review: Susan Lape, Race and Citizen Identity in the Classical Athenian Democracy. Cambridge University Press, 2010.

Target 1. Ensure proper focus of your investigations

DISCUSSION PRACTICAL POLITICS AND PHILOSOPHICAL INQUIRY: A NOTE

Positivism A Model Of For System Of Rules

2017 Philosophy. Higher. Finalised Marking Instructions

Writing Essays at Oxford

A R G U M E N T S I N A C T I O N

Instrumental reasoning* John Broome

THE FORM OF REDUCTIO AD ABSURDUM J. M. LEE. A recent discussion of this topic by Donald Scherer in [6], pp , begins thus:

The Quality of Mercy is Not Strained: Justice and Mercy in Proslogion 9-11

* I am indebted to Jay Atlas and Robert Schwartz for their helpful criticisms

IN DEFENCE OF CLOSURE

Wittgenstein and Moore s Paradox

Descartes: A Guide for the Perplexed

Reductio ad Absurdum, Modulation, and Logical Forms. Miguel López-Astorga 1

2004 by Dr. William D. Ramey InTheBeginning.org

CRITICAL NOTES. z "The Beginnings of Gospel Story." 2 The relative dates of Mark and Q will of course be determined in the discussion

CONCEPT FORMATION IN ETHICAL THEORIES: DEALING WITH POLAR PREDICATES

1/10. The Fourth Paralogism and the Refutation of Idealism

Nature and its Classification

PHI 1500: Major Issues in Philosophy

This is a repository copy of Does = 5? : In Defense of a Near Absurdity.

Israel Kirzner is a name familiar to all readers of the Review of

Chapter 18 David Hume: Theory of Knowledge

Phoebus, Mia. Mia Phoebus collection of Tennessee Williams papers 1940,

Transcription:

This is a repository copy of Dionysius of Halicarnassus On Imitation. White Rose Research Online URL for this paper: http://eprints.whiterose.ac.uk/3586/ Article: Heath, M. (1989) Dionysius of Halicarnassus On Imitation. Hermes, 117. pp. 370-373. ISSN 0018-0777 Reuse Unless indicated otherwise, fulltext items are protected by copyright with all rights reserved. The copyright exception in section 29 of the Copyright, Designs and Patents Act 1988 allows the making of a single copy solely for the purpose of non-commercial research or private study within the limits of fair dealing. The publisher or other rights-holder may allow further reproduction and re-use of this version - refer to the White Rose Research Online record for this item. Where records identify the publisher as the copyright holder, users can verify any specific terms of use on the publisher s website. Takedown If you consider content in White Rose Research Online to be in breach of UK law, please notify us by emailing eprints@whiterose.ac.uk including the URL of the record and the reason for the withdrawal request. eprints@whiterose.ac.uk https://eprints.whiterose.ac.uk/

Hermes 117 (1989), 370-3 Franz Steiner Verlag Wiesbaden GmbH Dionysius of Halicarnassus On Imitation MALCOLM HEATH (UNIVERSITY OF LEEDS) ABSTRACT: This paper defends Usener s theory that the extract from Dionysius On Imitation in the Letter to Pompeius is from an unfinished draft of the text which lies behind the epitome of On Imitation. The survey of historians in Dionysius Letter to Gnaeus Pompeius purports to be a transcription of part of the second book of his treatise On Imitation. This treatise has otherwise been preserved only in a fragmentary epitome; but there are disrepancies between the two sources, especially in their handling of the pragmatikõj tòpoj, which suggest that the transcription in the Letter was not in fact made from the same original as the epitome. In 1889 Usener suggested that the Letter reproduced a draft, the epitome the published version of the treatise. 1 More recently K.S. Sacks has argued that the Letter does not attempt to reproduce but substantially reworks Imitation, and that this reworking reflects significant changes in Dionysius thinking on historiography. 2 I shall argue that Usener was right. The first difference between the two sources is the most dramatic. The relevant section of the Letter begins with a comparison between Herodotus and Thucydides with respect to the pragmatikõj tòpoj that fills just over six pages in the Teubner edition of Usener and Radermacher (II 232.18-239.2); this corresponds to a single sentence in the epitome: As for the historians, Herodotus has executed the pragmatikõn edoj better (II 207.5-6). As Sacks sees (68), there are two possibilities; either the epitomator has cut out a large section of his original, or Dionysius did not include this comparison in the original from which the epitome was made. Since the comparison is found in the Letter, and Dionysius claims that the Letter reproduces Imitation (232.13-17), it is natural to infer that the epitomator was responsible for the omission. 3 Sacks comments (68): The lone sentence on the pragmatikon eidos comes directly after the passage in the comic poets, where pragmatikon there also receives mere mention and the lektikos topos greater development ; but we cannot possibly determine the relationship of the epitome to its original by comparing one part of the epitome with another in this way. Sacks offers no compelling argument against the natural inference. 1 Dionysii Halicarnassensis de imitatione librorum reliquiae ab H. Usenero collectae (Bonn 1889), 6: Mutuam sibi opem et epistula et epitoma ferunt. quod si quando desunt in epistula quae librariorum neglegentia omitti minus est probabile, hoc tenendum erit, in epistula illud caput translatum esse ante quam totum opus perpolitum a scriptore emitteretur, epitomam non ex epistula sed ex opere perfecto excerptam. [Additional note (December 2007): I would now wish to modify my conclusions on this question in the light of the important discussion in Gavin Weaire, The relationship between Dionysius of Halicarnassus De imitatione and Epistula ad Pompeium, Classical Philology 97 (2002), 351-9.] 2 K.S. Sacks, Historiography in the rhetorical works of Dionysius of Halicarnassus, Athenaeum 60 (1983), 65-87. 3 An earlier section of the Letter is claimed to be transcribed from Dionysius work on Attic orators (226.22-227.1); comparison with Demosthenes shows that this is true: there are only slight verbal differences. 1

There are, in fact, a number of clear indications that the epitomator has omitted material from his original here. First, the epitome says that Herodotus handles the pragmatikõj tòpoj better. The comparative suggests a comparison, and in the ensuing discussion of the lektikõj tòpoj we find that a súgkrisij of Herodotus and Thucydides is indeed being conducted. But this is never formally inrtoduced; Thucydides is not even named in the sentence on the pragmatikõj tòpoj. So something has been left out. Secondly, the pragmatikõj tòpoj is treated in greater detail when the epitome reaches the minor historians; but it would have been odd of Dionysius in Imitation to pass over this topic when discussing the two major historians but to develop it for the minor historians. Furthermore, the treatment of this topic in the minor historians makes frequent reference to the major historians. In the discussion of Philistus the epitome refers to Thucydides treatment of the pragmatikõj tòpoj to the incompleteness of his ØpÒqesij (208.17-19) and to his poor arrangement (208.19-209.1); this surely implies an original Imitation in which these points had already been established in a discussion of Thucydides. A similar conclusion is implied by the section on Xenophon in the epitome; here (208.3-5) the pragmatikõj tòpoj in Herodotus is recapitulated in greater detail than the epitome gives when it is concerned with Herodotus himself. These anomalies are easier to understand in notes taken for private use than in a formal treatise prepared for publication. External evidence supports the conclusion to which these pointers direct us. At the beginning of his Thucydides Dionysius says that in Imitation he indicated t naj kastoj aùtîn (sc., the historians) e sfšrei pragmatik j te kaˆ lektik j ret j. This claim is not true of the epitome, in which the pragmatika reta of the two most important historians are neglected; so the epitome must have omitted some part of Imitation. Admittedly Dionysius says that his discussion in Imitation was brief ( n Ñl goij); and a few lines later he says specifically of his treatment of Thucydides that it was concise and summary (suntòmj te kaˆ kefalaièdei grafí, cf. kefalaiwdîj in the epitome, 211.8). But even this is untrue of the epitome, although it is true of the Letter, which by comparison with Thucydides is concise and summary. The conclusion seems inescapable, therefore, that the sentence on the pragmatikõn edoj in the epitome has replaced a more extensive discussion in the original Imitation, and that the original discussion was, like that in the Letter a súgkrisij. It is reasonable to infer, then, that the original discussion and that in the Letter were one and the same. Some further points arise in the discussion of the minor historians. Sacks says (68) that the Letter uses the standard five headings of the pragmatikõj tòpoj for Xenophon and Philistus, while Imitation (he should, of course, have said the epitome) only has three. These three are ØpÒqesij, o konom a and Ãqoj. Sacks is in doubt as to how to take o konom a, but he ought not to be. The Letter refers to ØpÒqesij, o konom a and Ãqoj, and subdivides o konom a into three subheadings (begining/ending, division and variety) to give five (241.15-19); the epitome has simply omitted the subdivision of o konom a, a condensation plausibly attributable to the epitomator. 2

More interesting are the discrepancies which Sacks notes in the discussion of Philistus; these are the evidence on which he bases his claim that Dionysius has changed his mind. First, the epitome criticises Philistus for leaving his ØpÒqesij incomplete, like Thucydides; in the Letter to Pompeius, however, it is when Dionysius discusses Xenophon s subjects that he notes that the subject of Thucydides work is incomplete...; more importantly, Dionysius does so in a manner that implies no criticism (69). Secondly, the epitome criticises Philistus servile Ãqoj but admires Thucydides freedom; the Letter criticises Philistus in similar terms, though omitting the comparison with Thucydides, but elsewhere it is critical of Thucydides Ãqoj. These discrepancies are real, but neither affords evidence that Dionysius has changed his mind. First, an adverse judgement of Thucydides incompleteness is to be found in the Letter, in the súgkrisij of the major historians (236.1-5). Secondly, criticism of Thucydides anti-athenian bias, such as we find in the Letter, is wholly consistent with praise of his freedom, such as we find in the epitome; both are to be found in Thucydides (cc. 8, 41; cf. Sacks 69 n.18). It is quite possible that the adverse comment found in the Letter is absent from the epitome simply because the whole súgkrisij has been omitted. In neither case, therefore, is there any reason to conclude that Dionysius assessment of Thucydides has been revised. There is an important point here, even so. The omission of material from the Letter in the epitome is readily explained as the work of the epitomator; but the presence of additional material in the epitome is not. 4 So the references to Thucydides incompleteness and to Thucydides Ãqoj in the epitome s account of Philistus do point to a difference between its original and that of the Letter, as Usener saw. 5 We shall return to this point. Sacks also points out (71) that the praise of Theopompus commitment to the profession of history in the Letter is missing in the epitome, and this he thinks certainly new ; but without the obviously circular assumption that the epitome accurately reflects the contents of the original Imitation his certainty is unwarranted. The Letter is also more expansive on Theopompus parrhs a; Sacks comments: Dionysius discussion here is clearly a revision of that found in Mimesis, for in the Letter the term parresia not used, nor does Dionysius discuss Theopompus talent for divining the motives of actions and speeches, but just those of actions. This has no force. The fact that the word parrhs a does not occur in the Letter is irrelevant, since it is a reasonable summary of Dionysius defence of Theopompus critical stance towards historical characters, such as might easily have occurred to the epitomator. The addition of the words kaˆ lecqšntwn does not obviously go beyond the range of the epitomator s rephrasing, but it may be a further instance of additional material in the epitome. We may now return to the question of the epitome s additional material. We have seen that the epitome s account of Philistus contains such additions; it is also 4 It is possible in principle that the epitomator made the additions himself; but to cut down the súgkrisij so radically implies a lack of interest in the pragmatikõj tòpoj, which makes additions elsewhere unlikely. 5 See n.1 above. It is possible that the preceding discussion of Xenophon s faults with respect to tõ pršpon would have been relevant here; the lacuna at 242.10 makes this uncertain, but the remains of the Letter at this point are not easily reconciled with the epitome. 3

differently ordered. In the Letter Dionysius says: Philistus is like Thucydides in his choice of ØpÒqesij, his organisation and his lack of variety; and his Ãqoj is bad. The epitome: Philistus is like Thucydides, not in Ãqoj (he is servile, Thucydides is not), but in incompletness and bad organisation. No inferences can safely be drawn from the absence of material in the epitome that is found in the Letter (the choice of ØpÒqesij and the lack of variety) since it is possible that this is the result of epitomisation; but the additional material and the different order are significant. It is, I suggest, the order which points us to the correct solution. The order in which the points are made in the Letter is standard, and it is possible to misread the last point as a further similarity to Thucydides. The order in the epitome is unexpected, and the unwanted implication concerning Thucydides Ãqoj is explicitly removed. This does not suggest that the Letter is the more highly developed version of the material, as Sacks contends; rather, it supports Usener s conjecture that the Letter is a version of the epitome s source which had not received its final polish. In the Letter Dionysius says that the third book of Imitation is incomplete (232.12-13); it is a reasonable inference that Imitation was still being written when the extract from it was transcribed for Pompeius, 6 and in that case the supposition that the epitome reflects a revision for publication of the version of Imitation transcribed in the Letter is perfectly plausible. 6 But this is not of course certain: S.F. Bonner, The Literary Treatises of Dionysius of Halicarnassus (Cambridge 1939), 36-7 points out that the first two books may have been issued separately, and that there is no evidence to confirm that that the third book was ever completed. 4